To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
In the history of human inquiry, philosophy has the place of the central sun, seminal and tumultuous: from time to time it throws off some portion of itself to take station as a science, a planet, cool and well regulated, progressing steadily towards a distant final state … Is it not possible that the next century may see the birth, through the joint labours of philosophers, grammarians, and numerous other students of language, of a true and comprehensive science of language? Then we shall have rid ourselves of one more part of philosophy (there will still be plenty left) in the only way we ever get rid of philosophy, by kicking it upstairs.
(Austin, 1956: 131–2)
Introduction
In these conclusions we shall try to tie together some of the loose strands of thought that have run through this book, by considering the relation between pragmatics and other disciplines. One discipline will stand noticeably absent: philosophy, the ‘prodigal provider’, cannot easily re-absorb the empirical studies that it has spawned (but cf. Atlas, 1979). The general tenor of this book has been the description of how, from original, mostly philosophical concepts, a series of empirical modes of investigation have developed, which jointly form the climate of the Anglo-American tradition in pragmatics. As the quotation indicates, Austin foresaw, and indeed hoped for, just this development of a field that he, perhaps more than any other single individual, did most to promote.
In the previous Chapter we discussed conversational implicature as a special kind of pragmatic inference. Such inferences cannot be thought of as semantic (i.e. as pertaining to the meanings of words, phrases and sentences) because they are based squarely on certain contextual assumptions concerning the co-operativeness of participants in a conversation, rather than being built into the linguistic structure of the sentences that give rise to them. We turn in this Chapter to another kind of pragmatic inference, namely presupposition, that does seem at least to be based more closely on the actual linguistic structure of sentences; we shall conclude, however, that such inferences cannot be thought of as semantic in the narrow sense, because they are too sensitive to contextual factors in ways that this Chapter will be centrally concerned with.
The reader should be warned of two things at the outset. The first is that there is more literature on presupposition than on almost any other topic in pragmatics (excepting perhaps speech acts), and while much of this is of a technical and complex kind, a great deal is also obsolete and sterile. The volume of work is in part accounted for by a long tradition of philosophical interest which, because it is much referred to in the linguistic literature, will be briefly reviewed in 4.1.
Of all the issues in the general theory of language usage, speech act theory has probably aroused the widest interest. Psychologists, for example, have suggested that the acquisition of the concepts underlying speech acts may be a prerequisite for the acquisition of language in general (see e.g. Bruner, 1975; Bates, 1976), literary critics have looked to speech act theory for an illumination of textual subtleties or for an understanding of the nature of literary genres (see e.g. Ohmann, 1971; Levin, 1976), anthropologists have hoped to find in the theory some account of the nature of magical spells and ritual in general (see e.g. Tambiah, 1968), philosophers have seen potential applications to, amongst other things, the status of ethical statements (see e.g. Searle, 1969: Chapter 8), while linguists have seen the notions of speech act theory as variously applicable to problems in syntax (see e.g. Sadock, 1974), semantics (see e.g. Fillmore, 1971a), second language learning (see e.g. Jakobovitz & Gordon, 1974), and elsewhere. Meanwhile in linguistic pragmatics, speech acts remain, along with presupposition and implicature in particular, one of the central phenomena that any general pragmatic theory must account for.
Given this widespread interest, there is an enormous literature on the subject, and in this Chapter we cannot review all the work within linguistics, let alone the large and technical literature within philosophy, from which (like all the other concepts we have so far reviewed) the basic theories come.
The purpose of this Chapter is to provide some indication of the scope of linguistic pragmatics. First, the historical origin of the term pragmatics will be briefly summarized, in order to indicate some usages of the term that are divergent from the usage in this book. Secondly, we will review some definitions of the field, which, while being less than fully satisfactory, will at least serve to indicate the rough scope of linguistic pragmatics. Thirdly, some reasons for the current interest in the field will be explained, while a final section illustrates some basic kinds of pragmatic phenomena. In passing, some analytical notions that are useful background will be introduced.
The origin and historical vagaries of the term pragmatics
The modern usage of the term pragmatics is attributable to the philosopher Charles Morris (1938), who was concerned to outline (after Locke and Peirce) the general shape of a science of signs, or semiotics (or semiotic as Morris preferred). Within semiotics, Morris distinguished three distinct branches of inquiry: syntactics (or syntax), being the study of “the formal relation of signs to one another”, semantics, the study of “the relations of signs to the objects to which the signs are applicable” (their designata), and pragmatics, the study of “the relation of signs to interpreters” (1938: 6).
To squeeze all that goes under the rubric of pragmatics within the confines of a linguistics textbook would be neither possible nor desirable. Consequently this book is quite conservative in scope and approach, and considers the main topics in a particular tradition of work. This is the largely Anglo-American linguistic and philosophical tradition that builds directly, for the most part, on philosophical approaches to language of both the logical and ‘ordinary language’ variety (an exception is the set of topics treated in Chapter 6, which has a sociological origin). In contrast, the continental tradition is altogether broader, and would include much that also goes under the rubric of sociolinguistics. But even within this much narrower field, this book is in some ways restricted, since its main aim is to provide an introduction and background to those topics that, perhaps largely for historical reasons, are central to the Anglo-American tradition of work in pragmatics. The would-be pragmaticist must understand these issues in depth, if he or she is to understand the background to a great deal of current research in both linguistics and philosophy.
One major way in which this book is perhaps innovative is the inclusion in Chapter 6 of a brief review of work in conversation analysis. Apart from its demonstrable importance for theories of language usage, work in conversation analysis contributes directly to many of the same issues that have preoccupied philosophers of language, and thence linguists, while employing a startlingly different methodology.
Despite the battle of Mantineia in 418 (see 205), the Spartans and the Athenians remained formally at peace with each other and the Spartans made no attempt to come to the help of Melos (see 206). But the Sicilian expedition clearly induced a majority at Sparta to believe that Athens must and could be attacked and defeated; and this time, there was none of the feeling which had dogged Sparta in the Archidamian War, that she had been guilty of starting the war and therefore enjoyed no success. The exile Alkibiades found a ready hearing and the Spartans moved to fortify Dekeleia in the heart of Attika.
But even after the defeat of the Sicilian expedition, Athens was far from being down; and the Spartans were even now only able to make headway by persuading Persia to provide them with the money for a fleet. The long-term effect of the Spartan offensive was to make Persia once more a major factor in Greek affairs.
See in general Lewis, Sparta and Persia.
228. Alkibiades in Sparta
Choosing exile rather than trial (see 214), Alkibiades arrived in Sparta in the winter of 415/14; he there set out to disarm opposition generated by his earlier activities inimical to Spartan interests and his democratic leanings, and then proceeded to make himself indispensable by terrifying the Spartans with an account of Athenian plans to conquer Sicily, Italy and Carthage and deploy the forces so acquired against Sparta.
The study of the history of ancient Greece is both exciting and infuriating – exciting because of the inherent interest of the way in which Greek society organised itself, and because the members of that society still seem able through their writings to communicate as individuals with us who are the inheritors of much which they created; infuriating because in the course of transmission over two and half millennia much information has disappeared, and because the information which remains often shatters on inspection the first impression of similarity between the Greeks and ourselves.
We hope that the texts and other sources presented here will provide a coherent and comprehensible picture of ancient Greece; certain things, however, need some comment.
The characteristic institution of the Greek world was the polis, a small, independent community consisting of an urban nucleus, or astu, and territory, or chōra. Although a few Greeks chose to spend much or all of their lives away from the place of their birth, for most Greeks existence outside their polis was unthinkable. An exile was prepared to go to almost any lengths to secure his return and if a polis was destroyed by one great power and restored by another, as sometimes happened, the survivors of the destruction returned to re-people their home. If a colony (apoikia) was destroyed, its men were likely to return to the polis which had sent them out.
The economic foundations of Athens, as of all poleis, lay in land, the land of Attika. The Athenians claimed to be ‘sprung from the soil’ (autochthonous), and whatever alternative sources of community supply and of personal affluence might arise, cultivating the chōra of Attika preserved the polis as an agricultural state, and owning a part of it was and always remained the traditional, basic and best source and index of wealth. Yet the foundations of Athens' robust economic position in the fifth century had been set down, by Solon and then the Peisistratidai, principally by fostering the non-landed sectors of the Athenian economy. By about the time of the Persian Wars three interconnected areas were clearly emerging as important: a large and energetic immigrant community (160); a thriving commercial traffic through the Peiraieus (159) – these two linked by a policy of welcoming foreigners, whether as residents or visitors (158); and the optimisation of Attika's supreme natural asset, the silver mines (161). These three areas were still seen as crucial in the mid-fourth century, when Xenophon came to write his treatise Ways and Means (Poroi); in addition he proposed acquisition by the state of a slave labour force (see 277, and Ch.29 in general). The bulk of chattel-slaves were in fact in private ownership, however; and their contribution to the economy was vital (162).
The nuances of Spartan politics can no more be observed during the Peloponnesian War than at any other time; with Athens one can, on the other hand, piece together some evidence for the character and problems of war-time political life. The basic context for it was the fact that the entire population of Attika was evacuated to the astu itself (207). On an abstract view this might have been no bad thing, with decision-making in the ekklēsia thus more fully representative of ‘the Athenians’ as a whole than ever before (and ever again), and general political awareness profitably increased thereby. In fact however the outcome seems to have been at best apathy (211) and at worst the development of symptoms of stress and strain within the very fabric of a radical democratic system, now left (as Thucydides, at any rate, saw it: 208–209) with inferior and unstable leaders to guide it through the war; the competence of the dēmos to sustain a consistent strategy was called into question (210), and a gulf began to open between those advising a course of action and those who had the job of implementing it (212).
The Persian and the Greek worlds met along the coast of Asia Minor. There, the Greek (and particularly the Ionian) poleis found themselves, after the fall of Lydia, as the western seaboard of the Achaimenid empire – the dominant military and territorial power of the Near and Middle East. But the Asiatic Greeks never fully reconciled themselves to Persian suzerainty; and their efforts, under energetic and ambitious leaders, to enlist the support of the Balkan and Aegean Greeks in throwing off Persian rule brought the two worlds into direct conflict with each other. The confrontation – chronicled by the West's first true historian, Herodotus – saw the Persians twice beaten back; while at the other end of the Mediterranean the Greeks of Sicily withstood a scarcely less weighty assault from Carthage. See in general Burn, Persia, and Hignett, Xerxes.
The tyrants sponsored by Persia
The Persians no doubt found it easy to deal with a single person in each of the poleis under their control, as well as in accord with their belief in the propriety of monarchy, and few Greeks were able to resist the temptation offered by the position of tyranny or quasi-tyranny which resulted (see Andrewes, Tyrants, 123–4). In the course of Dareios' Skythian expedition, the Greek leaders guarding the bridge over the Danube were invited by the Skythians to remove it; their response was not automatic and was, in the end, negative.
In the immediate aftermath of the Persian Wars, the Athenians showed themselves more eager than anyone else to carry the war into enemy territory and before long replaced the Spartans as the hēgemones of the allied forces; and a new alliance was created to prosecute the war (129–130). Much modern debate centres round an alleged transformation of this Delian League into an Athenian empire (for instance, Meiggs, Empire, ch.9). It is of course clear that practice hardened into precedent as the years went by, and that the Athenians took various coercive measures as they became necessary to ensure their hegemony; it is also clear that the phrase used by the Athenians ‘the poleis over which the Athenians rule’ (e.g. Thuc. V.47.2) is not conceivable in 477, and that allied perceptions of their position changed between then and 431; but it is not clear that Thucydides is wrong to hang his general account of the Athenian empire on the first revolt and largely ignore the detailed mechanisms by which the Athenians ensured their hegemony (134–135). What is important is that it was an Athenian organisation from start to finish (compare VIII.68.4 = 227b, and see M. I. Finley, ‘The fifth-century Athenian empire: a balance sheet’, in P. D. A. Garnsey and C. R. Whittaker (eds.), Imperialism in the Ancient World (Cambridge, 1978), ch.5).
The acquisition of an empire of course went hand in hand with the emergence of the dēmos in control at Athens itself, a fact of which the demos took advantage.
Of the allies of Sparta, the Boiotians, Corinthians, Eleians and Megarians had voted against the peace of 421 (see 193); in the uncertain atmosphere of the period, the Spartans seem to have attempted to restore the unity between themselves and the Athenians which had obtained at the time of the Persian Wars. The Argives, fearing the Spartans, sought first to ally themselves with Sparta's disgruntled allies, then to bring in an Athens suspicious of Sparta; and ‘traditional’ alignments at once asserted themselves once more – Sparta and her allies (except for Elis and Mantineia) on the one side, Athens and Argos on the other.
202. The problems of peace
One factor which had no doubt encouraged some Spartans to vote for war in 432 was the fear that their allies would otherwise abandon them (and the defensive ring round the vulnerable Spartan politeia disappear); Spartan hopes in 421, however, that they would not be forced to choose between peace with Athens and the satisfaction of their allies, turned out to be ill-founded.
It fell by lot to the Spartans to be the first to give back what they held, and so they at once released the men whom they held as prisoners and sent Ischagoras and Menas and Philocharidas as ambassadors to the area of Thrake to order Klearidas to hand over Amphipolis to the Athenians and everyone else to implement the terms of the treaty as they applied to them.
The archaic period – conventionally the eighth, seventh and sixth centuries – is a uniquely interesting and important era of Greek history. It is also uniquely difficult to study in detail, especially through the medium of a source-book of this kind, chiefly because (as already explained, p. 5) the developments which characterise it were already under way before the appearance of any record, literary or epigraphical, to document them. Already by the eighth century, for example, the Greeks probably perceived themselves as an entity, racial and cultural, distinct from all others (see 1–2); and although the part played by the formation of a shared system of values can often be adequately illustrated (5, 6, 12, 13), it remains extraordinarily hard to make sense of the period and its trends, and marshal the meagre and diverse data in the service of some sort of explanation of what was happening. One theme predominates: the evolution of what was to become, and remain, the characteristic form and expression of Greek society – the polis. (See above, pp. 1–4. There is an excellent discussion of this (problematical) historical development by Austin and Vidal-Naquet, Economy, 49–53.)
At the beginning of the first millennium, Greek communities formed the population of mainland Greece, the Aegean islands, some areas of western Asia Minor and parts of Cyprus (the last two as a result of recent settlement). In the core of this area – Greece, the Aegean and coastal Asia Minor – they lived in small, poor, static communities, with little contact with the rest of the Mediterranean. Five centuries later, the communities of this core of the Greek world were – by ancient standards – wealthy, organised and creative; and similar communities were spread throughout the Mediterranean and the Black Sea.