Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 March 2024
Indigenous peoples have long challenged the claims of European states and their settler colonial successors to exercise sovereignty over their territories. Ever since the 1960 United Nations (UN) ‘Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial Countries and Peoples’, General Assembly Resolution 1514 (XV) (United Nations 1960) limited the right of self-determination to subjugated territories that were ‘geographically separate’ – a requirement often misleadingly referred to as the ‘blue water’ or ‘salt water’ thesis, suggesting the need for there to be ocean between the colonial power and the territory in question – their path towards decolonisation has been different from that of the territories decolonised during the 1950s and 1960s. Up until the adoption in 2007 of the UN ‘Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples’, General Assembly Resolution 61/295 (UNDRIP, United Nations 2007), it has largely been pursued through the domestic courts and legislatures of the settler colonial countries. These countries developed a range of constitutional and legal settlements that determined the status of the Indigenous peoples, from domestic dependant sovereignty to treaties and the recognition of common law rights to land and other resources. A variety of arguments have been put forward in support of special status and specific rights for such colonised Indigenous peoples, in the ongoing effort to ‘decolonise’ their relationship to the liberal democratic states that have inherited these constitutional and legal settlements. One such argument raises questions about the legitimacy of government by such states (Ivison 2017; Moore 2010; Patton 2009, 2019).
There are two distinct approaches to the question of legitimacy in contemporary political philosophy. One approach builds on the tradition from John Locke to Immanuel Kant and John Rawls in supposing that government is legitimate when it produces the kinds of moral goods expected of government, such as justice. In these terms, it may be argued that citizens who benefit from the protections of a just social order tacitly consent to the government that provides those protections. Rawls argues that the exercise of (coercive) political power is legitimate when it produces justice, or at least a political regime that is not too unjust.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.