To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
The interest of the community then is – what? The sum of the interests of the several members who compose it.
Jeremy Bentham
Whereas one can speak of the positive theory of public choice, based upon economic man assumptions, one must think of normative theories of public choice, for there are many views of what the goals of the state should be and how to achieve them. This potential multiplicity has been the focus of much criticism by positivists, who have argued for a “value-free” discipline. For the bulk of economics, it might be legitimate to focus on explanation and prediction, and leave to politics the explication of the goals of society. For the study of politics itself, in toto, to take this position is less legitimate; thus the interest in how the basic values of society are or can be expressed through the political process. The challenge that normative theory faces is to develop theorems about the expression and realization of values, based on generally accepted postulates, in the same way that positive theory has developed explanatory and predictive theorems from the postulates of rational egoistic behavior. Part V reviews some efforts to take up this challenge.
The Bergson-Samuelson social welfare function
The traditional means for representing the values of the community in economics is to use a social welfare function (SWF). The seminal paper on SWFs is by Bergson (1938), with the most significant further explication by Samuelson (1947, ch. 8).
The individuals themselves, each in his own personal and sovereign right, entered into a compact with each other to produce a government; and this is the only mode in which governments have a right to arise and the only principle on which they have a right to exist.
Thomas Paine
The ideally perfect constitution of a public office is that in which the interest of the functionary is entirely coincident with his duty. No mere system will make it so, but still less can it be made so without a system, aptly devised for the purpose.
John Stuart Mill
We have already discussed several works that have assumed uncertainty over future position to derive a normative theory of social choice. Rawls's (1971) theory discussed in Chapter 25 uses uncertainty over future position to derive principles of justice to be included in a social contract; Harsanyi (1953, 1955, 1977) uses it to derive an additive SWF (see Chapter 23).
Buchanan and Tullock (1962) develop a theory of constitutional government in which the constitution is written in a setting resembling that depicted by Harsanyi and Rawls. Individuals are uncertain about their future positions and thus are led out of self-interest to select rules that weigh the positions of all other individuals (Buchanan and Tullock, 1962, pp. 77–80). Buchanan and Tullock's theory is at once positive and normative.
In this Method [the Method of Marks], a certain number of marks is fixed, which each elector shall have at his disposal; he may assign them all to one candidate, or divide them among several candidates, in proportion to their eligibility; and the candidate who gets the greatest total of marks is the winner.
This method would, I think, be absolutely perfect, if only each elector wished to do all in his power to secure the election of that candidate who should be the most generally acceptable, even if that candidate should not be the one of his own choice: in this case he would be careful to make the marks exactly represent his estimate of the relative eligibility of all the candidates, even of those he least desired to see elected; and the desired result would be secured.
But we are not sufficiently unselfish and public-spirited to give any hope of this result being attained. Each elector would feel that it was possible for each other elector to assign the entire number of marks to his favorite candidate, giving to all the other candidates zero: and he would conclude that, in order to give his own favorite candidate any chance of success, he must do the same for him.
To sum up, for the Fascist everything is within the state and there exists nothing, human or spiritual, or even less has value, outside of the state. In this sense Fascism is totalitarian and the Fascist state interprets, develops and multiplies the whole life of the people as a synthesis and unity of each value.
Benito Mussolini
The postulate of methodological individualism underlies all public choice analysis. In trying to explain governmental actions, we begin by analyzing the behavior of the individuals who make up the government. In a democracy these are the voters, their elected representatives, and appointed bureaucrats. The postulate of methodological individualism has a normative analogue. The actions of government ought to correspond, in some fundamental way, to the preferences of the individuals whom these actions affect – the citizens of the state. This postulate of normative individualism underlies much of the normative analysis in public choice. It is quite understandable, therefore, that virtually all research in public choice has concentrated on the analysis of democratic governments, first because virtually all public choice scholars have lived in democratic countries and thus this form of political system has the most intrinsic interest for them, and second because they feel that all governmental systems ought to be organized as democracies.
Among the laws that rule human societies there is one which seems to be more precise and clear than all others. If men are to remain civilized or to become so, the art of associating together must grow and improve in the same ratio in which the equality of conditions is increased.
Alexis de Tocqueville
In his book Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (1970), Albert Hirschman developed the useful distinction between processes in which individuals express their preferences via entry or exit decisions, and those in which some form of written, verbal, or voice communication is employed. An example of the first would be a market for a private good in which buyers indicate their attitudes toward the price-quality characteristics of a good by increasing or decreasing (entry or exit) their purchases. An example of the exercise of voice to influence a price-cost nexus would be a complaint or commendation of the product delivered to the manufacturer. A necessary condition for the effective use of exit is obviously that the potential users of this option be mobile: and full mobility of both buyers and sellers (free entry and exit) is an assumption underlying all demonstrations of market efficiency. In contrast, the literature focusing on voting processes, public choice and political science, has almost exclusively assumed (most often implicitly) that exit is not an option. The boundaries of the polity are predefined and inclusive; the citizenry is fixed.
Unanimity is impossible; the rule of a minority, as a permanent arrangement, is wholly inadmissible; so that, rejecting the majority principle, anarchy or despotism in some form is all that is left.
Abraham Lincoln
… unless the king has been elected by unanimous vote, what, failing a prior agreement, is the source of the minority's obligation to submit to the choice of the majority? Whence the right of the hundred who do wish a master to speak for the ten who do not? The majority principle is itself a product of agreement, and presupposes unanimity on at least one occasion.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
In Chapter 4 we argued that the ubiquitous popularity of majority rule might be attributable to the speed with which committees can make decisions using it. This quickness defense was undermined considerably in Chapter 5 by the results on cycling. A committee caught in a voting cycle may not be able to reach a decision quickly, and the outcome at which it eventually does arrive may be arbitrarily determined by institutional details, or nonarbitrarily determined by a cunning agenda setter. Is this all one can say in majority rule's behalf? Does the case for the majority rule rest on the promise that quasi-omniscient party leaders can arrange stable trades to maximize the aggregate welfare of the legislature discussed in Section 5.13.3?
When asked to explain majority rule's popularity, students unfamiliar with the vast public choice literature on the topic usually mention justness, fairness, egalitarian, and similar normative attributes that they feel characterize majority rule.
Politicians are the same all over. They promise to build a bridge even where there is no river.
Nikita Khruschev
Much attention in both lay and academic discourse has been given to the question of the proper size of government and the reasons for its growth. Public choice, the economic analysis of political institutions, would seem to be the natural tool for answering these questions, and it has frequently been employed in this task. A review of these efforts follows.
The facts
That government has grown, and grown dramatically in recent years, cannot be questioned. Total government expenditure in the United States in 1999 as a percentage of GNP was 28.3 percent, up from 23 percent in 1949 and 10 percent in 1929 (see Table 21.1). Moreover, this growth is confined neither to this century nor to the United States. Federal government expenditures as a percentage of national income in the United States were only 1.4 percent of national income in 1799. They rose to double that figure by the end of the nineteenth century, but were still only 3 percent of the GNP in 1929. Starting in the 1930s, however, federal expenditures took off, rising sevenfold as a percentage of the GNP over the next 70 years.
The government sector has also grown outside of the United States with this growth beginning at least as far back as the nineteenth century. Table 21.2 presents figures from Tanzi and Schuknecht (2000) for 16 countries in addition to the United States.
The positive evils and dangers of the representative, as of every other form of government, may be reduced to two heads: first, general ignorance and incapacity, or, to speak more moderately, insufficient mental qualifications, in the controlling body; secondly, the danger of its being under the influence of interests not identical with the general welfare of the community. (Italics in original)
John Stuart Mill
In Chapter 12 we discussed a model of political competition in which politicians provide policies or legislation to win votes, and citizens and interest groups provide votes. From the discussion up to this point, it seems reasonable to think that the legislation consists of either public goods with characteristics that appeal to given groups of voters or income transfers from one sector of the population to another. The latter might be a tax loophole benefiting a particular group coupled with a rise in the average tax rate to make up for the revenue lost through the loophole. Income can be transferred from one group to another by other, more subtle means, however.
The government can, for example, help create, increase, or protect a group's monopoly position. In so doing, the government increases the monopoly rents of the favored groups at the expense of the buyers of the groups' products or services. The monopoly rents that the government can help provide are a prize worth pursuing, and the pursuit of these rents has been given the name of rent seeking.
Political organization is to be understood as that part of social organization which constantly carries on directive restraining functions for public ends. …
That the cooperation into which men have gradually risen secures to them benefits which could not be secured while, in their primitive state, they acted singly, and that, as an indispensable means to this cooperation political organization has been, and is, advantageous, we shall see on contrasting the states of men who are not politically organized with the states of men who are politically organized in less or greater degrees.
Herbert Spencer
As the state arose from the need to keep class antagonisms in check, but also arose in the thick of the fight between the classes, it is normally the state of the most powerful, economically dominant, class which by its means becomes also the politically dominant class and so acquires new means of holding down and exploiting the oppressed class. The ancient state was, above all, the state of the slave owners for holding down the slaves.
Friedrich Engels
When there is no middle class, and the poor greatly exceed in number, troubles arise, and the state soon becomes to an end.
Aristotle
A decent provision for the poor is the true test of civilization.
Samuel Johnson
It is easy to envisage government arising out of pristine anarchy to fulfill a collective need of the community (say, protection from a predator) or to coordinate hunting or other food-gathering activity.
This book is a revision of Public Choice II. In revising the book, I have largely retained the structure of Public Choice II – most of the material contained in that volume reappears in this one. In some cases, this has resulted in very modest changes in a chapter and in quite substantial changes in others. Several new chapters have been written to cover topics that have cropped up or increased in importance since the previous edition was written. I have also attempted to retain the same level of difficulty as the previous version. Because the literature has become continuously more theoretical and mathematical, more mathematics appears in the new material than in the previous text, and the distinction between “easy” and “difficult” sections denoted by a * has become more arbitrary. Some may question my decision not to drop more material from the previous text, where little new work has appeared, to leave more space for new material. I have chosen not to go this route because I still think of the book as a survey of all of the major topics in public choice. That little new has appeared concerning Arrow impossibility theorems in recent years does not imply that the issues raised by this work are any less important, or that they should be omitted in a basic course in public choice – or so I believe.
To what expedient, then, shall we finally resort, for maintaining in practice the necessary partition of power among the several departments, as laid down in the Constitution? The only answer that can be given is, that as all these exterior provisions are found to be inadequate, the defect must be supplied, by so contriving the interior structure of the government as that its several constitutent parts may, by their mutual relations, be the means of keeping each other in their proper places.
The Federalist, No. 51
In the rent-seeking model of politics discussed in Chapter 15, politicians buy and sell legislation to interest groups. The legislature is a marketplace at which rents are bought and sold. Problems of bureaucratic discretion are ignored. The legislature is in complete control. In stark contrast, in the first model of bureaucracy discussed in the previous chapter, the legislature is at the complete mercy of an all-powerful bureaucracy. Both types of models are, of course, polar cases derived to illustrate certain features of the political process. In this chapter we take a further look at the relationship between the legislature and the bureaucracies charged with implementing the policies initiated in the legislature. We also consider the separate role played by the chief executive in presidential systems like that of the United States, and the role of the judiciary. We begin with a model that completely reverses the power relationship of the Niskanen bureaucracy model.
There can be no doubt, that if power is granted to a body of men, called representatives, they, like any other men, will use their power, not for the advantage of the community, but for their own advantage, if they can.
James Mill
Each official is evidently more active within the body to which he belongs than each citizen within that to which he belongs. The government's actions are accordingly influenced by the private wills of its members much more than the sovereign's [citizenry's] by those of its members – if only because the official is almost always individually responsible for any specific function of sovereignty. (Italics in original)
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
The preceding chapters have focused upon the demand side of public choice. The citizen voter's preferences determine outcomes in the public sector. Government, like the market in a pure exchange economy, is viewed simply as an institution for aggregating or balancing individual demands for public policies. Those in government, the candidates and representatives, have been depicted as single-mindedly seeking to be elected. To do so they must please voters, so that those in government are merely pawns of those outside in a competitive political system. Only in the rent-seeking literature just reviewed does one begin to obtain a glimpse of another side of government. Politicians may not live by votes alone. They, too, may seek wealth and leisure. Their preferences may impinge on the outcomes of the public sector.
When we move … away from the private concerns of the family and the business office into those regions of national and international affairs that lack a direct and unmistakable link with those private concerns, individual volition, command of facts and method of inference soon cease to fulfill the requirements of the classical doctrine. What strikes me most of all and seems to me to be the core of the trouble is the fact that the sense of reality is so completely lost. Normally, the great political questions take their place in the psychic economy of the typical citizen with those leisure-hour interests that have not attained the rank of hobbies, and with the subjects of irresponsible conversation. These things seem so far off; they are not at all like a business proposition; dangers may not materialize at all and if they should they may not prove so very serious; one feels oneself to be moving in a fictitious world.
The reduced sense of reality accounts not only for a reduced sense of responsibility but also for the absence of effective volition. One has one's phrases, of course, and one's wishes and daydreams and grumbles; especially, one has one's likes and dislikes. But ordinarily they do not amount to what we call a will – the psychic counterpart of purposeful responsible action. In fact, for the private citizen musing over national affairs there is no scope for such a will and no task at which it could develop.