1. Introduction
Let
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
be a sequence. The pair correlation counting function of
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is defined by

where we write
$\|x\| = \min\{ |x-k| \;:\; k\in \mathbb{Z} \}$
for the distance of
$x\in \mathbb{R}$
to its nearest integer. The sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is said to have Poissonian pair correlations (or PPC, for abbreviation) if

The notion of PPC is known to have connections with mathematical physics, which go far beyond the scope of this paper. For instance, we only mention the famous Berry–Tabor Conjecture [Reference Berry and Tabor3]. PPC have recently attracted increasing attention from the purely theoretical point of view. In particular, it has been shown (partially independently) by various authors that sequences with PPC are necessarily uniformly distributed [Reference Aistleitner, Lachmann and Pausinger1, Reference Grepstad and Larcher4, Reference Marklof6, Reference Steinerberger11].
The notion of PPC has an “inhomogeneous” variant, which nonetheless is not equally well studied. Given
$\gamma \in \mathbb R,$
we say that a sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
has
$\gamma$
- PPC if

where we define

Clearly, for
$\gamma=0$
and more generally for any integer value of
$\gamma $
in the above definition, one recovers the classical property of PPC. Since the property of
$\gamma$
- PPC is invariant under integer translations of
$\gamma,$
we will only consider values of
$\gamma \in [0,1].$
When
$0{\lt} \gamma {\lt} 1$
, we may refer to the property of
$\gamma$
- PPC as inhomogeneous Poissonian pair correlations with respect to
$\gamma$
. Also since
$\gamma$
- PPC is equivalent to
$(1-\gamma)$
- PPC, it will be sufficient to restrict our attention to values
$0{\lt} \gamma \leqslant 1/2.$
A first treatment of the notion of
$\gamma$
- PPC can be found in [Reference Ramirez7]. There, it is explained that like PPC, the property of
$\gamma$
- PPC with
$\gamma\neq 0$
is a pseudorandomness property, in the sense that if
$(X_n)_{n=1}^{\infty}$
is a sequence of i.i.d. random variables, all following the uniform distribution in [0, 1], then with probability 1 the sequence
$(X_n)_{n=1}^{\infty}$
has
$\gamma$
- PPC. In [Reference Ramirez7] it is also stated among other results that just like their homogeneous counterpart,
$\gamma$
- PPC is a property that is stronger than uniform distribution; in other words, any sequence with
$\gamma$
- PPC is automatically uniformly distributed.
In the first result of our paper, we prove that this statement is actually false!
Theorem 1·1. Let
$0{\lt}\gamma {\lt}1$
. Then there exists a sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
that has
$\gamma$
- PPC but is not uniformly distributed.
In addition to Theorem 1·1, we try to shed some light on the reason why PPC imply uniform distribution while
$\gamma$
- PPC with
$\gamma\neq 0$
do not. Among the several proofs of the fact that PPC imply uniform distribution that were mentioned earlier, Aistleitner, Lachmann and Pausinger in [Reference Aistleitner, Lachmann and Pausinger1] prove a stronger statement that connects the limiting behaviour of the pair correlation function
$R_2(s,N)$
with the asymptotic distribution function of the sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} .$
We say that the function
$G:[0,1] \to \mathbb{R}$
is the asymptotic distribution function of the sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
if

Their result is the following.
Theorem (ALP). Let
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
be a sequence with asymptotic distribution function
$G:[0,1] \to \mathbb{R}.$
Let
$F:[0,\infty)\rightarrow [0,\infty]$
be defined by

Then the following hold:
-
(i) if G is not absolutely continuous, then
$F(s)=\infty$ for all
$s{\gt}0$ ;
-
(ii) if G is absolutely continuous and g is the corresponding density function (that is,
$g = G'$ almost everywhere), then
(1·1)\begin{equation} \limsup_{s \to \infty}\frac{F(s)}{2s} \geqslant \int_0^1 g(x)^2 \,\mathrm{d}x. \end{equation}
This resultFootnote
1
indeed implies that PPC is a property stronger than uniform distribution. If
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is not u.d. mod 1, then the integral on the right-hand side of (1·1) is strictly greater than 1 and
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
cannot have PPC.
For uniformly distributed sequences, the density function is
$g(x)=1$
and thus the ALP Theorem implies that for any
$\varepsilon {\gt} 0$
,
$\liminf_{N\to \infty}R_2(s,N) \geqslant 2s- \varepsilon$
for arbitrarily large values of the scale
$s{\gt}0.$
In other words, among all uniformly distributed sequences, for those who have PPC, the quantity

exhibits an extremal behaviour, in the sense that it has the minimal possible asymptotic size, and this extremal behaviour is not attainable for non-uniformly distributed sequences.
Returning to the inhomogeneous PPC, the proof of Theorem 1·1 makes use of the following statement, which establishes a connection between the density function g and the limiting behaviour of
$R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)$
in a probabilistic context. We say that a random variable X with support in [0, 1] is distributed with respect to the function
$G\;:\;[0,1]\to \mathbb{R}$
if
$\mathbb P(X{\lt} t) = G(t)$
for all
$t\in [0,1].$
Theorem 1·2. Let
$\gamma\in\mathbb R$
and
$G:[0,1]\to \mathbb{R}$
be an absolutely continuous distribution function with corresponding density function
$g\in L^2([0,1]).$
Let
$(X_n)_{n\in\mathbb N}$
be a sequence of independent random variables on some probability space
$(\Omega, \Sigma, \mathbb P)$
with support in [0, 1] that are distributed with respect to G. Then, for the
$\gamma$
-pair correlation function of
$(x_n)_{n\in\mathbb N} \;:\!=\; {}(X_n(\omega))_{n\in\mathbb N}, \omega \in \Omega$
, we have
$\mathbb{P}$
-almost surely

Remark 1·3. In the rest of the paper, when
$g:[0,1]\to \mathbb{R}$
is a density function as above and
$\gamma\neq 0,$
we implicitly extend g to the real numbers periodically mod 1 and write
$\int_0^1 g(x)g(x+\gamma)\,\mathrm{d} x$
instead of
$\int_0^1 g(x)g(\{x+\gamma\})\,\mathrm{d} x$
, which would be more accurate.
We note that for the specific choice
$\gamma=0,$
Theorem 1·2 is the heuristic observation made in [Reference Aistleitner, Lachmann and Pausinger1, equation (2)]. Theorem 1·1 follows straightforwardly from Theorem 1·2 once we find a non-constant density g such that
$\int_{0}^{1} g(x)g(x + \gamma)\,\mathrm{d}x = 1$
for a fixed
$\gamma$
.
After establishing the connection between
$R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)$
and the density function g for random variables described in (1·2), we suspected that an analogue of the ALP Theorem is also true for
$\gamma\neq 0.$
That is, if g is the distribution function of the sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
and we define

then

However, it turns out that (1.4) is not true, either.
Theorem 1·4. For any
$0{\lt}\gamma {\lt}1$
, there exists a sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
with asymptotic density function
$g\;:\; [0,1] \to \mathbb{R}$
such that for the function
$F_\gamma$
as in (1.3) we have

Finally, we examine the relation between the property of
$\gamma$
- PPC for different values of
$\gamma.$
Observe that in view of Theorem 1·1,
$\gamma$
- PPC for
$\gamma \neq 0$
does not imply PPC; otherwise, every sequence with
$\gamma$
- PPC would need to be uniformly distributed. As a last result of the paper, we show that this is not a phenomenon that distinguishes between PPC and inhomogeneous pair correlations. In particular, it follows that the classical PPC property is not stronger than its inhomogeneous counterparts.
Theorem 1·5. Let
$\gamma_1,\gamma_2 \in [0,1/2]$
with
$\gamma_1 \neq \gamma_2$
. Then there exists a sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
that has
$\gamma_1$
- PPC but not
$\gamma_2$
- PPC.
Why
$\gamma$
- PPC? Before proceeding to the proofs of the theorems, we think it would be worth discussing what we view as the motivation behind the definition of
$\gamma$
- PPC. Beyond pure interest in the notion itself, this motivation arises in an open problem from the metric theory of (homogeneous) Poissonian pair correlations. Given an increasing sequence
$\mathcal{A} = (a_n)_{n\in \mathbb N} \subseteq \mathbb N$
, a series of results [Reference Aistleitner, Larcher and Lewko2, Reference Rudnick and Sarnak8–Reference Rudnick and Zaharescu10] shows that under certain assumptions on
$\mathcal{A}$
, the sequence
$(a_nx)_{n\in \mathbb N} $
has PPC for almost all
$x\in [0,1]$
. There also exist results [Reference Aistleitner, Larcher and Lewko2, 12] that provide conditions on
$\mathcal{A}$
under which the sequence
$(a_n x)_{n\in \mathbb N}$
has PPC for almost no
$x\in [0,1].$
However, it remains an open question to determine whether for any choice of
$\mathcal{A}$
, the sequence
$(a_n x)_{n\in \mathbb N}$
has PPC either for almost all or for almost no
$x\in [0,1],$
thus establishing a zero-one law in the theory of metric Poissonian pair correlations.
For
$\mathcal{A}$
fixed, writing
$ X_{\mathcal{A}} = \{ x\in [0,1] \;:\; (a_nx)_{n\in\mathbb N} \text{ has PPC}\},$
the aforementioned problem is equivalent to determining whether
$\lambda(X_{\mathcal{A}})=0$
or 1 for any choice of
$\mathcal{A}.$
To answer this question, it would suffice to check whether the set
$X_\mathcal{A}$
is invariant under the ergodic transformation
$T(x) = 2x \mod 1.$
Given
$x\in X_\mathcal{A},$
we have
$2x\in X_\mathcal{A}$
if and only if the pair correlation function of the sequence
$(2a_nx)_{n\in\mathbb N}$
satisfies
$\lim_{N\to \infty}R_2(2x,2s,N) = 4s$
for all
$s{\gt}0$
. But

and therefore
$2x\in X_\mathcal{A}$
if and only if the sequence
$(a_nx)_{n\in\mathbb N}$
has
${1}/{2}$
-PPC! In particular, Theorem 1·4 shows that the naïvest approach of immediately implying
$2x \in X_{\mathcal{A}}$
does not work and thus, if possible at all, one has to use the additional structure of the sequence.
Notation. Given
$x\in \mathbb{R}$
and
$r{\gt}0$
we write
$B(x,r)=\{ t \in \mathbb{R} \;:\; \|t-x\| \leqslant r\}$
for the interval of points in the unit torus that have distance at most r from x. Also throughout the text we shall use the standard Vinogradov
$\ll$
-notation: we write
$f(x)\ll g(x), x\to \infty$
when
$\limsup_{x\to \infty} f(x)/g(x) {\lt} \infty$
.
2. Proof of Theorems 1·1 and 1·2
As explained in the introduction, we begin with the proof of Theorem 1·2, which is a more general result of probabilistic nature. The existence of sequences
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
with
$\gamma$
–PPC that are not uniformly distributed will then follow as a simple corollary.
2·1. Proof of Theorem 1·2
When
$m\neq n,$
the random variable
$X_m - X_n$
has probability density function

Writing
$\mathcal{X} \;:\!=\; (X_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}}$
, the
$\gamma$
-pair correlation function

is itself a random variable with expectation

Since
$g\in L^2([0,1]),$
the function d(t) defined in (2·1) is bounded and continuous, hence

This allows us to conclude that

In the rest of the proof, we will write

for the set of pairs of indices appearing in the pair correlation functions.
The second moment of
$R_2^{\mathcal{X}}(\gamma;\; s, N )$
is equal to

The first of the terms above is equal to
$({1}/{N}) \mathbb E[ R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)].$
For the second term, we note that for
$\gamma = 0$
or
$\gamma = 1/2$
, we get another contribution of
$({1}/{N}) \mathbb E[ R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)]$
, while if
$\gamma \notin \{0,1/2\}$
, the second term vanishes for N sufficiently large. Thus, in any case, the contribution of the second term is bounded from above by
$({1}/{N}) \mathbb E[ R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)]$
, and it remains to examine the third term of (2·2).
In order to do so, note that the contribution of pairs
$(k,\ell), (m,n) \in \mathcal{D}_N$
that share one common coordinate is

which is equal to

Since for
$\ell \neq m$
the random variables
$X_\ell, X_m$
are independent, the above is equal to

Back to (2·2), for pairs
$(k,\ell), (m,n) \in \mathcal{D}_N$
with no common coordinate, the random variables
$X_k-X_\ell$
,
$X_m-X_n$
are independent and the corresponding contribution is

If we apply the same case distinction to the sum in

and combine with the equations above, we deduce that

where we used again that
$g \in L^2([0,1])$
. An application of Chebyshev’s inequality in combination with the first Borel–Cantelli Lemma shows that
$\mathbb{P}$
-almost surely in
$\omega\in \Omega$
we have

and a standard approximation argument (see e.g. [Reference Aistleitner, Larcher and Lewko2, p. 475]) shows that the same is true along the whole sequence
$R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)$
. This proves (1·2) for fixed
$s {\gt} 0$
.
In order to deduce (1·2) for all
$s {\gt} 0$
simultaneously, we apply the above procedure for every
$s \in \mathbb{Q}_{\geqslant 0}$
. Using that
$\mathbb{Q}$
is countable and dense in
$\mathbb{R}$
, the monotonicity of
$R_2(\gamma;\;s,N)$
as a function in s, and the continuity of
$s \mapsto 2s \cdot \int_{0}^{1} g(x)g(x + \gamma)\,\mathrm{d}x$
allows us to deduce that (1·2) holds almost surely for all
$s {\gt}0$
.
2·2. Proof of Theorem 1·1
In view of Theorem 1·2, in order to prove the existence of a sequence with
$\gamma$
- PPC that is not uniformly distributed, it simply suffices to define a density function g such that
$\int_0^1 g(x)g(x+\gamma)\,\mathrm{d} x =1$
and g is not identically equal to
$1.$
Then, any sequence of random variables
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
that has probability density function equal to g will almost surely have
$\gamma$
-PPC (by (1·2)) but will not be uniformly distributed; otherwise we would have
$g(x)=1$
for all
$x\in [0,1].$
Given
$\gamma \neq 0$
, we first consider the case when
$0 {\lt} \gamma {\lt} 1/2$
. Choose some
$\delta{\gt} 0$
with
$\delta {\lt} \gamma$
and
$\delta {\lt} 1 - 2\gamma$
and define

In the case when
$\gamma = 1/2$
, we take some
$0 {\lt} \delta {\lt} 1/2$
and let

In both cases, it is straightforward to check by elementary computations that the following three statements hold:

The case when
$1/2{\lt}\gamma{\lt}1$
is covered by the first case dealt with earlier, because
$\gamma$
-PPC is equivalent to
$(1-\gamma)$
-PPC. This concludes the proof of Theorem 1·1.
3. Proof of Theorem 1·3
We first prove the result for
$\gamma = 1/2$
and then we explain how the proof can be generalised to values
$0{\lt}\gamma {\lt} 1/2$
. In both cases, we shall make use of the binary van der Corput sequence
$(c_n)_{n\in \mathbb N}$
that is defined as follows (see also [Reference Kuipers and Niederreiter5]): writing
$n-1 = a_m(n)2^m + \ldots + a_1(n)2 + a_0(n)$
for the binary expansion of the integer
$n-1$
, the nth term of
$(c_n)_{n\in\mathbb N}$
is the number

When
$\gamma = 1/2.$
We shall construct a sequence
$ (x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1]$
that on the one hand is uniformly distributed, which implies
$\int_{0}^1 g(x) g(x-1/2) \,\mathrm{d}x = 1$
, but on the other hand

We will actually show something stronger: the relation above will hold with limit instead of liminf. We define the auxiliary sequences
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}}, (z_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
as follows: we set
$y_n = {1}/{2} c_n$
and

By these definitions, it is obvious that
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [0,1/2]$
and
$(z_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \subseteq [1/2,1]$
.
The sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is constructed recursively, with the Nth step involving the definition of the terms
$x_n, \, 2(N-1)2^{N-1} {\lt} n \leqslant 2N2^N.$
At step
$N = 1$
, we set

Assume that for some
$N\geqslant 1$
we have defined all points
$x_n, 1\leqslant n\leqslant 2N2^{N}.$
Set

The
$2(N+1)2^N$
-tuple
$(x_{2(N+1)2^N+1},\ldots, x_{2(N+1)2^{N+1}})$
is then defined by concatenating the
$2^{N+1}$
tuple

$N+1$
-times with itself. In that way, for each
$N\geqslant 1$
the terms
$x_1,\ldots, x_{2N2^N}$
contain N copies of the points
$y_1,\ldots,y_{2^N}$
and N copies of the points
$z_1,\ldots, z_{2^N}.$
It is straightforward to check that the sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is uniformly distributed, so it remains to prove that
$F_{\frac12}(s)=0$
. For any
$N\geqslant 1$
, set

We claim that

This is obvious for
$a,b \in Y_N$
. Since

the inequality in (3·1) also holds when
$a,b \in Z_N$
. It remains to check the case when
$a \in Y_N, b \in Z_N$
(or vice-versa); then

since 3 is coprime to
$2^N$
. This proves (3·1).
Now given
$M \in \mathbb N$
, let
$N = N(M)\geqslant 1$
be defined by

We then have the inclusion

Thus for a fixed value of
$s {\gt} 0$
, whenever
$ \#\left\{a,b \in Y_N \cup Z_N\;:\; \lVert a- b - 1/2 \rVert \leqslant{s}/{2N\cdot 2^N}\right\}=0,$
then also
$\#\left\{n, m \leqslant M\;:\; \lVert x_n - x_m - 1/2 \rVert \leqslant{s}/{M} \right\}=0$
. Hence for all
$N \geqslant 6s$
, (3·1) implies that
$\#\left\{n, m \leqslant M\;:\; \lVert x_n - x_m - 1/2 \rVert \leqslant{s}/{M} \right\}=0$
and we obtain
$F_{1/2}(s) = 0$
.
When
$0 {\lt} \gamma {\lt} 1/2$
. We set
$\varepsilon = 2^{-i}$
where
$i\geqslant 1$
is large enough such that
$0 {\lt} \varepsilon {\lt} min \{(1/2-\gamma)/2, \gamma\}$
. We then define
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
and
$(z_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
by setting

The sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is then defined precisely as in the case
$\gamma = 1/2$
.
One can use the same arguments as before to show that for any
$s{\gt}0$
we have
$F_\gamma(s)=0.$
On the other hand, the asymptotic density function of
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
is

and thus
$ \int_{0}^1 g(x)g(x+\gamma) \mathrm{d}x = 1/(4\varepsilon) {\gt} 0, $
which concludes the proof.
Remark 3·1. Note that the sequence defined above for
$\gamma \neq 1/2$
is not uniformly distributed. However, one could adapt the construction by “diluting” the sequence with i.i.d. samples on
$[\varepsilon,\gamma] \cup [\gamma + \varepsilon,1]$
in order to get a sequence that almost surely is uniformly distributed mod 1 and satisfies

We leave the details to the interested reader.
4.
$\gamma_1$
- PPC does not imply
$\gamma_2$
- PPC
We finish with the proof of Theorem 1·4. Let
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
be a sequence of independent random variables, following the uniform distribution in [0, 1]. Define
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
by

In what follows, we will write
$R_2^{\mathcal{X}}$
and
$R_2^{\mathcal{Y}}$
for the pair correlation functions of
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
and
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
respectively. Then by definition of
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
,

Taking
$s {\lt} {1}/{4}$
, the above shows that
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
does not have
$\gamma_2$
- PPC. We claim that
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
has still almost surely
$\gamma_1$
- PPC: we have

Since
$\gamma_1 - \gamma_2, \gamma_1 + \gamma_2 \notin \mathbb{Z}$
, the last two terms in the above equation vanish if N is sufficiently large. By Theorem 1·2, the sequence
$(x_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
has
$\gamma_1$
- PPC and
$(\gamma_1-\gamma_2)$
- PPC and
$(\gamma_1+\gamma_2)$
- PPC almost surely, therefore with probability 1 we have

A standard approximation argument now gives that
$\lim_{N\to \infty}R_2^\mathcal{Y}(\gamma_1;\;s,N) =2s$
for all scales
$s{\gt}0$
, which means that
$(y_n)_{n \in \mathbb{N}} $
has
$\gamma_1$
- PPC almost surely.
Acknowledgements
MH is supported by the EPSRC grant EP/X030784/1. A part of this work was supported by the Swedish Research Council under grant no. 2016-06596 while MH was in residence at Institut Mittag-Leffler in Djursholm, Sweden in 2024. AZ is supported by European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation Program, Grant agreement no. 754475.