Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-5jtmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-12T01:12:32.982Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2025

Joseph Mendola
Affiliation:
University of Nebraska, Lincoln
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'

Information

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Abramov, I. and Gordon, J.. 1994. Color appearance: on seeing red – or yellow, or green, or blue. Annual Review of Psychology 45, 451485.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Akins, K. 1996. Lost the plot? Mind & Language 11, 143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albert, B., Heald, R., and Johnson, A., et al. 2015. The Molecular Biology of the Cell, sixth edition. New York: Garland Press.Google Scholar
Allen, K. 2009. Inter-species variation in colour perception. Philosophical Studies 142, 197220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aranyosi, I. 2013. The Peripheral Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of Mind. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Aronov, D., Nevers, R., and Tank, D. W.. 2017. Mapping of a non-spatial dimension by the hippocampal-entorhinal circuit. Nature 543, 719722.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arstila, V. and Lloyd, D.. 2014. Subjective Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, D. F. 1985. What’s the Meaning of “This”? Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Azzouni, T. J. 2013. Semantic Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, B. J. 1988. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baars, B. J. 1997. In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workplace of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, D. J. 2012. “The experience of left and right” meets the physics of left and right. NOUS 46, 483498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balog, K. 2012. Acquaintance and the mind-body problem. In Gozzano, S. and Hill, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Type Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barinaga, M. 1999. Learning visualized, on the double. Science 286, 1661.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bartoshuk, L. 1978. History of taste research. In Carterette, E. and Friedman, M. (eds.), Handbook of Perception, VIa. New York: Academic Press, 318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barwich, A. S. 2020. Smellosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batty, C. 2014. Olfactory objects. In Stokes, D., Matthen, M., and Biggs, S. (eds.), Perception and Its Modalities. New York: Oxford University Press, 222246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayne, T. 2008. The unity of consciousness and the split-brain syndrome. Journal of Philosophy 105, 277300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayne, T. 2009. Perception and the reach of phenomenal content. Philosophical Quarterly 59, 385404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayne, T. 2010. The Unity of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayne, T. 2020. Conscious thought. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 142163.Google Scholar
Bayne, T., Hohwy, J., and Owen, A. M.. 2016. Are there levels of consciousness? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 20, 405413.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beament, J. 2003. How We Hear Music. Martlesham: Boydell.Google Scholar
Bear, M. F., Connors, B. W., and Paradiso, M. A.. 2016. Neuroscience, fourth edition. Philadelphia, PA: Wolters-Kluwer.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. 1966. Kant’s Analytic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berger, M. and Gerstenbrand, F.. 1981. Phantom illusions in spinal cord lesions. In Siegried, J. and Zimmermann, M. (eds.), Phantom and Stump Pain. Berlin: Springer, 6673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkeley, G. 1710. An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision. Dublin: Rhames.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. 2003. Thinking Without Words. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biederman, I. 2013. Psychophysical and neural correlates of the phenomenology of shape. In Albertazzi, L. (ed.), Handbook of Experimental Phenomenology: Visual Perception of Shape, Space, and Appearance. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 417436.Google Scholar
Billock, V. A. and Tsou, B. H.. 2010. Seeing forbidden colors. Scientific American 302, 7277.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blackwell, H. R. and Schlosberg, H.. 1943. Octave generalization, pitch discrimination, and loudness thresholds in the white rat. Journal of Experimental Psychology 33, 407419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 1978. Troubles with functionalism. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9, 261325.Google Scholar
Block, N. 1990. Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives 4, 5379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 1995. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18, 227247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2007. Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30, 481548.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. 2008. Consciousness and cognitive access. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 108, 289317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2010. Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues 20, 2363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2013. The grain of vision and the grain of attention. Thought 1, 170184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2014. Rich conscious perception outside focal attention. Trends in Cognitive Science 18, 445447.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. and Stalnaker, R.. 1999. Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review 108, 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, G. H., Diamant, H., Ström, L., and Zotterman, Y.. 1967. The relation between neural and perceptual intensity. The Journal of Physiology 192, 1320.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boring, E. G. 1942. Sensation and Perception in the History of Experimental Psychology. New York: Appleton.Google Scholar
Bourget, D. 2010. Consciousness is underived intentionality. NOUS 44, 3258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bower, J. M. and Parsons, L. M.. 2003. Rethinking the “lesser brain”. Scientific American 296, 5157.Google Scholar
Bowmaker, J. K. and Dartnall, H. J. A.. 1980. Visual pigments of rods and cones in a human retina. Journal of Physiology 298, 501511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradbury, J. 2004. Taste perception: cracking the code. PLoS Biology 2, 295297.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bregman, A. S. 1990. Auditory Scene Analysis: The Perceptual Organization of Sound. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bricker, P. 2001. Island universes and the analysis of modality. In Preyer, G. and Siebelt, F. (eds.), Reality and Humean Supervenience. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2755.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. 2006. Absolute actuality and the plurality of worlds. Philosophical Perspectives 20, 4176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broackes, J. 2010. What do the color-blind see? In Cohen, J. and Matthen, M. (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 291404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broackes, J. 2011. Where do the unique hues come from? Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2, 601628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bull, M. and Back, L. (eds.). 2003. The Auditory Culture Reader. Oxford: Berg.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D.. 2003. Color realism and color science, with commentaries. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26, 364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D.. 2010. How do things look to the color-blind? In Cohen, J. and Matthen, M. (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 259290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J. 1997. A simple view of color. In Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D. (eds.), Readings on Color, Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 177190.Google Scholar
Campbell, J. 1999. Past, Space, and Self. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, J. 2002. Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, K. 1970. Body and Mind. London: Doubleday.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cao, R. 2012. A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain. Biology and Philosophy 27, 4971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cao, R. 2014. Signaling in the brain: in search of functional units. Philosophy of Science 81, 891901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, S. B. 2005. Endless Forms Most Beautiful. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2000. Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cervero, F. 2012. Understanding Pain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2, 200219.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2002. Does conceivability entail possibility? In Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 145200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2004. Epistemic two-dimensional semantics. Philosophical Studies 18, 153226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2010. The Character of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2012. Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. and Jackson, F.. 2001. Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review 110, 315361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chandrashekar, J., Hoon, M. A., Ryba, N. J. P., and Zuker, C. S.. 2006. The receptors and cells for mammalian taste. Nature 444, 288294.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chang, L. and Tsao, D. Y.. 2017. The code for facial identity in the primate brain. Cell 169, 10131028.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chemero, A. 2009. Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chirimuuta, M. 2014. Minimal models and canonical neural computation. Synthese 191, 127153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chuard, P. 2020. Temporal consciousness. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 188207.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. 1986. Some reductive strategies in cognitive neurobiology. Mind 95, 279309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. 1995. The Engine of Reason, The Seat of the Soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy. 1996. Being There. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Austen. 1993. Sensory Qualities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, Austen. 2000. A Theory of Sentience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Austen. 2004. Feature-placing and proto-objects, and reply to commentators. Philosophical Psychology 17, 451477 and 563–589.Google Scholar
Cohen, J. 2009. The Red and the Real. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cole-Adams, K. 2018. Anaesthesia. Berkeley, CA: Counterpoint Press.Google Scholar
Conee, E. 1994. Phenomenal knowledge. Australian Journal of Philosophy 72, 136150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coombs, J. 1993. The possibility of created entities in seventeenth-century Scotism. The Philosophical Quarterly 43, 447459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-P., and Thompson, E.. 2007. Neurodynamical approaches to consciousness. In Zelazo, P. D., Moscovitch, M., and Thompson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 731772.Google Scholar
Cowart, B. J. and Rawson, N. E.. 2001. Olfaction. In Goldstein, E. (ed.), The Blackwell Handbook of Perception. Oxford: Blackwell, 568.Google Scholar
Crane, H. D. and Piantanida, T. P.. 1983. On seeing reddish green and yellowish blue. Science 221, 10781080.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Craver, C. 2007. Explaining the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crick, F. and Koch, C.. 2003. A framework for consciousness. Nature Neuroscience 6, 119126.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cynx, J. 1993. Auditory frequency generalization and a failure to find octave generalization in a songbird, the European starling. Journal of Comparative Psychology 107, 140146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dainton, B. 2000. Stream of Consciousness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dainton, B. 2014. The phenomenal continuum. In Arstila, V. and Lloyd, D. (eds.), Subjective Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 101137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dainton, B. 2023. Temporal consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown & Co.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. 1994. Why do mirrors reverse left/right and not up/down? Philosophy 69, 205210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deonna, J. and Teroni, F.. 2020. Emotional experience. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 102123.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1973. Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of Signs, Allison, D. B. (trans.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Derrington, A. M., Krauskopf, J., and Lennie, P.. 1984. Chromatic mechanisms in lateral geniculate nucleus of macaque. Journal of Physiology 357, 241265.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DeValois, R. L. and DeValois, K. K.. 1988. Spatial Vision. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Di Lorenzo, P. M., Chen, J.-Y., and Victor, J. D.. 2009. Quality time: representations of a multidimensional sensory domain through temporal coding. Journal of Neuroscience 29, 92279238.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edelman, S. 1998. Representation is representation of similarities. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21, 449498.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Egan, A. 2006. Appearance properties? NOUS 40, 495521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenreich, B. 2018. Natural Causes. New York: Twelve.Google Scholar
Eliasmith, C. 1996. The third contender. Philosophical Psychology 9, 441463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellenberger, H. 1970. The Discovery of the Unconscious. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Elpidorou, A. 2015. Review of The Peripheral Mind. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, https://ndpr.nd.edu, 2015.04.26.Google Scholar
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference, ed. by McDowell, J.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Falkowski, P. G. 2015. Life’s Engines. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Farkas, K. 2008. Phenomenal intentionality without compromise. The Monist 91, 273293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, K. 2013. Constructing a world for the senses. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 99115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fields, R. D. 2004. The other half of the brain. Scientific American 297, 5461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fields, R. D. 2008. White matter matters. Scientific American 301, 5461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1990. A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Förster, E. 2002. Kant’s Final Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Frankish, K. 2016. Illusionism as a theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 23, 1139.Google Scholar
Friederici, A. 2017. Language in Our Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Freud, S. 1962. The Ego and the Id, Riviere, J. and Strachey, J. (trans.). New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1963. General Psychological Theory. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1965. The Interpretation of Dreams, Strachey, J. (trans.). New York: Avon Books.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1989. Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis and New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis, Strachey, J. (trans.). New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. and Zahavi, D.. 2014. Primal impression and enactive perception. In Arstila, V. and Lloyd, D. (eds.), Subjective Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 8399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazzaniga, M. S. 1970. The Bisected Brain. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R. B., and Mangun, G. R.. 2002. Cognitive Neuroscience, second edition. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Geldard, F. A and Sherrick, C. E.. 1972. The cutaneous “rabbit”: a perceptual illusion. Science 178, 178179.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gennaro, R. 1996. Consciousness and Self-Consciousness. Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gertler, B. 2001. Introspecting phenomenal states. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 305327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbs, W. W. 2003. The unseen genome. Scientific American 297, 4753.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Glennan, S. 1996. Mechanism and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44, 4971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, S. 2017. The New Mechanical Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2007. Information in biology. In Hull, D. and Ruse, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to The Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 103119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2016a. Animal evolution and the origins of experience. In Smith, D. L. (ed.), How Biology Shapes Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 5171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2016b. Individuality, subjectivity, and minimal cognition. Biology and Philosophy 31, 775796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2016c. Mind, matter, and metabolism. Journal of Philosophy 113, 481506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2017. Other Minds. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.Google Scholar
Godrey-Smith, P. 2020. Gradualism and the evolution of experience. Philosophical Topics 48, 201220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goff, P. 2017. Consciousness and Fundamental Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goff, P. and Coleman, S.. 2020. Russellian monism. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 301327.Google Scholar
Goodsell, D. S. 2010. The Machinery of Life, second edition, second corrected printing. New York: Copernicus Books.Google Scholar
Gordon, I. and Hayward, S.. 1973. Second-order isomorphism of internal representations of familiar faces. Perception & Psychophysics 14, 334336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E. J. 2015. Layered view of shape perception. British Journal of Philosophy of Science 68, 355387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E. J. 2016. Representationalism and perceptual organization. Philosophical Topics 44, 121148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E. J. 2017. Attentive visual reference. Mind & Language 32, 328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E. J. 2018. What do object files pick out? Philosophy of Science 85, 177200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E. J. 2019. On the perception of structure. NOUS 53, 564592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, S. and Batterman, R.. 2017. Biology meets physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 61, 2034.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greenfield, S. A. and Collins, T. F. T.. 2005. A neuroscientific approach to consciousness. Progress in Brain Research 150, 1123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Griffiths, P. 2001. Genetic information: a metaphor in search of a theory. Philosophy of Science 68, 394412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. and Stolz, K.. 2007. Gene. In Hull, D. and Ruse, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to The Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 85102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groh, J. M. 2014. Making Space. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grush, R. 2007a. Berkeley and the spatiality of vision. Journal of the History of Philosophy 43, 413442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grush, R. 2007b. Skill theory v2.0: dispositions, emulation, and spatial perception. Synthese 159, 5992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C. L. 1993. Color for Philosophers, expanded edition. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hardin, C. L. 1997. Reinverting the spectrum. In Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D. (eds.), Readings on Color, Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 289301.Google Scholar
Hardin, C. L. 2014. More color science for philosophers. In Stokes, D., Matthen, M., and Biggs, S. (eds.), Perception and Its Modalities. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 379389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1973. Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. The intrinsic quality of experience. In Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. IV. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing, 3152.Google Scholar
Harold, F. M. 2001. The Way of the Cell. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, C. 1965. Perceptual adaptation to inverted, reversed, and displaced vision. Psychological Review 72, 419444.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harris, C. 1980. Insight or out of sight?: two examples of perceptual plasticity in the human adult. In Harris, C. (ed.), Visual Coding and Adaptability. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 95149.Google Scholar
Harrison, B. 1973. Form and Content. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Harrison, B. 1986. Identity, predication, and color. American Philosophical Quarterly 23, 105114.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. and Epstein, W.. 1979. The sensory core and the medieval foundations of early modern perceptual theory. ISIS 70, 363384.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heidegger, M. 1962. Being and Time, Macquarrie, J. and Robinson, E. (trans.). New York: Harper & Rowe.Google Scholar
Helmholtz, H. 1954. On the Sensations of Tone, Ellis, A. J. (trans.), second edition. Mineola, NY: Dover.Google Scholar
Henry, M. 1975. Philosophy and Phenomenology of the Body, Etzkorn, G. (trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbert, D. 1987. Color and Color Perception. Stanford, CA: CSLI.Google Scholar
Hill, C. 1997. Imaginability, conceivability, possibility, and the mind-body problem. Philosophical Studies 87, 6185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, C. 2009. Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, C. 2015. Review of The Peripheral Mind. Mind 124, 312317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, J. A. 1988. The Dreaming Brain. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Holcombe, A. O. 2014. Are there cracks in the façade of continuous visual experience? In Arstila, V. and Lloyd, D. (eds.), Subjective Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 179198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J.. 2002. The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind. New York: Oxford University Press, 520533.Google Scholar
Howard, I. P., Craske, B., and Templeton, W. B.. 1965. Visuomotor adaptation to discordant exafferent stimulation. Journal of Experimental Psychology 70, 189191.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Howard, J. D., Plailly, J., Grueschow, M., Haynes, J.-D., and Gottfried, J. A.. 2009. Odor quality coding and categorization in human posterior piriform cortex. Nature Neuroscience 12, 932939.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howe, C. Q. and Purves, D.. 2005. Perceiving Geometry. New York: Springer.Google ScholarPubMed
Hubel, D. 1995. Eye, Brain, and Vision. New York: Scientific American Books.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. 1998. Consciousness in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. 2007. Neural dominance, neural deference, and sensorimotor dynamics. In Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell, 640656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. 1991. On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time, Brough, J. (trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1975. On the adverbial analysis of visual experience. Metaphilosophy 6, 127135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1977. Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 32, 127136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeannerod, M. 1997. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Action. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Science.Google Scholar
Jekely, G., Keijzer, F., and Godfrey-Smith, P.. 2015. An option space for early neural evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series B, Biological Science 370, 1684.Google ScholarPubMed
Joesch, M. and Meister, M.. 2016. A neuronal circuitry for colour vision based on rod-cone opponency. Nature 532, 236239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, P. K. and Boynton, R. M.. 1996. Human Color Vision, second edition. Washington, DC: Optical Society of America.Google Scholar
Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J., Jessell, T., Siegelbaum, E., and Hudspeth, A. J.. 2013. Principles of Neural Science, fifth edition. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. 2000. Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, E. F. 2000. The Century of the Gene. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, E. F. 2002. Making Sense of Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, J. M. 1993. Drawing and the Blind. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Kennedy, J. M. 1997. How the blind draw. Scientific American 289, 7681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kepple, D. and Koulakov, A.. 2017. Constructing an olfactory perceptual space and predicting percepts from molecular structure. arXiv 1708.05774. http://doi.org/10.48550/arKiv.1708.05574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 2011. Philosophy of Mind, third edition. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Kind, A. 2018. Imaginative presence. In Dorsch, F. and Macpherson, F. (eds.), Phenomenal Presence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 165180.Google Scholar
Kind, A. 2020. Imaginative experience. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 124141.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 1974. Zombies vs. materialists. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 48, 135152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knill, D. and Richards, W.. 1996. Perception as Bayesian Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koch, C. 2004. The Quest for Consciousness. Englewood, CO: Roberts.Google Scholar
Kohler, I. 1964. Formation and transformation of the perceptual world. Psychological Issues 3, 1173.Google Scholar
Kohlers, P. A. and von Grünau, M.. 1976. Shape and color in apparent motion. Vision Research 16, 329335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koulakov, A., Kolterman, B., Enikolopov, A., and Rinberg, D.. 2011. In search of the structure of human olfactory space. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience 5, 18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kriegel, U. 2009. Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kroon, F. 2013. Phenomenal intentionality and the role of intentional objects. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 137155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuehni, R. G. 2010. Color spaces and color order systems: a primer. In Cohen, J. and Matthen, M. (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langers, D., van Dijk, P., Schoenmaker, E., and Backes, W.. 2007. fMRI activation in relation to sound intensity and loudness. NeuroImage 35, 709718.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laurent, G. 1999. A systems perspective on early olfactory coding. Science 286, 723728.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, A. Y. 2023. Degrees of consciousness. NOUS 57, 553575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, G. 2006. The experience of left and right. In Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 292315.Google Scholar
Lee, G. 2007. Consciousness in a space-time world. Philosophical Perspectives 21, 341374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, G. 2014a. Experiences and their parts. In Bennett, D. and Hill, C. (eds.), Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 287321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, G. 2014b. Temporal experience and the temporal structure of experience. Philosopher’s Imprint 14, 121.Google Scholar
Lee, G. 2015. Review of The Conscious Brain. Philosophical Review 124, 163167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leng, G. 2018. The Heart of the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J. 1983. Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64, 354361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J. 2001. Purple Haze. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J. 2010. Review of Kriegel, Subjective Consciousness. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, https://ndpr.nd.edu, 2010.03.14.Google Scholar
Lewens, T. 2007. Adaptation. In Hull, D. and Ruse, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 121.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1975. Languages and language. In Gunderson, K. (ed.), Mind and Knowledge. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 335.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Liberman, A. M. 1996. Speech: A Special Code. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Loar, B. 1990. Phenomenal states. Philosophical Perspectives 4, 81108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockwood, M. 1989. Mind, Brain, and the Quantum. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Loebrich, S. and Nedivi, E.. 2009. The function of activity-regulated genes in the nervous system. Physiological Review 89, 10791103.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Loewenstein, W. 1999. The Touchstone of Life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 2004. The superiority of HOP to HOT. In Gennaro, R. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 115136.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 2020. Hearing As. In Brogaard, B. and Gatzia, D. E. (eds.), The Epistemology of Non-Visual Perception. New York: Oxford University Press, 118145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, W. 1986. The Disappearance of Introspection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., and Craver, C.. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67, 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mack, A. and Rock, I.. 1998. Inattentional Blindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maclachlan, D. L. C. 1989. Philosophy of Perception. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
MacLeod, D. 2010. Into the neural maze. In Cohen, J. and Matthen, M. (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 151178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marks, C. 1981. Commissurotomy, Consciousness, and Unity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. 1982. Vision. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Martin, M. G. F. 1997. Self-observation. European Journal of Philosophy 5, 119140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masrour, F. 2013. Phenomenal objectivity and phenomenal intentionality. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford University Press, 116136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masrour, F. 2015. The geometry of visual space and the nature of visual experience. Philosophical Studies 172, 18131832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masrour, F. 2016. Space perception, visual dissonance, and the fate of standard representationalism. NOUS 50, 565593.Google Scholar
Masrour, F. 2020. The phenomenal unity of consciousness. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 208229.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. 2005. Seeing, Doing, and Knowing. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mauk, M. and Buonomano, D.. 2004. The neural basis of temporal processing. Annual Review of Neuroscience 27, 307330.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McClelland, T. 2020. Self-representationalist theories of consciousness. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 458481.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McGovern, K. and Baars, B. J.. 2007. Cognitive theories of consciousness. In Zelazo, P., Moscovitch, M., and Thompson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 177205.Google Scholar
McGurk, H. and MacDonald, J.. 1976. Hearing lips and seeing voices. Nature 264, 746748.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meinong, A. 1960. The theory of objects, Levi, I., Terrell, D. B., and Chisholm, R. (trans.). In Chisholm, R. (ed.), Realism and the Background of Phenomenology. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 76117.Google Scholar
Mel, B. W. 1986. A connectionist learning model for 3-dimensional mental rotation, zoom, and pan. In Proceedings of the Eighth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 562571.Google Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2018. The Phenomenal Basis of Intentionality. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2020. How reliably misrepresenting olfactory experiences justify true beliefs. In Brogaard, B. and Gatzia, D. (eds.), The Epistemology of Non-Visual Perception. New York: Oxford University Press, 99117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendelovici, A. and Bourget, D.. 2020. Consciousness and intentionality. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 560885.Google Scholar
Mendola, J. 1997. Human Thought. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendola, J. 2006. Goodness and Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendola, J. 2008. Anti-Externalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendola, J. 2014. Human Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendola, J. 2021. Experience and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merino-Rajme, C. 2014. A quantum of felt duration. Analytic Philosophy 55, 239275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, D. and Goodale, M. A.. 2008. Two visual systems reviewed. Neuropsychologia 46, 774785.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mitrani, L., Shekerdjiiski, S., and Yakimoff, N.. 1986. Mechanisms and asymmetries in visual perception of simultaneity and temporal order. Biological Cybernetics 54, 159165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mojet, J., Köster, E. P., and Prinz, J. F.. 2005. Do tastants have a smell? Chemical Senses 30, 921.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mölder, B. 2014. Constructing time: Dennett and Grush on temporal representation. In Arstila, V. and Lloyd, D. (eds.), Subjective Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 217238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mole, C. 2020. Consciousness and attention. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 499537.Google Scholar
Mollon, J. D. 2009. A neural basis for unique hues? Current Biology 19, R441R442.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mollon, J. D. 2012. The origins of modern color science. In Shevell, S. (ed.), The Science of Color, second edition. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 139.Google Scholar
Montemayor, C. and Haladjian, H. H.. 2015. Consciousness, Attention, and Conscious Attention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, C. I. and Cao, R.. 2008. The hemo-neural hypothesis: on the role of blood flow in information processing. Journal of Neurophysiology 99, 20352047.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moore, P. B. 2012. How should we think about the ribosome? Annual Review of Biophysics 41, 119.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morales, J. and Lau, H.. 2020. The neural correlates of consciousness. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 233260.Google Scholar
Murphy, A. C., Muldoon, S., Baker, D., et al. 2018. Structure, function, and control of the human musculoskeletal network. PLoS Biology 16, e22002811.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83, 435450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 2002. The psychophysical nexus. In Nagel, T. (ed.), Concealment and Exposure. New York: Oxford University Press, 194236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, L. K. 1974. Elements of Statistical Thermodynamics, second edition. New York: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Neander, K. 2017. A Mark of the Mental. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, B. R. and Shanks, D. R.. 2014. Unconscious influences on decision making: A critical review, with critical discussion. Behavior and Brain Sciences 37, 161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nida-Rümelin, M. 1993. Pseudonormal vision. Philosophical Studies 82, 145157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nida-Rümelin, M. 1998. On belief about experiences. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58, 5173.Google Scholar
Noble, D. 2008. Genes and causation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A 366, 30013015.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Noble, D. 2012. A theory of biological relativity: no privileged level of causation. Interface Focus 2, 5564.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Noë, A. 2005. Real presence. Philosophical Topics 33, 235264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noë, A. 2006. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Noë, A. 2012. Varieties of Presence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northoff, G. 2023. Neurowaves. Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press.Google Scholar
Northoff, G. and Heiss, W.-D.. 2015. Why is the distinction between neural predispositions, prerequisites, and correlates of level of consciousness clinically relevant? Stroke 46, 11471151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northoff, G. and Zilio, F.. 2022. Temporo-spatial theory of consciousness (TTC). Behavioural Brain Research 424, 113788.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nusbaum, N., Blitz, D., and Marder, E.. 2017. Functional consequences of neuropeptide and small-molecule co-transmission. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 18, 389403.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Callaghan, C. 2007. Sounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Callaghan, C. 2015. Speech perception. In Matthen, M. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475494.Google Scholar
O’Callaghan, C. 2019. A Multisensory Theory of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1925.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., and Tononi, G.. 2014. From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: integrated information theory 3.0. PLoS Computational Biology 10, e1003588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Regan, J. K. 2011. Why Red Doesn’t Sound Like a Bell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Orlandi, N. 2013. Embedded seeing: vision in the natural world. NOUS 47, 727747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Orlandi, N. 2014. The Innocent Eye: Why Vision Is Not a Cognitive Process. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Shea, M. 2005. The Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Palmer, S. E. 1999. Vision Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 2002. Thinking About Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 2021. The Metaphysics of Sensory Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parkes, L. M., Marsman, J.-B., Oxley, D., Goulermas, J., and Wuerger, S.. 2009. Multivoxel fMRI analysis of color tuning in human primary visual cortex. Journal of Vision 9, 113.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Parsons, T. 1980. Nonexistent Objects. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Pautz, A. 2006. Sensory awareness is not a wide physical relation. NOUS 40, 205240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pautz, A. 2010. A simple view of consciousness. In Bealer, G. and Koons, R. (eds.), The Waning of Materialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pautz, A. 2013. The real trouble for phenomenal externalists: new empirical evidence for a brain-based theory of consciousness. In Brown, R. (ed.), Consciousness Inside and Out: Phenomenology, Neuroscience, and the Nature of Experience. Dordrecht: Springer, 237298.Google Scholar
Pautz, A. 2020. Representationalism about consciousness. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 405437.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1983. Sense and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, H. 2006. What is a gene? Nature 441, 399401.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peirce, C. S. 1982. Lowell lectures. In Fisch, M. H. (ed.), Writings of Charles S. Peirce. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 358504.Google Scholar
Pelczar, M. 2010. Presentism, eternalism, and phenomenal change. Synthese 176, 275290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penrose, R. 2005. The Road to Reality. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Perkins, M. 1983. Sensing the World. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Phillips, I. 2016. Consciousness and criterion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93, 419451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piantanida, P. 2010. Letter. Scientific American 303, 68.Google Scholar
Pitt, D. 2004. The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that P?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69, 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. 2012. The Conscious Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, P. 2001. Visual indexes, preconceptual objects, and situated vision. Cognition 80, 127158.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Quiroga, R. Q., Reddy, L., Kreiman, G., Koch, C., and Fried, I.. 2005. Invariant visual representation by single neurons in the human brain. Nature 435, 11021107.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rassoulzadegan, M., Grandjean, V., Gounon, P., et al. 2006. RNA-mediated non-mendelian inheritance of an epigenetic change in the mouse. Nature 441, 469474.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Recanati, F. 2012. Mental Files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Relkin, E. M. and Doucet, J. R.. 1997. Is loudness simply proportional to the auditory nerve spike count? Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 101, 27352740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Remez, R. E. and Trout, J. D.. 2009. Philosophical messages in the medium of spoken language. In Nudds, M. and O’Callaghan, C. (eds.), Sounds and Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 234264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rescorla, M. 2015. Bayesian perceptual psychology. In Matthen, M. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 694716.Google Scholar
Rescorla, M. 2016. Bayesian sensorimotor psychology. Mind & Language 31, 336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 2016. From the Knowledge Argument to Mental Substance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rock, I. 1966. The Nature of Perceptual Adaptation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Roelofs, L. 2019. Combining Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rojahn, S. Y. 2013. What it’s like to see again with an artificial retina. www.technologyreview.com/s/514081/can-artificial-retinas-restore-natural-sightGoogle Scholar
Röhl, M. B., Kollmeier, B., and Uppenkamp, S.. 2011. Spectral loudness summation takes place in the primary auditory cortex. Human Brain Mapping 32, 14831496.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rolls, E. T. 2007. The affective neuroscience of consciousness. In Zelazo, P. D., Moscovitch, M., and Thompson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 831859.Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, D. A. 1991. Human Motor Control. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, D. M. 2005. Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1905. On denoting. Mind 14, 479493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. and Tye, M.. 2012. Seven Puzzles of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sakurai, T., Misaka, T., Ueno, Y., et al. 2010. The human bitter taste receptor, hTAS2R16, discriminates slight differences in the configuration of disaccharides. Biochemical and Biophysics Research Communication 402, 595601.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sarkar, S. 1996. Decoding “coding” – information and DNA. BioScience 46, 857864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sasaki, T., Beppu, K., Tanaka, K., et al. 2012. Application of an optogenetic byway for perturbing neural activity via glial photostimulation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 109, 2072020725.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schechter, E. 2014. Partial unity of consciousness: a preliminary defense. In Bennett, D. and Hill, C. (eds.), Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 347373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnupp, J., King, A., Walter, K., and Bizley, J.. 2010. The representation of the pitch of vowel sounds in ferret auditory cortex. In Lopez, E. A., Palmer, A. R., and Meddis, R. (eds.), Advances in Auditory Physiology, Psychophysics and Models. New York: Springer, 407416.Google Scholar
Schnupp, J., Nelken, I., and King, A.. 2011. Auditory Neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Schrödinger, E. 1967. What Is Life? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scott, J. D. and Pawson, T.. 2000. Cell communication: the inside story. Scientific American 313, 7279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seager, W. 2016. Theories of Consciousness, second edition. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. 1991. Response. In Lepore, E. and Van Gulick, R. (eds.), John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 181192.Google Scholar
Shannon, C. 1948. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Systems Technical Journal 27, 279423 and 623–656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepard, R. N. and Chipman, S.. 1970. Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology 1, 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2006. Which properties are represented in perception? In Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Perceptual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press, 481503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2010. The Contents of Visual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Simons, D. and Chabris, C.. 1999. Gorillas in our midst: sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception 28, 10591074.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sinha, P., Wulff, J., and Held, R.. 2014. Establishing cross-modal mappings: empirical and computational investigations. In Bennett, D. and Hill, C. (eds.), Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 171191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sjovall, B. 1967. Psychology of Tension. Norstedts: Svenska Bokforlaget.Google Scholar
Skillings, D. J. 2015. Mechanistic explanation of biological processes. Philosophy of Science 82, 11391151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sklar, L. 1993. Physics and Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, B. 2015. The chemical senses. In Matthen, M. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. New York: Oxford University Press, 314352.Google Scholar
Smith, B. 2020. Tasting flavors. In Brogaard, B. and Gatzia, D. (eds.), The Epistemology of Non-Visual Perception. New York: Oxford University Press, 2952.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, D. V., Van Buskirk, R. L., Travers, J. B., and Bieber, S. L.. 1983. Coding of taste stimuli by hamster brain stem neurons. Journal of Neurophysiology 50, 541558.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. 1984. The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 1994. Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, second edition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, S. G. and Lennie, P.. 2007. The machinery of color vision. Nature, Reviews Neuro 8, 276286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soloway, P. D. 2006. Paramutable possibilities. Nature 441, 413414.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spence, C., Auvray, M., and Smith, B.. 2014. Confusing tastes with flavours. In Stokes, D., Matthen, M., and Biggs, S. (eds.), Perception and Its Modalities. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 247274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spinney, L. 2011. You smell flowers, I smell stale urine. Scientific American 324, 26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spivey, M. 2007. The Continuity of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Squire, L. R. 1987. Memory and Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1976. Possible worlds. NOUS 10, 6575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stockman, A., MacLeod, D., and Johnson, N.. 1993. Spectral sensitivities of the human cones. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, Optics, Image Science, and Vision 10, 24912521.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stoughton, C. M. and Conway, B. R.. 2008. Neural basis for unique hues. Current Biology 18, R698R699.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stratton, G. M. 1896. Some preliminary experiments on vision without inversion of the retinal image. Psychological Review 3, 611617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stratton, G. M. 1897. Vision without inversion of the retinal image. Psychological Review 4, 341360 and 463–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G. 2006. Realistic monism: why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 331.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1966. The Bounds of Sense. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Sundström, P. 2020. Visual experience. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3965.Google Scholar
Tailby, A., Solomon, S. G., and Lennie, P.. 2008. Functional asymmetries in visual pathways carrying S-cone signals in macaque. Journal of Neuroscience 28, 40784087.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Taylor, J. G. 1962. The Behavioral Basis of Perception. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Teller, D. 2003. Color: a vision scientist’s perspective. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26, 4849.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, B. 2010. The spatial content of experience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81, 146184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tjian, R. 1995. Molecular machines that control genes. Scientific American 308, 5461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tononi, G. 2007. The information integration theory of consciousness. In Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell, 287299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tononi, G. 2008. Consciousness as integrated information. Biological Bulletin 215, 216242.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tononi, G. and Koch, C.. 2015. Consciousness: here, there and everywhere? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 370, 20140167.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trestman, M. 2013. The Cambrian explosion and the origins of embodied cognition. Biological Theory 8, 8092.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trestman, M. 2014. The modal breadth of consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 27, 843861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trout, J. D. 2001. The biological basis of speech. Psychological Review 108, 523549CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trout, J. D. 2016. Wondrous Truths. New York: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turin, L. and Sanchez, T.. 2008. Perfumes, the A–Z Guide. London: Profile.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995a. A representational theory of pains and their phenomenal character. Philosophical Perspectives 9, 223239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 1995b. Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2003. Consciousness and Persons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2009. Consciousness Revisited. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 2017. Tense Bees and Shell-Shocked Crabs. New York: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2021. Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valberg, A. 2001. Unique hues: an old problem for a new generation. Vision Research 41, 16451657.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van Cleve, J. 2014. Berkeley, Reid, and Sinha on Molyneux’s question. In Bennett, D. and Hill, C. (eds.), Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 193208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gelder, T. J. 1995. What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy 92, 345381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gelder, T. J. 1998. The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science, with commentaries. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21, 615665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gulick, R. 2007. What if phenomenal consciousness admits of degrees? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30, 528529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Ness, H. C. 1969. Understanding Thermodynamics. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E.. 1991. The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, M. 2006. The Geometries of Visual Space. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Walters, D. 1996. How are bitter and sweet related? Trends in Food Science and Technology 7, 399403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiskrantz, L. 1986. Blindsight. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weng, G., Bhalla, U. S., and Iyengar, R.. 1999. Complexity in biological signaling systems. Science 284, 9295.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Werblin, F. and Roska, B.. 2007. The movies in our eyes. Scientific American 320, 7278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, S. L. 1986. The curse of the qualia. Synthese 86, 333368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, S. L. 2010. The property dualism argument. In Koons, R. and Bealer, G. (eds.), The Waning of Materialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 89113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. 1988. Real People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. A. and Stevenson, R. J.. 2006. Learning to Smell. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiltshire, J. 2014. The Hidden Jane Austen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoshioka, T., Dow, B. M., and Vautin, R. G.. 1996. Neural mechanisms of color categorization in areas V1, V2, and V4 of macaque monkey cortex. Behavioral Brain Research 76, 5170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, B. D., Keller, A., and Rosenthal, D.. 2014. Quality-space theory in olfaction. Frontiers in Psychology 5, 1.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zwicher, E. and Fastl, H. 2006. Psychoacoustics, third edition. New York: Springer.Google Scholar

Accessibility standard: Unknown

Accessibility compliance for the PDF of this book is currently unknown and may be updated in the future.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Joseph Mendola, University of Nebraska, Lincoln
  • Book: The Neural Structure of Consciousness
  • Online publication: 27 July 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009514774.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Joseph Mendola, University of Nebraska, Lincoln
  • Book: The Neural Structure of Consciousness
  • Online publication: 27 July 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009514774.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Joseph Mendola, University of Nebraska, Lincoln
  • Book: The Neural Structure of Consciousness
  • Online publication: 27 July 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009514774.009
Available formats
×