We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Christian August Crusius (1715–1775) was one of the most important German philosophers in the middle of the eighteenth century. His series of four German textbooks offered a systematic and sophisticated alternative to Wolffianism. Kant was at the beginning of his academic career when Crusius’ philosophical works were first published, so it is not surprising that Kant would come to be influenced by Crusius’ philosophy. This chapter contains a translation of selections from books 1 and 2 of Crusius’ Guide to Living Rationally (1744), capturing his theory of the will and desire, his theory of freedom, his voluntarist theory of ethics, his theory of the end of human life, and his moral proof of the immortality of the soul. The selections will help readers better understand Kant’s reference to Crusius’ moral philosophy as one based on the “will of God” (5:40), among many other things.
One of the arguments for which Immanuel Kant is best known is the moral proof of the existence of God, freedom, and the immortal soul. It is surprising that Kant gives hope, rather than belief, pride of place in the list of questions that motivate his entire critical philosophy. Commentators typically neglect the distinct nature and role of hope in Kant's system, and lump it together with the sort of belief that arises from the moral proof. A crucial difference between knowledge, rational belief, and rational hope is that they are governed by different modal constraints; the author discusses those constraints and the kind of modality involved. He offers what he takes to be Kant's account of the main objects of rational hope in that text, namely, alleged outer experiences (miracles); a supposed inner experience (effect of grace); and a future collective experience (the construction of a truly ethical society).
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.