We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Here, the authors present two justifications usually cited as sufficient to warrant patients‘ trust in physicians: professional status and individual merit. Whereas in ‘status trust’ professionalism is taken as a guarantor of trustworthiness, in ‘merit trust’ a physician’s trustworthiness is assessed individually. On either account, trust is justified by the physician’s professionalism. ‘Professionalism’ may be defined as ‘acting trustworthily’ in exchange for autonomy of decision-making, whereas trustworthiness refers to ‘competence’ in terms of episteme (theoretical knowledge), techne (craft or skill), and phronesis (practical knowledge or experience), and ‘commitment’ as ‘to act in a way that the truster approves’. The authors argue that although in principle trust in physicians is justified, since both professionalism and individually assessed trustworthiness grant derivative authority, the reality is different. because an increasing number of patients reject the concept of professionalism and, accordingly, find it difficult (or even impossible) to assess physicians’ trustworthiness. Hence, they no longer believe that their trust in physicians is justified.
Since to trust implies to run a risk, you may want to make sure your trust is justified before you decide to trust someone. In this chapter, the authors examine the justification of trust in the information we receive from others (epistemic trust). They stipulate that only information which is relevant to the receiver counts as testimony. Contrary to this, irrelevant information, arguments, and the provision of pieces of evidence do not count as testimony. By resorting to the concept of street-level epistemology, that is, by shifting from the truth content of a statement to the content relevance (i.e. relevance to the receiver of the information), it is possible to justify epistemic trust. Between the extreme positions of complete rejection and almost a priori acceptance of epistemic trust, the authors argue that it is responsible to grant derivative authority, i.e. to accept testimony to p if and only if we have sufficient reason to believe that p. To determine what counts as ‘sufficient reason’ they present two strategies: ‘epistemic vigilance’ and assessing the ‘epistemic trustworthiness’ of the trustee.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.