We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
This chapter analyzes the key notion of the “human act” (actus humanus) around which Aquinas’s action theory revolves. It argues that, for Aquinas, the general term ‘act’ is used broadly to denote any power-exercise in nature, whether in the animate or the inanimate domain. Given this broad scope of the term ‘act,’ the chapter considers, in a next step, what sets human acts apart from other power-exercises. It argues that, according to Aquinas, one differentiating feature is that a human act is a hylomophically organized composite of two power-exercises, where a volition that he refers to as “use” is the formal component and a power-exercise caused by volition that he refers to as the “commanded act” is the material component. However, as the chapter also shows, Aquinas chiefly relies on an aetiological criterion to differentiate human acts from other power-exercises, arguing that a human act is explained by a preceding act of free choice. It then shows that choice likewise displays a hylomorphic structure, for Aquinas. It is a volition materially speaking, and its form is the preferential character that this volition inherits from a preceding judgment that Aquinas refers to as the “judgment of choice.”
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.