With Tertullian, we find another complex account of catechetical knowledge, one both idiosyncratic and yet recognizable within the scope of late second-century Christianity. Though our knowledge of Tertullian’s catechesis, like Irenaeus’s, must remain circumspect, we have at least three texts – De baptismo, De spectaculis, and De paenitentia – in which he mentions catechumens or those “approaching baptism” as members of his audience. De oratione, too, has also been included among possibly catechetical texts.Footnote 1 Finally, Tertullian is, like Irenaeus, a key witness to the Rule of Faith in early Christianity, and here again we find suggestive ways in which the Rule might have functioned in catechetical settings.
In observing these texts, one is struck by the importance that ritual plays in Tertullian’s approach to shaping knowledge. When addressing catechumens and the newly baptized, Tertullian highlights the simplicity of material rituals and practices as commensurate with the kind of divine power that engenders spiritual knowledge. While pagan and heretical rites distract and obscure, participation in orthodox Christian rituals brings cognitive and spiritual illumination and union with God. In Tertullian’s catechetical writings, we learn not only about theological polemics but also about the correlations between epistemology and pedagogy taking place in a ritual initiation. Tertullian offers catechumens instruction on the meaning of participation in core rituals, arguing that divine power is made especially manifest through the simple rituals and moral purity attendant in orthodox Christian baptism.Footnote 2
This chapter will begin by reconstructing what we can of the North African catechumenate in Tertullian’s period. Next, it will peruse De spectaculis, De baptismo, and De oratione to tease out Tertullian’s epistemology of ritual simplicity, with an excursus on the important issue of delaying baptism. Finally, I analyze two of Tertullian’s appeals to the Rule of Faith to explore the connections between knowledge and ritual participation. Although Tertullian’s catechesis is multi-faceted and motivated by several overlapping concerns, a guiding thread is to teach catechumens that the simple practices of Christian ritual can become trustworthy pathways to divine knowledge.
The Catechumenate in Tertullian’s North Africa
While sources are too limited to construct an indubitable picture of the catechumenate in North Africa prior to Constantine, at least based solely on North African sources,Footnote 3 we can surmise that some formalized structure existed by the end of the second century, and certainly by the mid third century.Footnote 4 Though evidence is sketchier here than for later periods, we can conclude that catechesis was a visible practice by this time. In Tertullian’s writing, as well as the Passio Perpetuae, we find the Greek term catechumenus used in a technical sense to designate those affiliated with Christianity but distinct from the baptized.Footnote 5 Tertullian describes members in this class as audientes (paen. 6.15, 17), nouitioli (paen. 6.1), tirocinia (paen. 6.14), and, more generally, those who are “under instruction” (formantur; bapt. 1.1) or “proceeding” to faith/God (idol. 24; spect. 1.1).Footnote 6 The Passio refers to those arrested as “young catechumens” (adolescentes catechumeni) with a clear sense that this term located them within the Christian community though distinct from the baptized.Footnote 7 It is unclear whether Tertullian himself considered catechumens fully Christian.Footnote 8 We should not suppose that a strict disciplina arcani was in place during his time, with clear regulations, for example, about whether teaching the Lord’s Prayer, eucharist, or baptism should be withheld from the non-baptized. Tertullian both appears to teach non-baptized persons about what should be “inner” Christian doctrine, even as he criticizes heretics for indiscriminately allowing nonbelievers access to intra-Christian rituals.Footnote 9 Tertullian, famously, is an exceedingly difficult writer to pin down; he can make what appears to be contradictory statements depending on his audience and rhetorical purposes.
Teaching, it seems, could be administered by either ordained or lay persons and took place probably in homes during the Agape meal. Saturus, the teacher of Perpetua and her friends, was likely a lay person.Footnote 10 Tertullian’s own ecclesiastical status is, it should be noted, a source of no little puzzlement. Jerome’s comment that he was a presbyter is mostly rejected; Tertullian himself never claims as much.Footnote 11 He was perhaps one of the seniores laici, a somewhat unique status among North African churches – a kind of lay elder, not ordained but tasked with either patronal or disciplinary duties, including teaching.Footnote 12 If a lay member, then perhaps, like Justin Martyr but in an African context, he operated as a revered teacher within a larger ecclesial community. In terms of the setting for such teaching, Timothy Barnes has proposed the “love feast” described in Apologeticum 39, where Tertullian depicts a temperate meal, the reading of sacred texts, and times for exhortation and admonition.Footnote 13
No Roman North African writings in the pre-Constantinian era mention a specific length of time a person was to remain a catechumen. The common assumption of a three-year catechumenate comes only from sources elsewhere – namely, the Traditio apostolica, the canons of the Council of Elvira, and two potential but oblique references in Clement and Origen of Alexandria.Footnote 14 Tertullian argued against the hasty reception of baptism, of course, though the host of biblical arguments he is compelled to refute suggest that it was a contested practice among Christians.Footnote 15 Megan Devore has argued that the catechumens described in the Passio Perpetuae were not “new converts” but well-taught and committed disciples capable of making articulate declarations of the faith.Footnote 16 Nevertheless, there are no clear prescriptions or examples by which to ascertain the average duration of the North African catechumenate.
When we consider the rites of initiation, we have slightly better evidence. Our best aids are two passages from Tertullian, De baptismo 20 and De corona 3, along with a few other scattered references.Footnote 17 Tertullian mentions Easter as the preferred date for baptism,Footnote 18 and he describes a multi-stage process including the renunciation of Satan (one of the earliest records of this practice),Footnote 19 a threefold profession of faith in the waters,Footnote 20 a post-baptismal anointing and benediction,Footnote 21 reception of the eucharist (which included milk and honey),Footnote 22 and a prayer among the faithful.Footnote 23 Evidence from the Passio is more circumspect, but some scholars have noticed parallels between its literary account of martyrdom and baptismal initiation.Footnote 24 Perpetua’s invocation of Christ against Satan models the renunciation of Satan in baptism, while her exchanges with Saturus echo certain liturgical formulas.Footnote 25 Her reception of “cheese” perhaps alludes to eucharistic participation.Footnote 26 It is not clear to what extent the Lord’s Prayer was part of initiation at this point (as it would be, say, in Augustine’s time). However, it has been suggested that a baptismal setting for the Lord’s Prayer was emerging and that Tertullian’s treatise on the Lord’s Prayer perhaps originated here.Footnote 27
Many aspects of the early North African catechumenate remain uncertain. We will see certain developments by Cyprian’s bishopric in the next generation (discussed in more detail in Chapter 5), especially a growing focus on the role of the bishop in administering baptism. With Tertullian, though, our reconstruction must remain inconclusive: We can affirm that there was such a teaching practice in place, and that there was a growing need to clarify the rules and teachings appropriate for pre-baptismal candidates. In what remains, I will try to articulate Tertullian’s ritual-based epistemology of simplicity to understand this key moment in the development of early Christian catechesis.
Simplicity and the Doctrine of Creation in De spectaculis
De spectaculis was one of Tertullian’s earliest treatises, and it was addressed to both catechumens and the newly baptized.Footnote 28 In it, Tertullian’s main task is to persuade Christians that they should avoid participation in the shows, or “spectacles” – a major contested issue in early Christianity.Footnote 29 For our purposes, the most interesting aspect of this text is how Tertullian addresses the issue of participation in the spectacles as it relates to knowledge of God. Within his argument, Tertullian charts a path by which Christians hold together commitments both to the goodness of creation and to the obfuscation of rituals by demonic powers. Tertullian stresses that Christian truth is rendered visible through Christian rites, which are manifest and simple – not hidden in secrecy – and yet the perception of the truth found in the rituals is prone to distortion by demons.Footnote 30 De spectaculis thus offers catechumens a primer on how to understand God amid the conditions of the created world, which is both good but prone to distortion. As Christians participate in the rituals of the church, they are led to a proper understanding of divine truth and guided in a proper mode of action in the world.
In the exordium, Tertullian announces that he will respond to two kinds of arguments – one pagan and one Christian.Footnote 31 It is the former that likely would have held more sway among catechumens, and so I will focus on those arguments here. Pagans might argue, Tertullian writes, that the spectacles are merely bodily or sensory activities – not religious ones. They are pleasures of the eyes and ears but not the mind. Similarly, pagans might argue that attending the spectacles was acceptable if one continued to fear God. Finally, they could argue that if all things were created by a good God, as Christians teach, participation in the shows should not be illegitimate since these activities all involve created goods – the horse, the lion, the human body, the melodious voice. There is, therefore, no reason that Christians should oppose the spectacles.Footnote 32 Tertullian responds to these arguments by explicating the key differences between Christian and non-Christian knowledge, the fulcrum of which is baptism. Baptismal knowledge enables Christians to perceive God more clearly, which is also related to their better understanding of the origins and purposes of creation.
Tertullian makes clear that pagan practices like the spectacles do not indict the goodness of God or his creation. In fact, by discerning patterns in nature, even non-Christians can come to the knowledge that there is, for instance, only one God who is creator of all, which implies that creation is fundamentally good. However, there is a difference, explains Tertullian, between knowing God by laws of nature and knowing God by the more intimate knowledge afforded to Christians who know God as children through baptism.Footnote 33 Because of the more distant form of knowing God by laws of nature, pagans are ignorant of creation’s proper uses and the ways that demonic forces have perverted them. Christians, on the other hand, are privy to a kind of familial knowledge that comes through the adopted sonship of baptism. Such knowledge assumes the knowledge of God by laws of nature but also goes beyond them. In particular, the familial knowledge afforded in baptism allows Christians to know God as a father rather than only as a creator. Moreover, knowing God as father also affords Christians the knowledge of creation’s purposes and their susceptibility to demonic misuse. Through this kind of knowledge, Christians can maintain both the integral goodness of God’s creation while also affirming the demonic deception that generated the spectacles in the first place.
Tertullian’s rationale for avoiding the shows bears closely upon a theological epistemology attached to the ritual of baptism. Tertullian grounds his rejection of the shows by demonstrating how ritual knowledge instills true knowledge of God, who can be glimpsed but not fully grasped through natural laws but who requires baptism to be known more intimately. In view of the non-baptized members of Tertullian’s audience in this text, we can observe the way he takes this opportunity to teach them not only about the shows but also about the kind of knowledge attained through baptism.
In Praise of Water: Simplicity and Power in De baptismo
De baptismo provides another example of Tertullian’s ritual epistemology in catechesis.Footnote 34 While this work has attracted interest for understanding early Christian baptism, it also holds promise for analyzing Tertullian’s approach to knowledge. Against certain heretical groups that would reject the use of water in baptism, Tertullian provides a panegyric on water that articulates ordinary rituals as fitting and powerful means for expressing divine power.
Like De spectaculis, the addressees of De baptismo include but are not limited to baptismal candidates.Footnote 35 Tertullian’s point of departure is the teaching of a female leader of the “Cainite heresy,”Footnote 36 whose rejection of water baptisms have, according to Tertullian, led many Christians astray. We know very little about the Cainites apart from polemical sources.Footnote 37 While, as we saw in Chapter 1, reflection on the interplay between material symbols and spiritual potency in baptism were contested issues in this period, few Christian groups actually rejected such rites altogether. The Cainites, however, were a possible exception. In De baptismo, Tertullian focuses on their rejection of water baptism and the underlying view of the created world that this rejection entailed. He is at pains to show how the rejection of water undermined a view of creation in which Christianity’s simple ritual of baptism accentuated God’s simplicity and power.Footnote 38
Tertullian attacks the Cainite teaching by focusing on the premise that water rituals are too ordinary or lowly to carry spiritual power. A simple rite like water baptism seems too quotidian to convey the extraordinary reality of eternal life. On the contrary, Tertullian argues, it is precisely water’s simplicity that accentuates God’s power most supremely: “There is indeed nothing that so strengthens human minds as the simplicity of God’s works as they appear in action, compared with the magnificence promised in their effects.”Footnote 39 In the case of baptism, what occurs in the simplicity of baptism is nothing short of extraordinary:
With such complete simplicity, without pomp, without any unusual equipment, and (not least) without anything to pay, a man is sent down into the water, is washed to the accompaniment of a few words, and comes up little or no cleaner than he was, [yet] his attainment to eternity is regarded as beyond belief.Footnote 40
For Tertullian, it is precisely the simplicity of the ritual that most highlights God’s power. The use of pompous and expensive rituals facilitates belief only through facade – emphasizing the ritual elements themselves rather than the divine dynamis. The “solemn and secret rites” of pagan rituals, Tertullian explains, builds “credence and prestige by pretentious magnificence and by the fees that are charged,” while in reality they “deny to God his characteristic properties of simplicity and power.”Footnote 41 The humble means of water in orthodox baptism, meanwhile, displays divine power in an altogether more majestic way, cultivating faith and wonder (admiratio).Footnote 42 Drawing on the Pauline principle that God uses foolish things to confound the wise (1 Cor. 1:27) and the axiom that a juxtaposition of opposites highlights an entity’s power (uirtus), Tertullian contends that the simple creature, water, is a most fitting display for God’s power to elicit faith.Footnote 43 For Tertullian, nothing so strengthens the human mind like observing God’s mighty works amid the simplicity of these rituals.
Tertullian expounds upon the virtues of water based on its antiquity, honor, and achievement. Water’s great antiquity and role in the processes of creation merit it praise: Even before the world was formed, God’s Spirit chose water upon which to rest. While the other elements existed in unformed chaos, water remained – “always perfect, joyous, simple, of its own nature pure, laid down [as] a worthy carriage for God to move upon.”Footnote 44 Water was involved in the separation of earth and heaven and the creation of other creatures. After the creation of matter, water was needed to moisten it and render it malleable. Its originally generative function thus ought to attune Christians to its regenerative significance. At this point, Tertullian wonders whether he has not reverted from a treatise on baptism to a “panegyric on water”:Footnote 45
If I go on to tell of all or most of the things I could relate concerning the authority (auctoritate) of this element, the greatness of its power (uis) or its grace, with all the devices, all the functions, all the equipment with which it supplies the world, I fear I should seem to have composed a panegyric (laudes) on water instead of a rationale for baptism. Even so, I should be explaining more fully that there is no room for doubt whether God has brought into service in his very own sacraments that same material that he has had at his disposal in all his acts and works, and whether this which guides earthly life makes provision for heavenly things also.Footnote 46
Tertullian admits that he is praising the merits of water as much as providing a logic of baptism. This rhetoric, however, is not unrelated to the baptismal rite, precisely as it attempts to garner trust among his hearers that the simple ritual and the material creatures employed can offer true knowledge of God. He wants to instill confidence in these rituals as trustworthy means by which God offers his saving power. The same material disposed in the world’s creation is the same material by which the world is recreated.
If Tertullian has, by his own admission, strayed from a consideration of baptism per se, it is because he has found it important to show how the simple ritual of baptism unlocks certain capacities of human knowing. Through participation in the ritual of water baptism, properly understood, Christians gain true transforming knowledge of God.
Excursus: Delay of Baptism as Christian Paideia
An important issue for understanding the ritual aspects of knowledge in Tertullian’s setting concerns his well-known appeals for delaying baptism, especially in De baptismo 18 and De paenitentia 6. In these passages, Tertullian argues that Christians should only receive baptism once they have understood the meaning of Christ and the gravity of sin. This argument has sometimes been offered as evidence of a fundamental fault line underlying pre- and post-Constantinian catechesis. I propose, however, seeing Tertullian’s calls for baptismal delay within the scope of his apologetic purposes, comparable to the arguments he makes elsewhere in which he contrasts orthodox Christian churches as philosophical communities espousing discipline and piety while “heretical” Christians are inchoate and indiscriminate in their structure. In this way, Tertullian’s rationale for delaying baptism might thus be seen as part of a larger apologetic effort to present Christianity as a form of Christian paideia, a mode of learning that initiated new Christians into membership through the slow acquisition of virtue.Footnote 47
In De baptismo 18, the argument for delaying baptism comes after several refutations of two scriptural passages that would seem to warrant a quicker administration of baptism – a somewhat figural reading of a text from Luke’s Gospel, “Give to everyone that asks of you” (Luke 6:30), and the example of the Ethiopian Eunuch from Acts 8. In response, Tertullian argues that “deferment of baptism is more profitable, in accordance with each person’s character and disposition, and even age, especially regarding children.”Footnote 48 So, he continues,
Let them come when they are growing up, when they are learning, when they are being taught what they are coming to: Let them be made Christians when they have become competent to know Christ. … All who understand what a burden (pondus) baptism is will have more fear of obtaining it than of its postponement.Footnote 49
In this passage, Tertullian’s pedagogical emphasis is primarily on the learner’s intellectual and moral formation prior to baptism. New Christians need the proper character and cognitive understanding of key tenets of the faith. They need to obtain a proper knowledge of Christ and a sense of the seriousness of sin after baptism to understand what they receive at baptism. A lengthy process of time is thus warranted.
A similar emphasis appears in De paenitentia 6, though it is perhaps slightly more focused on moral and affective matters. Tertullian argues that delaying baptism cultivates an appropriate disposition toward God, guarding against a presumption that would view the catechumenate as an “interlude for sinning, rather than for learning not to sin.”Footnote 50 People who use the catechumenate like this are like those who demand a service without payment, as if baptism obligated God to grant remission of sins by necessity.Footnote 51 Delaying baptism, however, instills a posture of humility before God:
He who desires [baptism], honors it; he who receives it presumptuously, despises it. … Presumption is the part of rash irreverence. It puffs up the petitioner and contemns the donor; thus it is sometimes disappointed, since it promises itself something which is not yet its due and so always offends the one who is expected to grant it.Footnote 52
Without overplaying the difference between these two passages, the emphasis here seems slightly more on the affective dimensions of delaying baptism; delay serves to facilitate a disposition of piety and reverence for Christian rituals. At the same time, this rhetoric emphasizes purification: “We are not baptized so that we may cease committing sin but because we have ceased, since we are already clean of heart.”Footnote 53 With slightly different emphases, both passages share a similar logic: Emphasizing the delay of baptism counters the presumption that the rite’s apparent simplicity justifies an indifference toward the ontological change effected through divine power. Appearances to the contrary, Christian baptism entails a profound change in being.
The apologetic character of these arguments comes to light when we place them alongside Tertullian’s catalog of heretical practices in De praescriptione haereticorum 41 and Aduersus Valentinianos 1. In the former, Tertullian offers his famous portrayal of heresy as ecclesiastical chaos – lacking grauitas, auctoritas, and disciplina:
One cannot tell who is a catechumen and who is baptized. They come in together, listen together, pray together. Even if any of the heathen arrive, they are quite willing to cast that which is holy to the dogs and their pearls (false ones!) before swine. The destruction of discipline is to them simplicity, and our attention to it they call affectation …. Their catechumens are perfect before they are fully instructed…. Their ordinations are hasty, irresponsible and unstable …. So one man is bishop today, another tomorrow. The deacon of today is tomorrow’s reader, the priest of today is tomorrow a layman. For they impose priestly functions even upon laymen.Footnote 54
Especially of interest here is Tertullian’s claim that “catechumens are perfect before they are fully instructed” (ante sunt perfecti catechumeni quam edocti). The heretics, he alleges, do not take the time to teach catechumens but consider them as already having achieved knowledge, presumably through some more immediate process of spiritual enlightenment.
This portrait – polemical as it is – may seem at odds with his equally polemical characterization of Valentinian initiation. But the Valentinian’s lengthy initiation process, he argues, is equally contemptible, for it too betrays a rejection of classical learning. The Valentinians are only attractive to the uninitiated because they use tricks of concealment and mystery to delude initiates.Footnote 55 He compares Valentinian rituals to the Eleusinian mysteries, which likewise prey on the gullible and weak.Footnote 56 Valentinian initiation, for Tertullian, does not yield true learning but only kindles false desires through secrecy: “They teach initiates for five years in order that they may build their belief (opinionem) by a suspending of cognition and in this manner they may seem to exhibit so much greatness as to prepare desire (cupiditatem).”Footnote 57 Their teaching, in other words, is merely rhetorical – indeed sophistical: “They persuade before they teach.”Footnote 58 For Tertullian, by contrast, “truth persuades by teaching, it does not teach by persuading.”Footnote 59 While Valentinians had a lengthy initiation, they did not guide initiates in true wisdom and virtue.
We hardly need to suppose that Tertullian is giving us an objective description of his opponents to appreciate his purposes. Like Irenaeus before him – or indeed like Plotinus after him, in his famous critique of the “Gnostics”Footnote 60 – Tertullian presents his opponents as rejecting the educational standards of classical paideia. These writers associate the metaphysical duality associated with these groups as part and parcel of a rejection of learning and the patient acquisition of virtue. By presenting his version of the orthodox Christian community as a well-ordered society, by contrast, one that entails a lengthy process of catechetical learning before baptism, Tertullian seeks to distance his Christian community from such groups.
For all of Tertullian’s vitriol against pagan knowledge, we find him at key moments drawing on widely shared assumptions about the value of classical learning. For Tertullian, the rhetoric of delaying baptism fits well within the apologetic scope of his presentation of Christianity. It serves to present true Christianity as upholding moral and intellectual virtue, not resorting to mystifying rituals. The goods of learning are not rejected but ordered within a larger vision of knowledge and pedagogy. Catechesis, with its lengthy process of learning, is critical to this task.
Power and Prayer: Simplicity of Speech and Moral Virtue in De oratione
We can return now to other potential sources among Tertullian’s catechetical corpus. De oratione is perhaps a more questionable source for Tertullian’s catechesis, though it is not without merit for being included among his catechetical writings. It does not mention catechumens or those progressing to the font as an audience in the way the other treatises surveyed above do.Footnote 61 Most peculiarly, if this work emerged in pre-baptismal instruction, it betrays many secrets of Christian practice forbidden by the disciplina arcani. Again, though, it is unlikely that such strict rules of secrecy were in effect this early in Christian history.Footnote 62 While Tertullian notes, as we just observed in De praescriptione 41, that heretics allowed pagans access to prayer, it is not apparent that teaching intra-Christian rites was off-limits when pre-baptismal candidates were present. In addition, several clues in Tertullian’s De baptismo, along with Cyprian’s treatise on the Lord’s Prayer, indicate that the Lord’s Prayer was becoming part of the baptismal rite in this period, and thus instruction about its meaning and function would be entirely suitable for catechetical instruction.Footnote 63 We can cautiously propose, following Alistair Stewart, that while the audience of this text is not specified, “it is entirely reasonable to see these discourses [Tertullian’s and Cyprian’s treatises on prayer] reflecting the instruction that was given to catechumens … at the last stage of their formation.”Footnote 64
Like De spectaculis and De baptismo, De oratione considers a key aspect of Christian ritual – namely, the practices of corporate and personal prayer. The practices of prayer, no less than the rejection of the spectacles and Christian baptism, were key aspects of Christian identity in the ancient world.Footnote 65 Our attention will once again be drawn to how instruction on Christian ritual – here, the Lord’s Prayer – elucidates Tertullian’s approach to epistemology. Two features that stand out here are the correlation of divine power manifest through the simple speech of Christian prayer and the framing of prayer as a form of spiritual sacrifice, a corollary of moral virtue that contrasts ostentatious pagan ritual.
Prayer was a contested issue in ancient philosophy. Though prominent in nearly all forms of cultic ritual, many philosophers balked at the incongruity between petitionary prayer and commitments to divine omniscience and providence.Footnote 66 Tertullian’s reflections show clear engagements with such perspectives. For Tertullian, prayer is a nonnegotiable aspect of biblical Christianity, yet he wants to distance it from pagan practices and align it instead with philosophical impulses that understand prayer as a form of spiritual exercise. Hints of metaphysical reflection also color his reflections on prayer. For him, simple speech and the spiritual sacrifice of moral living are all that is needed to address the God who is omnipresent to creation and who does not demand bloody sacrifices. Following Paul, Tertullian understands prayer within the category of spiritual sacrifice (Rom. 12:1). Tertullian’s participatory epistemology of ritual simplicity allows him to teach the Lord’s Prayer as enabling the Christian’s prayer to “ascend to heaven, commending to the Father the things the Son has taught.”Footnote 67
Tertullian situates the Lord’s Prayer as a gift of heavenly wisdom that both complements and supersedes the prayer of John’s disciples (John 11:1). The coming of Christ transforms all that has gone before – it is “the new grace renewing all things from fleshly into spiritual being.”Footnote 68 A new pattern of prayer is thus required. The Lord’s Prayer is both the revelation of “heavenly wisdom” (caelestem eius sophiam) and a “summary of the entire gospel” (breuiarium totius euangelii).Footnote 69 Access to this heavenly wisdom unfolds through participation in the simple speech provided by the prayer’s brief phrases. And yet, lest his audience be deceived by the apparent simplicity of the short prayer, Tertullian demonstrates the breadth of divine power contained in the prayer’s simple speech, especially by appealing to Jesus’s injunctions to pray in secret and without ostentation (Matt. 6:6–8).Footnote 70 The Christian prays in secrecy and simplicity, Tertullian explains, because God is omnipresent to creation. The efficacy of prayer owes not to one’s spatial location or a multiplicity of words but to the faith of the believer who needs only to trust “him who is everywhere to hear and to see.”Footnote 71 By grounding the practice of prayer in a doctrine of divine omnipresence, Tertullian provides a rationale for how the simplicity of the Lord’s Prayer offers the Christian access to heavenly wisdom.
Alongside Tertullian’s high appreciation for simple speech is his insistence on moral virtue. Tertullian especially appeals to the Pauline teaching that describes moral virtue as a form of spiritual sacrifice (Rom. 12:1).Footnote 72 For prayer to ascend to God, Tertullian explains, Christians must be attentive to God’s instructions – chief among which is that Christians should be free from anger and unforgiveness. For “how shall one who is angry with his brother placate the Father, when all anger is forbidden us from the beginning?”Footnote 73 He adds that Christians should not only be free from anger but from “all manner of perturbations of the soul.”Footnote 74 Tertullian describes the acquisition of virtue here in sacrificial language. By living virtuously, the Christian’s prayer ascends to the heavenly throne: “We should lead [the prayer] up to the altar of God, devoted from the whole heart, fattened with faith, prepared by the truth, spotless in innocence, pure in chastity, garlanded with charity, with a procession of good works.”Footnote 75 The proper oblation to God cannot exclude the life of virtue. Instead, the Christian’s life must become a sacrifice pleasing to God.
Tertullian’s treatise on prayer evidences a form of catechetical knowledge commensurate with what we have seen in De spectaculis and De baptismo. If this text was indeed produced in or for a catechetical setting, it accords well with his other works of this kind. In it, Tertullian provides hearers with an account of Christian ritual that finds simple speech and virtue – not profuse verbosity or elaborate sacrifices – as most conducive for obtaining true knowledge of God.
Tertullian and the Rule of Faith
A final place to consider Tertullian’s catechetical epistemology is his use of the Rule of Faith.Footnote 76 As with Irenaeus, my interest in Tertullian’s appeals to the Rule does not concern the evidence they provide of credal-like statements or polemical tools.Footnote 77 Instead, my focus is on what Tertullian’s appeals suggest about theological epistemology. Looking at two key passages where Tertullian draws on the Rule of Faith – De praescriptione haereticorum 13–14 and Aduersus Praxean 2–3 – I want to draw attention to the way Tertullian structures knowledge of God around the discourse of simplicity. In the former passage, Tertullian appeals to the Rule’s simplicity as a guard against a vicious kind of incessant speculation. In the latter, however, Tertullian must demonstrate, against Praxeas’s monarchianism, that the purported complexity of his (Tertullian’s) trinitarianism did not compromise the simplicity espoused in the Rule of Faith. In these two quite different settings, the Rule enters the discussion when issues of simplicity arise. Speculatively, we can propose that this discourse was an important aspect of Tertullian’s approach to ordering knowledge of God in catechesis.
In De praescriptione haereticorum 13–14, after presenting a heretical genealogy of philosophical speculation, Tertullian introduces the Rule of Faith as the church’s guide to sound inquiry, learned from Christ himself. Here he associates the Rule with belief in one God who created the world through the Word – the same Word who was made known in the prophets, who became flesh in the incarnation, proclaimed a new law of the kingdom, was crucified and resurrected, and who sent the Holy Spirit to lead believers into eternal life.Footnote 78 The Rule, in other words, entails a certain picture of how the ultimate creator is related to divine activity in the economy of creation and redemption. After this summary, Tertullian contrasts the simplicity of faith with the curiosity-laden “exercises” of the heretics:
In the last resort, however, it is better for you to remain ignorant, for fear that you come to know what you should not know. For you do know what you should know. “Thy faith hath saved you,” [Luke 18:32] it says; not an exercise in Scripture (exercitatio scripturarum). Faith is established in the Rule. There it has its law, and it wins salvation by keeping the law. Learning derives from curiosity and wins glory only from its zealous pursuit of scholarship (de peritiae studio). Let curiosity give place to faith, and glory to salvation. Let them at least be no hindrance, or let them keep quiet. To know nothing against the Rule is to know everything.Footnote 79
Tertullian contrasts the simplicity of faith with the curiosity of the scriptural exercitatio, which for Tertullian is equivalent to a kind of self-glorification that stands in contrast to the Rule of Faith that leads to salvation. Rather than seeing this rhetoric as an example of fideism – of faith opposing knowledge – it seems more appropriate to understand Tertullian presenting the faith learned in the Rule as a distinct mode of knowledge,Footnote 80 one that eschews the vice of curiosity and is instead governed by what Jean-Claude Fredouille has called Tertullian’s “aesthetic of brevity.”Footnote 81 This aesthetic of brevity, which has both scriptural and classical (especially Stoic) sources, is Tertullian’s way of highlighting the divine origin and content of the faith, rather than the manner of speech in which it is decorated.Footnote 82 Unlike Tertullian’s depiction of Valentinian initiation, which substitutes persuasion for teaching,Footnote 83 orthodox teaching employs an aesthetic of breuitas to accentuate the stability and substance of truth.
Tertullian’s account of the Rule here is instructive in its linkage of the simple taxis of the divine economy in De praescriptione 13 with the juxtaposition of faith and curiosity-prone exercises in De praescriptione 14. Tertullian’s treatment of the Rule here shows that the orthodox account of God’s relation to creation is commensurate with a form of theological knowledge that prizes simple faith.Footnote 84 For Tertullian, Christianity provides access to the one God, creator of all, yet it does so through the unexpected means of faith and an aesthetic of brevity, not vainglorious curiosity or scriptural exercises.
Tertullian’s appeal to the Rule of Faith in Aduersus Praxean also shows how the Rule functioned to shape theological knowledge vis-à-vis the simplicity of faith. Here, however, Tertullian’s adversary is not the infinite speculations of demiurgical heretics but the monarchian theology of Praxeas, who viewed trinitarianism as an unnecessary complication of the simple teaching that God is one. In building his case for trinitarian theology on the logic of the Rule of Faith, Tertullian shows that a nuanced view of the relation between Father, Son, and Holy Spirit is not incommensurate with the simple teaching that God is one. For Tertullian, rather, the Rule of Faith offers a reliable guide to understand the deep connections between divine unity and plurality – the distinction but not division of Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.
The monotheism of Praxeas, according to Tertullian, failed to distinguish properly between Father and Son and so led to the impious conclusion that it was the Father who was born and who suffered on the cross.Footnote 85 Tertullian then introduces the Rule of Faith to relate the one God with the plurality of the three persons in the divine economy:
We … believe that there is one only God, but under the following dispensation, or οἰκονομία, as it is called, that this one only God has also a Son, his Word, who proceeded from himself, by whom all things were made, and without whom nothing was made.Footnote 86
He follows with an account of the dispensation of the Son’s birth, death, resurrection, coming again, and sending of the Spirit,Footnote 87 before turning to a discussion of how the Rule of Faith functions in theological knowing. It begins with turning “simple people” from polytheism to monotheism: “The Rule of Faith itself transfers [them] from the many gods of the age to the one, true God.”Footnote 88 This suggests that a key function of the Rule in shaping belief was the exclusion of multiple gods.Footnote 89 However, when “simple” people encounter the monotheism governed by the Rule, they may become confused as to how divine unity accords with multiple stages or a graded divine hierarchy, which seems incumbent with descriptions of the economy: “They judge that economy, implying a number and arrangement of trinity, is really a division of unity; whereas [in fact] unity, deriving trinity from itself, is not destroyed by it but made serviceable.”Footnote 90 Tertullian’s task in the remainder of this treatise is to demonstrate the coherence of this thesis.
Tertullian next outlines a way of understanding the unity between monarchy and economic plurality, offering a variety of scriptural expositions, arguments, and metaphors – many of which would figure in later trinitarian debates.Footnote 91 Important to our purposes here, however, is that Tertullian introduces the Rule to present a mode of knowing God in which speculative reflection on the divine being is commensurate with the “simple” belief in one God. In an anti-monarchian context, Tertullian must counter his opponent’s ostensibly simpler paradigm that eschews the complex distinctions of trinitarian theology. Indeed, Praxeas might well have accused Tertullian of the vain “curiosity” that Tertullian himself decried in De praescriptione. Tertullian, therefore, must show how the divine economy does not threaten the divine monarchy expressed in the Rule but is in fact a logical corollary – that which underscores the inseparable unity of the one God who is Father, Son, and Spirit.Footnote 92
Given the Rule’s focus on correlating divine unity with trinitarian plurality, we can see the way in which a discourse of simplicity was important to Tertullian’s understanding of the Rule of Faith. This simplicity was not opposed to reason or speculation. Rather, beginning with the simple Rule of Faith was the way in which Christians could find a generative context to discern the ultimately mysterious nature of the triune God.
Conclusion
Tertullian’s catechesis is characterized by a mode of knowing God in which the paradox between divine power and ritual simplicity comes to the fore. He aimed to teach not only certain tenets of belief or morals but also to guide new Christians into forms of practice that would generate true knowledge. Contestations over the nature of the world and its relation to God were, of course, marked features of early Christian discourse – not only between differing Christian communities but also between Christians and non-Christians. The boundaries between such groups were fluid and often unclear. One way in which Tertullian sought to structure Christian identity was by shaping a mode of attention to God through the simplicity of Christian ritual. The simple rituals of water baptism and the succinct formula of the Lord’s Prayer accentuated the power and greatness of God. The simplicity of belief encapsulated in the Rule of Faith was likewise a sure guide to knowing the one God who is Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. The Christian’s rejection of the shows was grounded in a view of creation’s goodness but susceptibility to demonic perversion. In each of these contexts, Tertullian stressed that Christian knowing prioritizes simplicity and faith as a reliable means of knowing the one true God.