Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-11T07:01:26.394Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Rise of the Procedural Paradigm: Judicial Review of EU Legislation in Vertical Competence Disputes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 May 2017

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

EU Law–Vertical competence review of EU secondary law–Court of Justice control of the exercise of EU legislative powers–Strict procedural review of EU legislation–Standard of judicial review and intensity of judicial review–Judicial review as a safeguard of federalism–Constitutional review of EU legislation–Proportionality, subsidiarity and principle of conferral–Balance between the EU legislator’s prerogatives and the need to ensure that EU legislation conforms to the precepts of EU law–Distribution of competences between Member States and the EU

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2017 

Basic context: setting out the problem of competence review of EU legislation

A central question for any court engaged in constitutional review (i.e. where statutes are scrutinised for their conformity with principles enshrined in constitution or other basic lawsFootnote 1 ) is how rigorously the Court should scrutinise legislation. A court’s choice is arguably a two-fold matter of institutional and constitutional choice. In a federal jurisdiction (and systems of a similar nature) it appears that the intensity that is used when the court reviews legislation (deriving from the central legislator) determines not only the balance of powers between the court and the legislator but also between the central government and its component entities.Footnote 2 Stringent review of federal legislation tends, put simply, to favour the states and the courts vis-à-vis the central legislator. More leeway to the federal legislator instead suggests that the court may not wish to encroach upon the prerogative of the legislator to make policy, nor impose excessive burdens on the federal legislator in relation to the states.Footnote 3 The question of intensity and standard of judicial review is therefore a question of who, the Court or another societal decision-maker, should make the final decision in a democracy of what the constitution means.Footnote 4 This is a question of comparative institutional choice. Courts tend to engage in more deferential review where they enjoy inferior (democratic) legitimacy, competence and expertise than the legislator to analyse a certain question.Footnote 5 Regardless whether one wishes to conceive judicial review primarily as a constitutional question or an institutional one, it seems that any judicial review court would ultimately have to address these two questions.

This essay intends to contribute to this debate by exploring the role of the European Court of Justice in judicial review of EU legislation in vertical competence disputes: i.e. litigation where EU legislation has been pleaded to be contrary to the constitutional principles of conferral, subsidiarity and proportionality.Footnote 6 The Court of Justice’s role in policing the constitutional order of competences enshrined by the Treaties remains contested. To this date, it appears that the Court of Justice, when faced with complex competence/legal basis litigation, has tended to address the ‘constitutional question’ in favour of the Union vis-à-vis the Member States, thus accepting the EU legislator’s broad interpretation of its legislative powers.Footnote 7 The Court’s approach should, however, not be surprising. As contended below, it appears that the vague content of the principles limiting the exercise of EU powers has pushed the Court of Justice to the outer limits of its legitimacy as derived from the Treaties. The quasi-political and empirical questions involved in assessing the proportionality of EU legislation, the question of what ‘benefits’ the internal market, and the question of the right regulatory level for achieving an EU objective (subsidiarity) are all issues that the Court as an institution may be less equipped than the Union legislator to address. Thus, the ‘institutional choice’ has tended to tilt in favour of the EU legislator.Footnote 8

The recent Philip Morris judgment illustrates these concerns. In this case, a revised tobacco advertising directive was contested inter alia on the ground that it prohibited the marketing of tobacco products with a ‘characterising flavour’, thus preventing rather than facilitating trade with regard to the product concerned. Despite this, the directive was considered as falling within the scope of Article 114 TFEU.Footnote 9 The Court addressed proportionality in an equally deferential manner. It explicitly stated that the Union legislature must be allowed a broad discretion within the field of public health, as this policy involves political and social choices on its part ,and complex assessments. The legality of a measure adopted in that area can be affected only if the measure is manifestly inappropriate having regard to the objective that the competent institutions are seeking to pursue.Footnote 10 On the basis of this standard, it was well-anticipated that the Court found the measure to be proportionate.Footnote 11 The Court of Justice’s subsidiarity assessment also demonstrated a very low-intensity review. Whilst the Court did consider the substantive part of the subsidiarity test, its approach to procedural subsidiarity was strikingly deferential. The Court stated in one sentence that there was sufficient information in the impact assessment and the explanatory memorandum demonstrating the need for Union action.Footnote 12 Philip Morris consolidates the Court’s approach to judicial competence review of EU legislation, which so far can be characterised as deferential and perhaps incapable of protecting the distribution of competences between the Member States and the Union.

In light of this, this article examines how, i.e. with what intensity and what test, the Court of Justice should enforce the constitutional principles of conferral, subsidiarity, and proportionality in a challenge to EU secondary legislation.Footnote 13 It advances the argument that a more intense ‘process-based’ review rather than ‘substantive’ reviewFootnote 14 of EU legislative activities is an appropriate judicial safeguard of federalism. The scope of the article is constrained to a review of secondary EU law having general application and will thus not examine in-depth situations where the EU legislator acts as an administrative agency. This limitation is justified given that the role of the Court of Justice is different with regard to judicial review of general secondary EU legislation than with regard to review of individual administrative decisions. The Court of Justice’s position is delicate with regard to the position of the EU institutions in their role as legislator, which includes the making of sensitive policy choices. The Court’s role with regard to the EU legislator when it acts as an administrative agency is more taken for granted, as judicial review is deemed necessary within this context to ensure that the administrative discretion is not exercised in an arbitrary manner resulting in infringements of an individual’s fundamental rights.Footnote 15

The article is structured as follows: The first section evaluates the rationales behind the Court’s conventional approach to competence review by examining how the framing of the Treaties has influenced the Court of Justice’s capacity to engage in judicial review. The following section then considers the case for procedural review. It will be argued that institutional considerations and the advancement of a legitimacy discourse support the view that procedural review is the appropriate form of review (or ‘paradigm’) for enforcing the principles in Article 5 TEU. The third section subsequently develops a test for judicial review, based upon an analysis of the Court’s ruling in Spain v Council that the Court can apply to assess the legality of EU legislation. The final section summarises the argument and reflects on the implications of the proposed model.

Institutional and conceptual problems of vertical competence review

This section provides a more detailed account of the concerns against judicial review raised in the introduction. Institutional arguments against judicial review are commonplace in constitutional discourse. The premise within the context of review of EU legislationFootnote 16 is that principled analysis, of the kind required by the principles in Article 5 TEU involving complex empirical and normative judgment of the effectiveness and appropriateness of different EU policies, is beyond the capacities of the EU courts. This is because in such cases the Union Courts are operating at the border of judicial legitimacy derived from their authority and competence.Footnote 17 A conventional understanding of democratic legitimacy therefore suggests that the primary responsibility for policy-making should reside with the EU political institutions that enjoy the legitimacy to perform this task. Only a political procedure can ensure that important decisions are taken after a transparent procedure in which all relevant stakeholders can participate and engage in a genuine political debate over the balance to be struck between conflicting interests.Footnote 18

The institutional problems of judicial review within the EU context are reinforced by the conceptual problems of the existing limits on EU competences. A lack of clarity as to the meaning of the principles in Article 5 TEU means that if the Court of Justice is to engage in proper substantive judicial review, it must become involved in assessing open-ended political, economic and social issues.Footnote 19 The Court is fundamentally ill-equipped for this task. Furthermore, since several important legislative powers such as Article 114 and Article 352 TFEU are framed as purposive and functional powers defined by the goal to be achieved,Footnote 20 the Treaties have provided grounds for an expansive interpretation by the Union legislator of the scope of the Union’s powers.Footnote 21 Appeals to objectives or policies cannot work as a limit to EU competences, since they do not provide the Court with hard legal criteria to resolve disputes.Footnote 22 The teleological imperative of further integration enshrined in the design of the EU legal order has furthermore placed constraints on the Court to effectively enforce the vertical order of competences. If the Union is to achieve the objectives set out in the Treaties and resolve functional problems, the necessary powers must be placed at the service of the Union.Footnote 23 With this imperative, the Court has consistently supported a broad interpretation of the scope of Union competences in order to enhance the effectiveness of Union law.Footnote 24 The Court of Justice’s position in the legal order of the Union furthermore provides an argument against strict competence review. The Court is in fact an EU institution (and an agency of the Union) and may have institutional incentives to protect that interest. Certainly the behaviour of the Court in the past suggested that it viewed itself as a force for integration rather than as a guardian of Member State interests.Footnote 25

The link between institutional, teleological and theoretical considerations in determining the intensity of judicial review is demonstrated by the Court of Justice’s approach to scrutiny of legislation adopted under Article 114 TFEU. The wording of this provision – giving the EU legislator power to adopt the measures ‘for the approximation of the provisions laid down by law, regulation or administrative action in Member States which have as their object the establishment and functioning of the internal market’ – suggests that the EU legislator has been endowed with a wide margin of discretion as to how it executes the internal market objectives. This discretion is well-recognised by the Court. For example, the Court has upheld the view that the authors of the Treaty intended to confer a freedom of choice to the Union legislator under Article 114 TFEU depending on the general context and the specific circumstances of the matter to be harmonised, and with regard to the most appropriate mode and method for achieving the objectives of the internal market.Footnote 26 Ultimately, the Court’s deferential approach has resulted in feeble enforcement of the outer limits of Article 114 TFEU.Footnote 27

The reasons behind the Court’s cautious stance to subsidiarity and proportionality can be traced to similar concerns. The subsidiarity principle forces the Court to engage in an assessment of the complex political-economic questions of reliance on Member State alternatives, and seek compromise using the values of efficiency and democracy in order to determine whether there is a need for EU action. These are matters of political judgment that the EU legislative institutions, for reasons of legitimacy and competence, are better equipped to evaluate.Footnote 28 The Court’s own perception of its institutional capacity does in fact permeate its approach to subsidiarity review, which is marked by an extremely deferential review of the principle.Footnote 29 When it comes to the Court’s proportionality review of general EU policy schemes, it seems to be recognised that EU political institutions make policy assessments that involve complex factors to be balanced and weighed by the EU legislature. The EU courts are not well equipped to make these assessments and should therefore not overturn the EU legislator’s political choices.Footnote 30 These general considerations have led the Court to review proportionality on the basis of a ‘manifestly inappropriate’ test, which has resulted in poor enforcement of Article 5(4) TEU.Footnote 31

Two points summarise the discussion so far. The first is the connection between the clarity of the Treaty limits in Article 5 TEU and institutional arguments for deferential judicial review. Since the Court does not have any clear criteria against which it can assess conformity with the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU, it must venture to the borders of its authority and analyse issues beyond the law to engage in the review required by this provision. The Court is apparently not comfortable taking on this task. Second, there is something persuasive about the institutional arguments for lenient review of EU legislation. It appears axiomatic that the Court of Justice should, given its questionable expertise and legitimacy relative to the legislator, neither substitute the judgement of the appropriateness of EU measures nor political choices where the EU legislature was required to balance divergent political interests against each other. This suggests that it may be difficult for the Court to engage in stronger substantive review, as this would mean that the Court would have to go beyond its legitimacy and competence by reconsidering the EU legislator’s political decisions. Notwithstanding these observations, there is still hope for more intense judicial scrutiny of the principles in Article 5 TEU. As contended in the remainder of this article, in order to respond to the arguments for deferential review advanced above the Court is encouraged to develop its current procedural form of review.

The case for strict procedural review

Because of the numerous terms used in the literature, an account of a definition of procedural reviewFootnote 32 is necessary for the purposes of the present article. The article proceeds from a strict understanding of procedural review that compels the Court to consider whether the reasoning and evidence of the EU legislator is sufficient to justify the exercise of general legislative powers.Footnote 33 This suggests that the Court, at a minimum, should consider whether the EU legislator conformed to the procedural steps and structures mandated by the Treaties.Footnote 34 On the one hand, this definition is broader than that of ‘pure’ procedural review, which entails that courts in their review focus exclusively on whether the legislature met certain statute-based procedural requirements in the legislative process. On the other hand, it is narrower than ‘substantive review’ that requires courts to determine the validity of legislation based strictly on an examination of the statute’s content.Footnote 35

What then are the pros and cons of procedural review? The key argument in support of this form of review is that it responds to the institutional objections against the Court of Justice’s capacity to engage in competence review.Footnote 36 Whilst the EU legislator’s choice of policy may go beyond the Court’s authority to review, the question of whether EU legislative institutions has substantiated its legislative choices is an issue that the Court is well-equipped to examine.Footnote 37 Procedural requirements relating to the adequacy of the evidential basis for decision-making also help remedy the problems of reviewing the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU.Footnote 38 Since procedural review requires policy-makers to collect evidence, the Court will have at its disposal a useful mass of materials that will help it to determine the legality of a given act.Footnote 39

The literature has, nevertheless, identified several problems with this type of review, namely that: (i) intense procedural review regularly is transformed to substantive review; (ii) procedural review gives too much discretion to judges in deciding what relevant reasoning and information is; (iii) procedural review is contrary to the principle of institutional balance (and the principles of democracy). Each of these will be considered in turn.

Martin Shapiro has expounded on the challenge for courts to maintain review of a ‘procedural’ nature. He contends there is a virtually unidentifiable line between intense procedural review for ‘adequate’ reasoning and substantive review as regards giving reasoning requirements.Footnote 40 Referring to the example of the reasoning requirement in the US Administrative Procedure Act, Shapiro expresses concerns that procedural requirements imposed by courts may develop to an intrusive style of substantive review. This occurs when the court not only looks at the purely procedural question of whether reasoning exists, but also at the substantive question of whether the reasoning is sufficient. Procedural review also gives judges unbridled discretion in deciding in each case what the relevant information is, and what would constitute appropriate reasoning.Footnote 41

There is force in Shapiro’s criticism. It is clear that procedural review may turn into substantive review if the Court of Justice assesses the adequacy of the reasoning given. The scope of the suggested procedural review is, however, limited. Procedural review does not suggest review of the appropriateness of legislation or that the Court substitutes the EU legislator’s political choices. Instead, it grants a substantial amount of discretion to the EU legislature in the field of the common policies as long as the legislature has considered the evidence of the case. Neither does procedural review suggest that the Court should track the whole legislative procedure. It is limited to considering whether legislative choices fit with the reasoning and the evidence in the legislative background documents (impact assessments, explanatory memoranda, and proposals/amendments to the legislative proposal deriving from EU institutions).Footnote 42

Can strict procedural review be distinguished from substantive review? Admittedly, there is a very fine line between these two forms of review. If it is possible to uphold the distinction, the line between ‘strict procedural review’ and ‘substantive review’ is crossed if the Court starts to assess whether the EU legislator’s choice has been the best or most appropriate choice.Footnote 43 Shapiro illustrates himself where the border may be drawn between strict procedural review and substantive review through the Remia case.Footnote 44 In Remia, the Court of Justice held that it had competence to review whether the simple, first order facts were accurately stated, and whether the legislator’s reasoning indicated that the legislator had considered those facts. The Court, however, disclaimed competence to review the economic/political analysis that the legislator had applied to the facts in order to reach its decisions.Footnote 45

Shapiro’s criticism that judicially created procedural demands may give too much discretion to courts should also be taken seriously. It is recognised that the Court of Justice might, when faced with an uncertain construction of Union legislation, in pursuing strict procedural review be led to a different mode of analysis to which it may not be accustomed. This problem is, however, not unique to demanding procedural review. The Court’s substantive review in fundamental rights cases and its proportionality jurisprudence within the context of the fundamental freedoms is characterised by difficult political judgments as well as open-ended assessments of the appropriateness of certain measures. Rights-based review is regularly justified on the basis that it has always been considered the proper domain of courts in terms of legitimacy and expertise.Footnote 46 The Court’s proportionality review within the fundamental freedoms must be considered within its proper context. This concerns prima facie infringements by Member States of the fundamental freedoms and where the Member State later raise a defence based on the relevant Treaty article or a mandatory requirement. The four freedoms are therefore central to the very idea of market integration that lies at the economic heart of the EU. Given this, it is unsurprising that the Court of Justice has applied proportionality intensively in such cases. Furthermore, it is clear that several of the judgments on proportionality and the fundamental freedoms have emerged in the context of Article 267 TFEU proceedings where the Court of Justice does not apply proportionality to the facts of the national dispute but leaves this assessment for national courts. This is not to say that the Court may give the national courts very close guidance on proportionality questions. It does, however, qualify the proposition that proportionality review in fundamental freedom cases perforce must be intensive.Footnote 47 Having recognised these justifications for strict proportionality review and stringent rights-based review, it is clear that the Court of Justice still is well-placed to review societal questions when enforcing the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU. It would even seem to be an indispensable task for the Court of Justice, as a constitutional court, to perform within the EU.Footnote 48 It is therefore difficult to see why procedural forms of review assessing the adequacy of reasoning and the evidence for measures should be considered as too intrusive.Footnote 49

Procedural review, although less controversial in terms of legitimacy and competence than substantive review, has still suffered from such institutional criticisms as were accounted for in the previous section. US scholarship has particularly underlined the problem of separation of powers that occurs when courts engage in intense procedural review. Taking the example of the Supreme Court’s jurisprudence, Cristopher Bryant and Timothy Simeone suggest that the judiciary has no authority or legitimacy to impose requirements regarding the kind of legislative record that the legislator must compile when enacting a statute. Judgments relating to the need for legislation are often inherently value-laden, political and consigning such judgments to the judiciary flies in the face of the principle of institutional balance. This criticism is exacerbated when courts impose upon the legislature heightened judicially-created requirements leading potentially to substitution of the legislator’s policy choices.Footnote 50

Bryant and Simeone’s argument against procedural review is undoubtedly compelling. There is obviously a risk that courts, in identifying the procedural steps to be followed, might make value judgments similar to those expressed by substantive review courts. Procedural review, nonetheless, poses a lesser challenge to democratic political theoryFootnote 51 and the principle of institutional balance than substantive review. Intense process-based review only requires normative judgments about how decisions should be made, not judgments with reference to the content of the political decision. The aim is thus to refine rather than to frustrate democratic decision-making.Footnote 52

Therefore, it is sustained that there remains, also with respect to the precepts of democracy, a legitimate place for judicial competence review within the EU political context.Footnote 53 Even if one argues that courts generally enjoy less legitimacy than the political decision-maker, it appears that the political procedures in the EU are weaker in democratic terms than classical national political systems such as the United States, which was used as a target for Jeremy Waldron’s famous attack on judicial review.Footnote 54 It seems that the present state of the EU political process, with the Union still suffering from a democratic deficit (compared to western democracies), partly undermines the classic challenge to the Court. Whilst the European Parliament is popularly elected, its powers are still limited and the other EU institutions cannot claim a democratic mandate. Neither the Council nor the Commission is selected by or accountable to the electorate. There are also structural limits to the realisation of input democracy in the EU. The fact that the people are represented through the European Parliament and the Member States in the Council means that it is not possible under existing arrangements (where Council representatives are not chosen by the citizens) for the EU citizens to directly vote out those in power and substitute them with a different party. It is thus questionable whether Waldron’s main assumption on ‘democratic institutions in a good working order’Footnote 55 is met with respect to the EU political procedure, which undermines the ‘core case’ against judicial review of EU legislation.Footnote 56

Although a strong case could be made that procedural review may, at times, upset the institutional balance between courts and the legislator and be subject to similar institutional criticism in terms of legitimacy and competence as substantive review, there is still a good argument for courts to develop demanding forms of procedural review. Strict procedural review has an intrinsic value in promoting a more legitimate legislative process. The latter appears pressing since the EU still today,Footnote 57 post-Lisbon, seems to suffer from legitimacy challenges in terms of a lack of transparency and accountability as regards political decision-making. A Eurobarometer survey in 2011 revealed that 42% of European citizens are not satisfied with the level of transparency in the EU administration, while only 9% are satisfied.Footnote 58 The EU’s specific institutional structure, the opaque decision-making procedure and the complexity of the typology of legal acts, obscure appreciation of the vertical allocation of powers and the accountability for decisions.Footnote 59 Although there have been general improvements as regards access to documents and more open legislative deliberations, citizens still perceive a great distance between themselves and the governing EU institutions in Brussels. It is argued that more demanding procedural review imposed by the Court will be instrumental in addressing these concerns.

The premise for this argument is that such a form of review by courts supports a discourse of legitimacy by focusing on the legislator’s justification, by fostering deliberation and by structuring the exercise of public power. Procedural review has its strongest underpinnings in procedural democratic theories that consider the process by which laws are generated as the main source of legitimacy.Footnote 60 Such theories contrast with substantive legitimacy theories, which focus on the content of the law and its conformity with some normative moral standard. In the present context, it is not necessary to determine whether it is most appropriate to endorse the procedural or substantive theories of democracy. There are particular legitimacy benefits connected to procedural justice, and it is sustained that strict procedural review is apt to produce them. Several empirical studies (particularly of the US Congress) indicate that a person’s perception that the legislator employs fair decision-making procedures positively impacts on the social legitimacy of the legislative procedure.Footnote 61 The literature on procedural justice also suggests that a deliberative process that is perceived to be fair and inclusive to differing points of view receives higher legitimacy assessments and more positive assessments of the outcome produced than one that is perceived to be closed and partial.

On the basis of the literature reviewed in the previous paragraph, it is suggested that the model of procedural review advanced here will promote the values mentioned and thus be a legitimacy-reinforcing instrument within the EU.Footnote 62 The relationship between transparency and procedural review illustrates this point. In this respect, it appears that the Court of Justice’s case law on the giving-reasoning requirement in Article 296 TFEU exhibits that transparency is one of the foundations for strong procedural review. Such a review requires that citizens may legitimately claim a right to know about the reasons behind a government decision. By requiring the EU institutions to substantiate their decisions with reasoning and evidence, procedural review reinforces the importance of transparency in the legislative procedure.Footnote 63

It is thus contended that stringent procedural review may increase both the social and legal legitimacyFootnote 64 of the EU’s decision-making procedures. By enforcing standards of rational decision-making and by requiring EU action to be more accountable, the Court promotes the social legitimacy of the EU system of governance as a whole (and confidence among EU citizens with this system).Footnote 65 The procedural review model proposed here is also capable of advancing a broader culture of justification in policymaking by inducing the EU legislators to rely upon sufficient knowledge before they exercise their discretion.Footnote 66 This will in turn reinforce legal legitimacy, as adherence to the court-imposed procedural requirements will serve as a check that the legislative outcome is in conformity with the Treaty mandate. The aspiration of procedural review is, thus, ultimately, to restore integrity in the making of EU legislation.Footnote 67

A Proposal for a General Standard of Review and Test for Legality of EU Legislation

This section develops, on the basis of the procedural review framework suggested in the previous section, a more concrete benchmark that the Court should use to review the legality of EU legislation.

The Court of Justice’s track record in procedural review

The following examines the Court’s leading judgments on process-based review,Footnote 68 in particular by reference to the principles in Article 5 TEU.Footnote 69

A review of the case law shows some common trends and development. Germany v Parliament and CouncilFootnote 70 suggested that the Court may not be willing to enforce procedural subsidiarity. In this case, the Court of Justice accepted that the Deposit Guarantee Directive complied with subsidiarity, whilst the principle was not even mentioned in the preamble to the legislation. The Court even went quite some way to help the EU legislator to defend compliance with subsidiarity by indicating in the judgment those preambles that would support that EU action provided added value with regard to the regulation of deposit guarantee schemes.Footnote 71 The Court’s feeble stance on procedural subsidiarity has, however, been confirmed by subsequent case law.Footnote 72

There are, nevertheless, single Court judgments which show a stronger stance on procedural review.Footnote 73 Spain v Council,Footnote 74 which concerned a proportionality challenge to a regulation on a new cotton support scheme,Footnote 75 laid down high informational requirements on the Union legislator. The Court of Justice applied a stringent procedural testFootnote 76 and quashed the contested regulation on the basis of the Commission’s failure to take into account all ‘relevant information’ pertaining to the situation and its failure to produce and present clearly the ‘basic facts’ that had to be taken into account as the basis of the contested regulation.Footnote 77

Vodafone, concerned with a challenge to the EU roaming regulation, was the next important judgment on procedural review. In this case the Court clearly articulated a process-based approach to competence review by explicitly relying for the first time on the impact assessment and explanatory memorandum when examining the legality of an EU policy measure.Footnote 78 The Court, however, did not entertain intense process-based review according to the standard of ‘relevant circumstances’ suggested by Spain v Council. Footnote 79 Both in relation to its proportionality assessment and the review of the Roaming Regulation’s conformity to Article 114 TFEU (which was the chosen legal basis for the measure), the Court employed the legislative background documents primarily to confirm that the EU legislator’s choices as to the intensity and scope of the measure (covering both retail and wholesale charges) were justified.Footnote 80 With regard to the analysis of Article 114 TFEU, the Court confirmed the Commission’s contention that unless the Union intervened, there was a risk that divergent national measures would be adopted that would lead to distortion of the EU roaming market.Footnote 81

Afton Chemical, decided only a month after Vodafone, also contains important guidance from the Court on its approach to procedural review. Afton Chemical was a case concerned with a challenge to a directive on the specification of petrol, diesel and gas-oil.Footnote 82 The Court referred in the case to the test in Spain v Council of ‘relevant circumstances’Footnote 83 but adopted a weak procedural approach to proportionality review. The problem in Afton Chemical was that the EU legislator had imposed new limits on the use of MMTFootnote 84 in the final directive without any clear scientific basis for this limit or any explanation for why it had been included in the directive but not in the original proposal. The Court, however, held that the validity of EU legislation was not dependent on compliance with the underlying impact assessment, nor was there any requirement that deviation from the impact assessment be explained. This was, according to the Court, because the EU legislator, under the ordinary decision procedure, was entitled to make amendments to the impact assessment and the original proposal.Footnote 85

Whilst there are signs in the case law that the Court of Justice has gradually become engaged in a more ‘process-based review’, a modest reading suggests that these efforts should perhaps not be characterised as a success (with the exception of Spain v Council). There are, although Vodafone witnessed more intense procedural review, fairly strong indications in the case law that the Court’s threshold for compliance with informational requirements has been fixed at an insufficiently low level. Germany v Parliament and Council illustrates the extreme position of non-existing procedural enforcement of subsidiarity (similar to Philip Morris), whilst Afton Chemical shows a very deferential procedural review by accepting deviations from the impact assessment. If we compare the Court’s application of procedural review to the definition proposed in this article, it seems that the Court’s procedural enquiry is limited to considering whether the EU legislator has stated a justification, and not whether this justification is coherent with the grounds for exercising the competence under the relevant competence-conferring provision. Neither does the Court examineFootnote 86 whether the reasoning advanced for exercising the competence is supported by any evidence.

This turns us to the scope of procedural review. This section gave examples of procedural review in relation to all the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU. It is argued that the Court should not, even though most procedural review cases has been concerned with proportionality,Footnote 87 limit procedural review to this plea but also use this form of review to examine conferral and subsidiarity.Footnote 88 There is no a priori rationale for limiting review to proportionality, as it appears that the concerns of vague conceptual scope and institutional considerations apply equally to subsidiarity and conferral.Footnote 89 As seen from the discussion here, it is furthermore clear that the Court of Justice is willing to apply a form of procedural review, also with regard to subsidiarity (Netherlands v Parliament and Council, Phillip Morris) and conferral (Vodafone, Phillip Morris), albeit not in the form advanced in this article. Experience from the US shows further evidence for the contention that process-based review can be used generally to enforce the constitutional order of competences.Footnote 90

Spain v Council – providing the fruits for an appropriate standard for judicial review

This section develops, on the basis of the procedural review framework suggested in the previous section, a more concrete benchmark which the Court should use to review the legality of EU legislation. Whilst the intense test in Spain v Council of ‘relevant circumstances’ has not, as suggested above, been used consistently in relation to review of broad EU policy schemes,Footnote 91 this section argues that this judgment should be used as a benchmark for judicial review.

As we know from above, in this case, Spain challenged a Council regulation on new support schemes for cotton on the basis that it infringed the proportionality principle by not taking into account relevant information when deciding on the specific amount of aid granted under this scheme. The Court underlined, as regards judicial review of the principle of proportionality, the wide discretion enjoyed by the Union legislature in the field of the Common Agricultural Policy and that a measure adopted in this field could only be affected if the measure was manifestly inappropriate in terms of the objective that the EU institution is seeking to pursue and if the institution has manifestly exceeded the limits of its discretion.Footnote 92 Up to this point, the Court simply followed its standard case law on review of proportionality within the sphere of broad EU policies. However, the Court dramatically changed this course of reasoning in paragraphs 122 and 123, by imposing a new standard and test of review:

‘However even though [such] judicial review of [proportionality] is of limited scope, it requires that the Community institutions which have adopted the act in question must be able to show before the Court that in adopting the act they actually exercised their discretion, which presupposes the taking into consideration of all the relevant factors and circumstances of the situation the act was intended to regulate. It follows that the institutions must at the very least be able to produce and set out clearly and unequivocally the basic facts which had to be taken into account as the basis of the contested measures of the act and on which the exercise of their discretion depended.’Footnote 93

On the basis of these principles, the Court proceeded to annul the regulation. The Court noted that the Commission had failed to include certain labour costs in the study of the foreseeable profitability of cotton growing under the new scheme. The Court emphasised that labour costs were a relevant factor for the purposes of calculating the production costs of cotton and the foreseeable profitability of that crop. The Court also found that the potential effects of the reform on the economic situation of the ginning undertakings – whilst being a ‘basic factor’ to be taken into account – were not examined. The Court recognised that cotton production is not economically possible without the presence of such undertakings operating under sustainable conditions, since cotton has little commercial value before being processed and cannot be transported over long distances. Given that the Commission had been unable to show that it had actually exercised its discretion by taking into account all the relevant circumstances, the Court concluded that there was a breach of the principle of proportionality.Footnote 94

Analysis – why does Spain v Council provide an appropriate standard of review?

Commentators have argued that Spain v Council marks a clear evolution towards greater intensity in the judicial review of facts and in the application of procedural proportionality and that the standard of legality proposed by this case is consistent with the Court of Justice’s earlier jurisprudence on review of administrative decisions.Footnote 95 While Spain v Council appears to be an important judgment of principle, it is contestable whether this case can be interpreted as evidence for a transformation from deferential review to intense judicial examination of facts in relation to EU legislation. There are, as mentioned above,Footnote 96 no cases on competence review, post-Spain v Council, that have followed the intensity of review suggested by that judgment. Nor is there any clear basis in the Court’s case law on review in the field of the common policies prior to Spain v Council under which the Court’s propositions in that judgment could be grounded.Footnote 97 Furthermore, although the review by the Court of Justice in Spain v Council was reminiscent of the Court of First Instance’sFootnote 98 strict factual review in Tetra Laval and Pfizer, the last-mentioned judgments must be distinguished from Spain v Council. The Court of First Instance’s extremely searching enquiries in Pfizer Footnote 99 and Tetra Laval,Footnote 100 although like Spain v Council phrased in terms of ‘manifest error’ and ‘manifestly inappropriate’, were prompted by the fact that those judgments were, in principle, related to individual decisions. Such decisions are generally subject to a highly-intense review by the EU courts.Footnote 101 Although the regulationFootnote 102 in Pfizer was formally of a general nature, its effect had the nature of a decision by withdrawing Pfizer’s authorisation to market virginiamycin and since Pfizer was the only company having such an authorisation. The act was thus of ‘direct’ and ‘individual’ concern to Pfizer’.Footnote 103 Tetra Laval, on the other hand, was concerned with a Commission decision prohibiting a prospective merger. The fact that this decision immediately affected the rights of Tetra Laval required a full judicial review of the Commission’s decision both in relation to law and facts.Footnote 104 Given the distinction in the EU courts’ case law between the nature of review in situations involving administrative decisions and general legislative acts, it seems that Spain v Council was an exception to the rule that review in the field of the common policies is of low intensity.

Notwithstanding this, it is argued that the benchmark suggested by Spain v Council provides an appropriate yardstick for showing how the Court of Justice should review EU legislation in vertical competence disputes. The Court’s standard requiring the objectives of the legislation to be substantiated is an appropriate ‘middle-way’ solution between full substantive review of facts and complete surrender to the political authority of the EU legislator.Footnote 105 The Court’s burden of proof, (deviating from the main rule that applicants challenging general EU legislative acts must demonstrate the measure to be disproportionate), requiring the EU institutions to show that it had exercised its discretion contributed in making the standard of review credible.Footnote 106 Thereto, it is clear that the rigour of the Court’s review was appropriate to implement the legality standard. The strict intensity entailed that the Court did not accept the assertions made by the Commission, but examined independently whether it had taken into account ‘relevant information’.Footnote 107

Spain v Council expresses a general standard of ‘adequate reasoning’ and ‘relevant information’

If we generalise the Court’s propositions from Spain v Council, it is contended that this case suggests a standard of legality both in relation to reasoning and evidence. The benchmark is whether the EU legislator provided for ‘adequate reasoning’ and took into account ‘relevant circumstances’ when it exercised its legislative competence.

The expression ‘relevant information’ used by the Court implicitly connotes a requirement in relation to the quality of the reasoning. The Court of Justice was not only critical of the fact that the Commission had failed to include labour costs and perform a socio-impact study; it also condemned the fact that the Commission had been unable to explain why an impact study was not necessary and why labour costs were not included in the assessment of profitability.Footnote 108 The Court’s assessment of the profitability study is instructive. The Council, basing its argument on the reform’s budgetary neutrality, contended that the profitability study should also take into account the income deriving from the single payment. Since the sum of the coupled and decoupled aid under the new scheme was equivalent to the total amount of the indirect aid granted under the previous scheme, the profitability of cotton growing could not be doubted according to the Council. The single payment should not be taken into account, according to the Court, as it is granted independently of the crop chosen, even if the farmer decides not to produce anything. The budgetary neutrality of the reform was furthermore of no relevance for assessing whether in the future farmers will abandon cotton growing.Footnote 109 The standard of ‘relevant circumstances’ furthermore entails a requirement with regard to the quality of the evidence. In Spain v Council, the Court itself decided what constituted ‘relevant’ information for deciding upon the amount of aid. The Court found that fixed labour costs should have been included in the profitability assessment under the new support scheme and that the effect of the reform on the situation of the ginning undertakings was also ‘relevant information’ without which the Commission could not exercise its discretion.Footnote 110

A proposed standard for review and test for legality

The proposed benchmark suggests a two-step examination of legality of EU measures. The first part of the enquiry implies that the Court of Justice should look ‘beyond the preamble of the measure’ when examining the adequacy of the reasoning and consider whether the reasons stated by the EU legislator in the ‘legislative background documents’Footnote 111 are pertinent for assessing compliance with the principles in Article 5 TEU. The test to assess whether the standard of ‘adequate reasoning’ has been conformed to is the following. The EU legislator must offer at least one justification that is by itself sufficiently compelling to justify compliance with the relevant principle or rule whose observance the institutions must ensure.Footnote 112 The reference point for the adequacy of the reasoning is the substantive justifications for the exercise of EU competences, as this has been generally recognised in the EU law literature and/or the Court’s case law. One example is if the EU legislator employs an argument based on distortions of competition to justify the ‘essentiality’ of criminal sanctions under Article 83(2) TFEU.Footnote 113 Since the question of ‘essentiality’ of criminal laws under this provision is only concerned with a comparison of criminal laws with other sanctions, it seems incoherent to mingle internal market considerations into this assessment.Footnote 114 Such considerations are not ‘relevant factors’Footnote 115 . ‘Adequate’ reasoning does not, however, require that the EU legislator offered the most appropriate reasoning for defending compliance with the precepts of the Treaties.Footnote 116 It is sufficient that the reasoning is ‘adequate’ to support adherence to the underlying Treaty condition or principle.Footnote 117

The second limb of the test considers whether the reasons are substantiated. In order to pass this part of the test, the EU legislator needs to show that the rationale given for the legislative act (which in itself justified the EU legislator’s adherence to the relevant EU rule or principle) is supported by sufficient and relevant evidence.Footnote 118

This standard entails requirements both in relation to the quantity and quality of the evidence. First, in order to prove a statement, it is necessary to refer to more than one source. If, for example, the evidence for a theoretically-plausible claim consists of a reference to only one study or one scholarly article, this would be insufficient.Footnote 119 The Court ought furthermore to examine whether the evidence in the legislative background documents is ‘adequate’ for substantiating the exercise of the legislative competence.Footnote 120 Taking again the example of EU criminal law competence, it is suggested that if the EU legislator uses evidence concerning ‘distortions of competition’ to justify the ‘essentiality’ of criminal sanctions it would also fail to conform to the standard of ‘relevant evidence’. This is because the ‘essentiality’ of criminal sanctions can only be justified on the basis of evidence showing that criminal sanctions are a greater deterrent than other sanctions.Footnote 121 The evidence should finally be ‘reliable’. Insignificant evidence or evidence of low credibility (such as hearsay evidence) cannot be used to support a statement. This means that the evidence needs to be in the nature of statistical studies, policy studies or scientific articles that provide more serious support for an argument.Footnote 122

Rationale and issues with the test

The following considers the purpose of the test. The test is not a substantive one intended to limit EU action or finding out the proper level of action.Footnote 123 The test is functional to ensure that the political discretion granted to EU an institution is exercised in a rational manner and that the Court is empowered to review the exercise of EU competences.Footnote 124 Since the proposed test requires reasons and evidence to always be given for the exercise of competences, it is more likely that the Court will be able to fulfil its task of monitoring that the law of the Treaties is observed.Footnote 125 The pragmatic rationale for the test is that it is predictable by clearly articulating under which circumstances intervention is justified.Footnote 126 The reference point here is whether one of the reasons relied upon in a legislative act constitutes sufficient basis to support that act and is substantiated by relevant evidence.Footnote 127

The main critique against this test of legality is probably that the proposed requirement on the EU legislator of offering ‘one cogent reason supported with sufficient evidence’ is borrowed from the Court of Justice’s case law on fundamental rights and targeted sanctionsFootnote 128 and its case law in the field of competition law/risk regulationFootnote 129 and that the concerns underlying this standard of review may not be applicable in the field of common policies. In the context of targeted sanctions, the strict interpretation of ‘manifest error’ has partly been driven by the limitations imposed on courts reviewing the Security Council resolutions that form the basis for EU regulations freezing assets of particular individuals and the fact those decisions have substantive negative effects for targeted individuals.Footnote 130 In relation to competition law, the strict review of ‘manifest error’ have been driven by the criticisms voiced about the role of the Commission as prosecutor, judge, and jury, and the fact that competition law enforcement is intrinsically concerned with potential infringements of the fundamental rights for the accused.Footnote 131

In this regard, it is important to underline that Court of Justice’s standard of review and intensity is not dependent upon whether review is undertaken in a specific area such as fundamental rights, internal market or competition law. The key rationale for stringent review in the discussed fundamental rightsFootnote 132 and competition law and risk/regulation cases is related to the fact that these cases were concerned with ‘individual decisions’ or decisions of a similar nature. It is clear that the EU Courts in such cases are tasked with reviewing both the factual and legal assessment of the administrative agency or legislator, i.e. the Commission. Although the freezing of assets cases were concerned with regulations, those acts were in fact in the nature of individual decisions rather than general legislative acts. In Kadi II, Tetra Laval and Pfizer, it is clear that there were targeted individuals and firms that were the subject of the decision/regulation. When the EU legislator acts more as an executive than as a general legislature, less deference is justified because the effects of annulment are less draconian, because strict review of individual decisions does not encroach upon the EU legislator’s political discretion and because individuals must be protected against discretionary interferences with their fundamental freedoms.Footnote 133 In relation to judicial review of the EU legislator’s discretionary policy choices, other considerations are relevant. It might be argued that scrutiny in the context of broad EU common policies should be very deferential because the facts are complex, since the EU legislator undertakes discretionary policy choices and because the EU legislature has to reconcile divergent interests when making such policies. In these cases, the Court is also normally tasked with reviewing a broad piece of framework legislation, which may have been subject to cumbersome negotiations between the different EU institutions, and which are envisaged to generally approximate Member States’ legislation in a certain field. It is clear that the Court may less willing to frustrate polices that have come at such a high cost.Footnote 134

The division in the case law between review of general legislative acts and acts being primarily addressed to certain individuals thus suggest that there must be a justification for transferring the intense test derived from the Court’s case law in Tetra Laval and Kadi II to the field of the common policies.Footnote 135 It is, however, suggested that a distinction must be made between the ‘test’ for legality and the ‘intensity’ of the review. The argument here does not suggest that the Court of Justice should review with the same intensity general EU legislative acts as it does administrative decisions. ‘Manifest error’ review in the style of Tetra Laval and Kadi II is strict substantive review that is used when the Court examines individual administrative decisions. Such review entails a de novo assessment of the legal and factual assessment made by the administrative agency.Footnote 136 Such a review is different from review of EU legislation in vertical competence disputes, which cannot be as intensive, as this would upset the principle of institutional balance.Footnote 137 It is only claimed here that the test, i.e. whether the EU legislator offered at least one compelling rationale for exercising competence and whether that reason was supported with ‘relevant’ evidence, should be analogous to the one adopted for review of administrative decisions.Footnote 138

This being so, it is a legitimate concern that the proposed test may encroach on the EU legislator’s discretion and entail substitution of judgment. If the Court were to apply the test as proposed here, there would be a risk that the Court might exceed the limits of its ‘authority’ and ‘legitimacy’ as derived from the Treaties. Whether this criticism can be sustained depends on ‘how’ the test, if it ever finds its way into the Court of Justice’s jurisprudence, is applied by the Court. If the Court applies the proposed test with the same rigour as it has done in fundamental rights and competition law/risk regulation cases and substantively re-examines the EU legislator’s political assessment,Footnote 139 this would entail an encroachment on the EU legislator’s discretion. Then, the Court should face criticism. If the Court, however, reviews legislation according to the guidelines provided above, the concern that the test would lead to substitution of judgment will be undermined.Footnote 140

Finally, whilst an evidence criterion in cases of competence review has not yet been fully embraced by the Court of Justice, there are implicit foundations in the case law to construct such a requirement. This suggests that it would not be such a bold move for the Court to apply the proposed test for legality. As we saw above, there was a requirement imposed in Spain v Council, that compliance with the proportionality principle needed to be defended by specific figures and evidence.Footnote 141 More importantly, it is argued that the Tobacco Advertising judgment indicates a firm evidence criterion for the EU legislature to fulfil when legislating under Article 114 TFEU. The Court stated in this judgment that it is not sufficient to show ‘hypothetical’ risks of obstacles. The EU legislator must thus show that disparities give rise to concrete obstacles or that it is likely that such obstacles will arise. The Court of Justice also clarified that the EU legislator cannot rely on incidental or potential distortions as justifications for harmonisation – instead it must demonstrate that the distortions of competition at issue are ‘appreciable’.Footnote 142

Furthermore, although cases such as Test Achat and Volker und Martin Schecke on fundamental rights cannot be used as evidence for a transformation to stricter ‘competence review’, it appears that the intense review in Spain v Council was endorsed in those judgments. In both these cases, which focused on the EU legislator’s justification for infringing the right to personal data (Volker und Martin Schecke)Footnote 143 and the right to equality (Test Achat),Footnote 144 the Court made a strict procedural enquiry of the EU legislator’s justification. The Court considered in Volker und Schenke that the EU legislator had not done its preparatory work properly, by failing to consider alternatives which interfered less with the fundamental rights of the beneficiaries concerned. In Test Achat the Court condemned the EU legislator because there was a contradiction between the challenged provision (which entailed an extension for Member States to apply discriminatory premiums to male and female beneficiaries) and the objectives pursued by the contested EU act that pursued the principle of non-discrimination. There is no good reason why the Court cannot use its approach in these fundamental right cases to also review challenges based on Article 5 TEU.Footnote 145

Whilst it is not possible to comprehensively discuss here whether the standard of judicial enforcement of federal values should be as intense as rights-based review, the argument here is sympathetic to Lynn Baker and Ernest Young’s compelling narrative on ‘double standards’. They suggest that there are no normative justifications for courts to discriminate between enforcement of human rights and implementation of federal values. On this basis, discrete enforcement of certain values of the EU constitutional order should be rejected on the ground that the values protected by that order should be of equal importance. It therefore appears that the recognition of limits on EU legislative authority and protection of state rights ultimately will increase the sphere of individual autonomy (which is one of the key rationales for rights-based review). Member States can act as a strong safeguard of individual freedoms since they are capable of imposing more serious obstacles to intrusive governmental interferences than those that individuals could achieve alone.Footnote 146 Judicial scrutiny of EU criminal law legislation under Article 83(2) TFEU illustrates this point. It is arguable that intense judicial review of the conditions in this provision, in particular the ‘essentiality’ condition, is justified by the fact that criminalisation tends to encroach on the fundamental freedom of liberty. Thus, a strict enforcement of the balance of powers between the Member States and the EU within this context would surely have the implications that individuals will be protected from intrusions into their personal autonomy.Footnote 147

The relationship of the proposed test to the EU Courts’ current approach

Whilst the genesis of the proposed standard springs from Spain v Council and the concrete test is derived from the Court’s manifest error review in Kadi II, it develops the Court of Justice’s intensity further than the Court’s current approach to review of EU legislation.

It appears that the Court’s current case law does not entail making informational demands on the Union legislator. The Court has never in its previous jurisprudence imposed any requirement to submit evidence for compliance with certain requirements of the Treaties such as ‘quantitative’ indicators in relation to subsidiarity or ‘appreciable distortions to competition’ in Article 114 TFEU. The Court seems to accept simple assertions of the EU institutions on the existence of effects or problems. In fact, it seems that the Court, instead of standing outside the legislative procedure, endeavours to support the EU legislator’s case by seriously looking for any evidence and reasoning that can justify compliance with the precepts of the Treaties.Footnote 148

The proposed test does not accept insufficient evidence for establishing compliance with Article 5 TEU. The Court must reverse its light test for judicial intervention and strike down legislation that contains assertions that are not justified by the facts of the case. Contrary to the Court’s approach in Germany v Council Footnote 149 and Swedish Match,Footnote 150 the suggested test does not accept mere reference to preambles as justification for legislation, but requires references to evidence in legislative background documents. The Court must also consider, in contrast to cases such as Vodafone Footnote 151 and Alliance Health,Footnote 152 whether the evidence is connected to the rationale for exercising the competence.

While this does not mean that a proper impact assessment is a requirement for legality, it does imply that the EU legislator must refer to empirical evidence, whether that be a scientific study, scholarly articles or statistics, to support the measure.Footnote 153 Admittedly, it appears that the test as applied to proportionality review will rarely result in annulment of EU legislation. The intensity of the test, however, entails that the EU courts would have to inquire more and in greater depth into the claim that the decision was ‘manifestly inappropriate’, as compared to the classical approach.Footnote 154 Instead of simply clearing the Union legislator by noting that he has not crossed the barrier of ‘manifestly inappropriate’, the standard forces the Court to autonomously determine whether the EU legislator has supported his conclusions by relevant evidence.Footnote 155 The key distinction from the Court’s current approach is thus that the proposal here asks the Court to be more intrusive when considering whether the necessary facts have been taken into account before exonerating the EU legislator.

Conclusions and reflections

The concluding part of this article contains a summary of the argument and reflections on the proposed model’s consequences for the federal dimension of EU law.

The aim of this contribution was to examine the problems of judicial review within the context of enforcing the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU. In particular, it queried how the Court of Justice, given the absence of appropriate legal criteria and institutional constraints, could develop a more intense form of judicial review in competence disputes. The main proposal for improving enforcement of conferral, subsidiarity and proportionality was to use a procedural type of review, requiring the Court to examine the EU legislator’s reasoning and evidence for a legislative measure. A move for the Court to stronger substantive review was rejected by reference to institutional constraints in terms of legitimacy and competence.Footnote 156 To some extent it appears that procedural review suffers from similar problems that are associated with substantive review. A procedural review is nevertheless less controversial in terms of institutional competence and democratic legitimacy than substantive review. Thereto, any disadvantages with a procedural form of review would be outweighed by the advantages of greater legitimacy in the EU decision-making procedure that such a review would entail.Footnote 157

The article subsequently developed, on the basis of the Court’s judgment in Spain v Council, a specific standard of review for all broad EU policy measures. This standard suggests that the EU legislator must offer ‘adequate reasoning’ and ‘relevant evidence’ for a proposed legislative measure in order for it to conform to the limits of the Treaties.Footnote 158 To control whether the proposed standard of ‘adequate reasoning’ and ‘relevant evidence’ has been met, the article proposed on the basis of the Court’s ruling in Kadi II an intrusive test of legality. The EU legislator must articulate at least one justification, which in theory – i.e. in light of the relevant literature and the Court’s case law – is sufficient as a basis for exercising the competence and substantiate this rationale by ‘sufficient’ and ‘relevant’ evidence. Such a demanding test was justified on the basis that it would push the EU legislator to prepare more evidence-based justification and ultimately restore confidence in the EU political procedure.

What are, then, the implications of the argument advanced in this article? It appears that the proposed model is likely to have bearings for the federal dimension of EU law: the relationship between the EU and its Member States. The suggested process-based test is intended to be employed in highly-contested challenges to EU legislation on the basis of proportionality, subsidiarity and lack of ‘competence’/incorrect legal basis. The Court’s approach to these principles has serious constitutional implications for the Union legal order by shaping the distribution of competences and by defining the standards for examining the legality of a Union act.Footnote 159

Critics of the test may argue that it will negatively affect the process of EU integration by imposing too cumbersome limits on the discretion of the EU legislator. Strict judicial review of the exercise of EU competences would compromise the Union’s capacity to act efficiently in order to fulfil the tasks of the Treaties and would impose significant costs reflected in inflexibility. They may also argue that the test will stretch the Court of Justice’s institutional capacities and force it to become involved in deeply political and constitutional choices on the future of EU integration and that the Courts lack the democratic credentials to make those choices.Footnote 160

There is force in this point, as the proposed test may push the Court to the limits of its legitimacy and authority. However, counterintuitively, legitimacy may be the best argument for the Court to enforce the constitutional principles in Article 5 TEU more seriously after Lisbon. Infusing judicial review of EU legislation with greater force is, as argued above, not only a way of enhancing the accountability of the EU legislative procedure but also the legitimacy of the Court of Justice.Footnote 161 The Court of Justice was created with the aim of providing an unbiased arbitrator to mediate between the interests of the EU and the Member States. The Court’s approach to date is, however, inadequate as a safeguard of federalism.Footnote 162 The Court’s weak stance in vertical competence litigation has not only failed to promote a culture of justification in the EU legislative process, but has also devalued Member State rights, the observance of which the Court should ensure. If the Court continues on this path it will face legitimate criticism that it is failing in its task to ensure that the law of the Treaties is observed.Footnote 163 To address these concerns, the Court must change its current deferential approach and review the exercise of EU powers with more vigour. The Treaty of Lisbon also suggests that the Court should submit the exercise of the EU competences to stricter control. By providing for a special review procedure for national parliaments of EU legislation,Footnote 164 by adopting a specific protocol on subsidiarity and proportionality,Footnote 165 by adopting a new provision for the protection of the constitutional identity of Member StatesFootnote 166 and by restating throughout the Treaties the importance of the principle of conferral,Footnote 167 the Member States have made a conscious decision to construct new limits to the exercise of EU powers.Footnote 168

Finally, even if the strict procedural review advanced here ultimately imposes substantive limits on the exercise of Union competences, there are good reasons for the Court to enforce those constraints. The Court has indeed an important role as guarantor of the values of federalism – such as local experimentation and potential for innovation, efficiency, participatory democracy, regulatory competition among jurisdictions, adaptation to local preferences, and governmental accountability to voters – in cases where the Union legislator fails to adhere to such values.Footnote 169 It is evident that the Union political institutions take indications from the Court as to what values should be safeguarded. If the Court were to announce that the issue of federalism is entirely subject to the whims of politics, the Union political branches would not take these values seriously in their own deliberations.Footnote 170 The Court of Justice is therefore tasked with ensuring the balance between Member States and the Union as set down in the TreatiesFootnote 171 and to make each of these constitutive units responsible for the exercise of their own powers.Footnote 172 The Court even stated in the Tobacco Advertising judgment that giving the EU legislator a general regulatory power under Article 114 TFEU would be contrary to the principle of conferral and absolve the Court from its duties under Article 19 TEU to uphold the law of the Treaties.Footnote 173

Whilst recognising that the Court also must impose some substantive limits on EU legislative authority,Footnote 174 the core argument still is that the values of federalism are best implemented by a strict procedural approach according to the lines suggested above. While the EU political institutions may be trusted to resolve most substantive disputes about EU policy, the Court of Justice is responsible for policing the system of political and institutional safeguards that the EU political process ordinarily rely on to resolve most problems.Footnote 175 Ultimately, it is envisaged that a stringent process-based judicial review of the EU law-making process will help us in reinstating the balance of powers between Member States and the Union and enable the Court to better protect Member State autonomy against the risk of illegitimate EU centralisation.Footnote 176

While genuinely engaging in the enforcement of the EU federal order of competences is a difficult constitutional choice, which implies that the Court must develop a stricter standard of review and become involved in fundamental political and social questions, it is argued that such a review is both necessary and legitimate to maintain the division of powers between the EU and its Member States.Footnote 177 Unless the Court steps up this challenge, EU constitutional law would regrettably have to rely solely on political control as a safeguard of federalism in the EU.

Footnotes

*

Associate Professor in Law, Örebro University. This article is the outcome of a discussion with many academic colleagues and friends throughout the last three years. I would wish to particularly acknowledge the valuable comments and constructive criticisms from Giorgio Monti, Loïc Azoulai, Damian Chalmers, Stephen Coutts, Christian Ayerst, Thomas Poole, Valsamis Mitsilegas and Carl-Fredrik Bergström. The editors of the European Constitutional Law Review and the anonymous reviewers deserve a special acknowledgment, as their comments and proposals really helped in improving the final form of the article. I furthermore owe intellectual debt to Ittai Bar-Siman-Tov, Koen Lenaerts and Ernest A. Young for their work on procedural review and federalism in the EU.

References

1 Waldron, J., ‘The Core of the Case against Judicial Review’, 115 Yale Law Journal (2006) p. 1346 at p. 1357-58CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Lenaerts, K., ‘Constitutionalism and the Many Faces of Federalism’, 38 American Journal of Comparative Law (1990) p. 205 at p. 206Google Scholar.

3 Craig, P., ‘The ECJ and Ultra Vires Action: a Conceptual Analysis’, 48 Common Market Law Review (2011) p. 395 at p. 396-397, 410Google Scholar; Weatherill, S., ‘The Limits of Legislative Harmonisation Ten Years after Tobacco Advertising: How the Court’s Case Law Has Become a “Drafting Guide”’, 12 German Law Journal (2011) p. 827 at p. 851CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Komesar, N., ‘A Job for the Judges: The Judiciary and the Constitution in a Massive and Complex Society’, 86 Michigan Law Review (1988) p. 658 at p. 659Google Scholar.

5 Ibid., p. 690-699.

6 Art. 5 TEU.

7 19 Journal of European Public Policy (2012) Special Issue: ‘Perpetual Momentum? Reconsidering the Power of the European Court of Justice’; Stone Sweet, A., The Judicial Construction of Europe (Oxford University Press 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Weiler, J.H.H., ‘The Transformation of Europe’, 100 Yale Law Journal (1991) p. 2403 at p. 2433-2447Google Scholar.

8 Weatherill, supra n. 3, p. 850-852.

9 ECJ 4 May 2016, Case C-547/14, Philip Morris Brands, paras. 107-125, 127-136. See, for equally deferential review in relation to Art.114 TFEU: ECJ 10 December 2002, Case C-491/01, British American Tobacco (Investments) and Imperial Tobacco [2002] ECR I-11453, paras. 81-88; ECJ 14 December 2004, Case C-210/03, Swedish Match [2004] ECR I-11893, paras. 35-40; ECJ 8 June 2010, Case C-58/08, Vodafone [2010] ECR I-04999, paras. 38-47; 9 October 2001, Case C-377/98, Netherlands v Parliament and Council [2001] ECR I-07079, paras. 14-18, 20-22, 24-25, 27-29.

10 Philip Morris Brands, supra n. 9, paras. 165-166. This light proportionality review of EU legislation is consistent with the Court’s previous case law: ECJ 12 March 2002, Joined Cases C-27/00 and C-122/00, Omega Air and other joined cases [2000] ECR I-2569, paras. 63-64; British American Tobacco (Investments) and Imperial Tobacco, supra n. 10, para. 123; ECJ 12 November 1996, C-84/94, United Kingdom v Council [1996] ECR I-05755, para. 58.

11 Philip Morris Brands, supra n. 9, paras. 171-191; Swedish Match, supra n. 9, paras. 48-57; ECJ 12 May 2011, Case C-176/09, Luxembourg v Parliament and Council [2011] ECR I-03727; paras. 62-72.

12 Philip Morris Brands, supra n. 9, paras. 220-226. See also ECJ 12 July 2005, Joined Cases C-154/04 and 155/04, Alliance for Natural Health [2005] ECR I-06451, paras. 104-107; ECJ 13 May 1997, Case C-233/94, Germany v Parliament and Council [1997] ECR I-02405, paras. 26-28; Vodafone, supra n. 9, paras. 72-80, for the Court’s low intensity review of subsidiarity.

13 I.e. legislation such as directives and regulations that is generally binding for everyone: see Art. 288 TFEU.

14 The distinction between these two forms of review is outlined below in the section ‘The case for strict procedural review’.

15 Craig, P., EU Administrative Law (Oxford University Press 2012) p. 400-445 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 See, for the general institutional argument against judicial review, Komesar, supra n. 4, p. 665, 668-690, 697; Daly, P., A Theory of Deference in Administrative Law: Basis, Application and Scope (Cambridge University Press 2012) p. 70-137 Google Scholar.

17 Scott, J. and Sturm, S., ‘Courts as Catalysts: Rethinking the Judicial Role in New Governance’, 13 Columbia Journal of European Law (2007) p. 565 at p. 569Google Scholar.

18 Gerards, J.H., ‘Pluralism, Deference and the Margin of Appreciation Doctrine’, 17 European Law Journal (2011) p. 80 at p. 86; Waldron, supra n. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Schütze, R., From Dual to Cooperative Federalism (Oxford University Press 2009) p. 136-139 Google Scholar.

20 Davies, G., ‘Democracy and Legitimacy in the Shadow of Purposive Competence’, 21 European Law Journal (2015) p. 2 at p. 4, 6; doi:10.1111/eulj.120794 Google Scholar.

21 Lindberg, L.N., The Political Dynamics of European Economic Integration (Stanford University Press 1963) p. 284 Google Scholar, 290, 293.

22 Weatherill, S., ‘Competence Creep and Competence Control’, 23 Yearbook of European Law (2004) p. 1 at p. 13-17, 25, 27, 46, 49; Schütze, supra n. 19, p. 136-156CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Pescatore, P., Law of Integration: Emergence of a New Phenomenon in International Relations, Based on the Experience of the European Communities (Springer 1974, English translation) p. 40-43 Google Scholar, 50-51.

24 Azoulai, L., ‘Introduction: the Question of Competence’, in L. Azoulai (ed.), The Question of Competence in the European Union (Oxford University Press 2014) p. 2 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 5-6.

25 See the literature in n. 7 supra for support of this point.

26 Swedish Match, supra n. 9, paras. 33-34; Vodafone, supra n. 9, para. 35.

27 See the cases referred to in n. 9 supra.

28 Bermann, G.A.Taking Subsidiarity Seriously’, 94 Columbia Law Review (1994) p. 332 at p. 337, 385-386, 391-394,400Google Scholar; Estrella, A., The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique (Oxford University Press 2002) p. 139 Google Scholar, 147, 165, 176.

29 See n. 12 supra for references to relevant case law.

30 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 592-593, 600-604, 629-630, 639.

31 See the cases in n. 11 supra for support.

32 Alemanno, A.The Emergence of Evidence-based Judicial Reflex: A Response to Bar-Siman-Tov’s Semiprocedural Review’, 1 The Theory and Practice of Legislation (2013) p. 327 Google Scholar; Coenen, D.T., ‘The Pros and Cons of Politically Reversible “Semisubstantive” Constitutional Rules’, 77 Fordham Law Review (2008–2009) p. 2835 Google Scholar; Bar-Siman-Tov, I., ‘Semiprocedural Judicial Review’, 6 Legisprudence (2012) p. 271 Google Scholar.

33 Case C- 310/04, Spain v Council [2006] ECR I-07285, paras. 122-123.

34 Lenaerts, K., ‘The European Court of Justice and Process-Oriented Review’, 31 Yearbook of European Law (2012) p. 3 Google Scholar, 4, 15.

35 Bar-Siman-Tov, supra n. 32, p. 272, 275, 279–280; Alemanno, supra n. 32, p. 332, 334-335.

36 See above text to nn. 16-19.

37 Lenaerts, supra n. 34, p. 15-16; Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 575.

38 See above in the section ‘Institutional and conceptual problems of vertical competence review’ for an outline of this problem.

39 Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 582, 586, 588, 590; Alemanno, supra n. 32, p. 333-336, 338.

40 See Art 296 TFEU.

41 See Shapiro, M., ‘The Giving Reasons Requirement’, University of Chicago Legal Forum (1992) p. 179 at p. 179 Google Scholar, 184-186, 188-189, 202, 206, 209-210, 218; Bryant, C. and Simeone, T.J., ‘Remanding to Congress: The Supreme Court’s New “On the Record” Constitutional Review of Federal Statutes’, 86 Cornell Law Review (2001) p. 328 at p. 395-396Google Scholar.

42 See Lenaerts, supra n. 34, p. 4, 15; Hammond, E. and Markell, D.L., ‘Administrative Proxies for Judicial Review: Building Legitimacy from the Inside-out’, 37 Harvard Environmental Law Review (2013) p. 313 Google Scholar, 316, 321-326; Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 590-591.

43 See ECJ 12 July 2001, Case C-189/01, Jippes v Minister van Landbouw, Natuurbeheer en Visserij [2001] ECR I-5689, para. 83.

44 ECJ 11 July 1985, Case 42/84, Remia BV and Others v Commission [1985] ECR 2545; Shapiro, supra n. 41, p. 214.

45 Remia BV and Others v Commission, supra n. 44, paras. 34-36.

46 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 617-618.

47 Ibid., p. 629-630, 636-639; ECJ 11 December 2011, Case C-438/05, International Transport Workers’ Federation and Finnish Seamen’s Union v Viking Line ABP and OÜ Viking Line Eesti [2007] ECR I-10779, paras. 77-90. See, however, ECJ 18 December 2007, Case C-341/05, Laval un Partneri [2007] ECR I-11767, paras. 101-111 for the problematic distinction between ‘interpretation’ and ‘application’ of proportionality within the context of preliminary ruling procedures.

48 Lenaerts, K., ‘Federalism: Essential Concepts in Evolution – The Case of the European Union’, 21 Fordham International Law Journal (1997) p. 746 at p. 795-797Google Scholar.

49 Kumm, M., ‘Constitutionalizing Subsidiarity in Integrated Markets: The Case of Tobacco Regulation in the European Union’, 12 European Law Journal (2006) p. 503 at p. 528CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Davies, G., ‘Subsidiarity: the Wrong Idea, in the Wrong Place, at the Wrong Time’, 43 Common Market Law Review (2006) p. 63 at p. 68-69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Bryant and Simeone, supra n. 41, p. 383-388, 391-392; Frickey, P.P. and Smith, S.S., ‘Judicial Review, the Congressional Process, and the Federalism Cases: an Interdisciplinary Critique’, 111 Yale Law Journal (2002) p. 1707 at p. 1740-1744, 1750, 1754Google Scholar.

51 See above text to n. 18 for the general democratic argument against judicial review.

52 Neubome, B., ‘Judicial Review and Separation of Powers in France and the United States’, 57 New York University Law Review (1982) p. 363 at p. 364-367Google Scholar; Wellington, H.H., ‘The Nature of Judicial Review’, 91 Yale Law Journal (1982) p. 486 at p. 504-505Google Scholar.

53 Walen, A., ‘Judicial Review in Review: A Four-Part Defense of Legal Constitutionalism. A Review Essay on Political Constitutionalism, by Richard Bellamy’, 7 International Journal of Constitutional Law (2009) p. 329 Google Scholar; Lever, A., ‘Democracy and Judicial Review: Are They Really Incompatible?’, 7 Perspectives on Politics (2009) p. 805 for general arguments in favour of judicial review on democratic groundsGoogle Scholar.

54 It is open to discussion if this is a fair comparison: see Craig, P., ‘Democracy and Rule-making Within the EC: An Empirical and Normative Assessment’, 3 European Law Journal (1997) p. 105 at p. 114-119, for a more nuanced assessment of the nature of democracy in the UnionGoogle Scholar.

55 Waldron, , supra n. 1, p. 1361-1362 Google Scholar.

56 Craig, P., The Lisbon Treaty: Law, Politics and Treaty Reform (Oxford University Press 2011) p. 73-74 Google Scholar; Young, E.A., ‘Protecting Member State Autonomy in the European Union: Some Cautionary Tales from American Federalism’, 77 New York University Law Review (2002) p. 1612 at p. 1638-1639Google Scholar.

57 De Búrca, G., ‘The Quest for Legitimacy in the European Union’, 59 Modern Law Review (1996) p. 349 at p. 367-376, for earlier assessments of the state of legitimacy in the UnionCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 The European Ombudsman, ‘Annual Report 2011’ (2011) p. 6 <www.ombudsman.europa.eu/activities/annualreports.faces;jsessionid=36BB77F9D3E8B63EDAAE9C73470AA169>, visited 27 March 2017. See also European Commission, ‘Special Eurobarometer 397 – Corruption’ (2014), <ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/ebs/ebs_397_en.pdf>, visited 27 March 2017, for the continuous transparency problems.

59 Hofmann, H.C.H. et al., Administrative Law and Policy of the European Union (Oxford University Press 2011) p. 170-171 Google Scholar; Craig, supra n. 54, p. 110-111.

60 Gangl, A., ‘Procedural Justice Theory and Evaluations of the Lawmaking Process’, 25 Political Behavior (2003) p. 119 at p. 119-132Google Scholar; Bar-Siman-Tov, I., ‘The Puzzling Resistance to Judicial Review of the Legislative Process’, 91 Buffalo Law Review (2011) p. 1915 at p. 1927-1931Google Scholar; Tyler, T.R., ‘Governing amid Diversity: The Effect of Fair Decision-making Procedures on the Legitimacy of Government’, 28 Law & Society Review (1994) p. 809 at p. 809-811, 813, 818-826Google Scholar; Delli Carpini, M.X. et al., ‘Public Deliberation, Discursive Participation and Citizen Engagement: A Review of the Empirical Literature’, 7 Annual Review of Political Science (2004) p. 315 at p. 320, 327, 336CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 Social legitimacy, as defined here, suggests that decisions are legitimate if the relevant public sees them as deserving support for reasons beyond fear of sanctions: see Fallon, R.H., ‘Legitimacy and the Constitution’, 118 Harvard Law Review (2005) p. 1787 at p. 1794-1801Google Scholar.

62 Leczykiewicz, D., ‘“Constitutional Justice” and Judicial Review of EU Legislative Acts’, (2013) Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper No 95/2013, p. 2-3, <ssrn.com/abstract=2355961>, visited 27 March 2017Google Scholar.

63 ECJ 4 July 1096, Case 24/62, Germany v Commission [1963] ECR 131, 69; Alliance for Natural Health and Others, supra n. 12, para. 133; Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 572.

64 Legal legitimacy depends on adherence to rules and suggests that decision of a public body is illegitimate if it transgresses some norm itself considered authoritative when it exercises its powers: see Fallon, supra n. 61.

65 Poole, T., ‘Legitimacy, Rights and Judicial Review’, 25 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (2005) p. 697 at p. 713-717, 722, 725Google Scholar; Hammond, and Markell, , supra n. 42, p. 316 Google Scholar, 321-326.

66 Scott, and Sturm, , supra n. 17, p. 570-571 Google Scholar, 582-583; Kumm, M., ‘The Idea of Socratic Contestation and the Right to Justification: The Point of Rights based Proportionality Review’, 4 Law and Ethics of Human Rights (2010) p. 142 at p. 153, 160-164.Google Scholar

67 Poole, supra n. 65, p. 719, 724. See Dworkin, R., Law’s Empire (Harvard University Press 1986) p. 176-276 for an examination of the concept of ‘integrity’ in the lawGoogle Scholar.

68 Alemanno, A., ‘Regulatory Impact Assessment and European Courts: When Ex Ante Evaluation Meets Ex Post Judicial Control’, 17 European Public Law (2011) p. 485, 499-503; Lenaerts, supra n. 34, p. 4-10; Schütze, supra n. 19, p. 255-256Google Scholar.

69 There are other intriguing cases on intense procedural review such as ECJ 9 November 2010, Case C-92/09, Volker und Martin Schecke and Eifert [2010] ECR I-11063 and ECJ 1 March 2011, Case C-236/09, Association belge des Consommateurs Test-Achats and Others [2011] ECR I-00773 concerned with procedural review and fundamental rights. Whilst these judgments potentially may have implications for the general allocation of powers between the Member States and the EU, they cannot be characterised as ‘competence disputes’ which is the main focus of this article.

70 Germany v Parliament and Council, supra n. 12.

71 Ibid., paras. 27-28.

72 Netherlands v Parliament and Council, supra n. 9, para. 33; Philip Morris Brands, supra n. 9, paras. 225-226 for equally feeble application of procedural subsidiarity.

73 See also the fundamental rights case law mentioned in n. 69.

74 Spain v Council, supra n. 33.

75 Council Regulation (EC) No 1782/2003 of 29 September 2003 establishing common rules for direct support schemes under the common agricultural policy and establishing certain support schemes for farmers and amending Regulations (EEC) No 2019/93, (EC) No 1452/2001, (EC) No 1453/2001, (EC) No 1454/2001, (EC) No 1868/94, (EC) No 1251/1999, (EC) No 1254/1999, (EC) No 1673/2000, (EEC) No 2358/71 and (EC) No 2529/2001 [2003] OJ 2003 L 270/1, inserted by Art. 1(20) of Council Regulation (EC) No 864/2004 of 29 April 2004 [2004] OJ 2004 L 161/48.

76 The case is discussed meticulously in the following sections.

77 Spain v Council, supra n. 33, paras. 122-135

78 Groussout, X. and Bogojevic, S., ‘Subsidiarity as a Procedural Safeguard of Federalism’, in Azoulai (ed.), supra n. 24, p. 246 Google Scholar, 252 for this observation. The Court referred to the impact assessments and explanatory memorandum in no less than eight paragraphs: see Vodafone, supra n. 9, paras. 39, 43, 45, 55, 58, 59, 63, 65.

79 Spain v Council, supra n. 33, para. 122.

80 Vodafone, supra n. 9, paras. 68-69; Brenncke, M., ‘Case note on European Court of Justice, C-58/08, Vodafone Ltd and Others v Secretary of State for Business, Enterprise and Re’, 47 Common Market Law Review (2010) p. 1793 at p. 1809-1810CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

81 Brenncke, supra n. 80, p. 1801.

82 Directive 2009/30/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 23 April 2009 amending Directive 98/70/EC as regards the specification of petrol, diesel and gas-oil and introducing a mechanism to monitor and reduce greenhouse gas emissions and amending Council Directive 1999/32/EC as regards the specification of fuel used by inland waterway vessels and repealing Directive 93/12/EEC [2009] OJ 2009 L 140/88, Art. 1(8).

83 ECJ 8 July 2010, Case C-343/09, Afton Chemical [2010] ECR I-07027, para. 34.

84 Methylcyclopentadienyl manganese tricarbonyl; see Directive 2009/30/EC, supra n. 82, recital 35.

85 Afton Chemical, supra n. 83, paras. 30 36-42, 56-69.

86 See below in the subsection ‘Spain v Council expresses a general standard of “adequate reasoning” and “relevant information”’.

87 Spain v Council, supra n. 33; Vodafone, supra n. 9; Afton Chemical, supra n. 83.

88 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 389-390; Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 570-575.

89 See above in the section ‘Institutional and conceptual problems of vertical competence review’.

90 See in particular United States v Lopez 514 U.S. 549 (1995); United States v Morrisson 529 U.S. 598 (2000), which are seminal judgments on the scope of the Commerce Clause, the US equivalent of Art. 114 TFEU.

91 Vodafone, supra n. 9; Luxembourg v Parliament and Council, supra n. 11.

92 Spain v Council, supra n. 33, paras. 96-99, 104-105.

93 Ibid., paras. 120-123.

94 Ibid., paras. 102, 131-135.

95 Groussout, X., ‘Judgment C-310/04, Kingdom of Spain v Council of the European Union’, 44 Common Market Law Review (2007) p. 761 at p. 777-782; Alemanno, supra n. 68, p. 501Google Scholar.

96 See n. 69 supra for reference to Court judgments on fundamental rights reflecting high intensity review.

97 See, however, Jippes v Minister van Landbouw, Natuurbeheer en Visserij, supra n. 43, paras. 80-101, 113-122, for an exception of more searching proportionality review.

98 Now referred to as the ‘General Court’.

99 ECJ 11 September 2002, Case T-13/99, Pfizer Animal Health v Council [2002] ECR II-03305, paras. 166-170.

100 ECJ 25 October 2002, Case T-5/02, Tetra Laval v Commission [2002] ECR II-04381, paras. 119, 140-141, 197-199, 224, 283, 308, 335-336; ECJ 15 February 2005, Case C-12/03P, Commission v Tetra Laval [2005] ECR I-00987, paras. 38-39.

101 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 416-424, 427-430, 438-439.

102 Council Regulation (EC) No 2821/98 of 17 December 1998 amending, as regards withdrawal of the authorisation of certain antibiotics, Directive 70/524/EEC concerning additives in feeding stuffs [1998] OJ 1998 L 351/4.

103 Art. 263(3) TFEU; Pfizer Animal Health v Council, supra n. 99, paras. 42, 81-87, 89-106, 171-172.

104 Tetra Laval v Commission, supra n. 100, paras. 89-90.

105 Lenaerts, supra n. 34, p. 7-9, 15.

106 ECJ 13 November 1990, Case 331/88, R v Ministry of Agriculture, Fisheries and Food, ex p FEDESA [1990] ECR I-04023, para. 14; British American Tobacco (Investments) and Imperial Tobacco, supra n. 9, paras. 123, 130, 140.

107 Spain v Council, supra n. 33, paras. 110, 113-119, 131, 132-133.

108 Ibid., paras. 105-111, 116-118, 124-129, 131.

109 Ibid., paras. 108-111.

110 Ibid., paras. 112-118, 126, 128-132.

111 See n. 42 for this expression.

112 ECJ 18 July 2013, Joined cases C-584/10 P, C-593/10P and C-595/10P, Commission v Kadi (‘Kadi II’), para. 130.

113 See, for example, Commission, ‘Proposal for a Directive of the European Parliament and of the Council on criminal sanctions for insider dealing and market manipulation’, COM (2011) 654 final, 3, 5, recital 7.

114 Asp, P., The Substantive Criminal Law Competence of the EU—Towards an Area of Freedom, Security & Justice—Part 1 (Jure 2013) p. 130-132 Google Scholar; Whelan, P., ‘Contemplating the Future: Personal Criminal Sanctions for Infringement of EC Competition Law’, 19 King’s Law Journal (2008) p. 364 at p. 370-371CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

115 Spain v Council, supra n. 33, para. 122.

116 See a similar formula for the assessment of proportionality; Vodafone, supra n. 9, para. 52.

117 See the discussion above in the section ‘The case for strict procedural review’ of the risk that the Court’s review of the legislator’s reasoning is transformed into substantive review.

118 Kadi II, supra n. 112, paras. 119 and 124, 130. This standard for the ‘evidence ‘requirement is also supported by the Court’s ruling in Commission v Tetra Laval, supra n. 100, para. 39; ‘Not only must the Community Courts, inter alia, establish whether the evidence relied on is factually accurate, reliable and consistent but also whether that evidence contains all the information which must be taken into account in order to assess a complex situation and whether it is capable of substantiating the conclusions drawn from it.’

119 Alemanno, supra n. 32, p. 333-335, 338.

120 Kadi II, supra n. 112, paras. 118-119, 124.

121 See n. 114 for reference to literature supporting this point.

122 See Kadi II, supra n. 112, paras. 151-162 for the application of the evidence standard. What the Court does is to monitor whether any of the reasons submitted, which can support the decision, is supported by sufficient evidence (para. 162). This is the same method that the Court should apply in cases of review of EU legislation.

123 Art. 5 TEU.

124 Scott and Sturm, supra n. 17, p. 592-593. This test is, however, wider than the ‘rationality’ review used in some jurisdictions, which seems, within the realm of EU law, to be confined to questions primarily addressed by proportionality review, see further Craig, P., ‘Judicial Review and Questions of Law: A Comparative Perspective’, Legal Research Paper Series No 56/2009 October 2009, p. 7-8 Google Scholar, 11-12, 21-22, 26.

125 Art. 19 TEU; Shapiro, supra n. 41, p. 218-220.

126 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 434-436.

127 See above in the subsection ‘Spain v Council expresses a general standard of “adequate reasoning” and “relevant information”’.

128 See, for example, Kadi II, supra n. 112, paras. 119, 121, 122, 130; ECJ 12 May 2013, Case T-392/11, Iran Transfo v Council, paras. 34, 44; ECJ 29 June 2010, Case C-550/09, E and F [2010] ECR I-06213, para. 57.

129 See the cases referred to in nn. 99-100.

130 See n. 128 for reference to the relevant case law.

131 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 438-439.

132 Where EU fundamental rights have been used to challenge common policies, review has traditionally tended to be deferential: see eg British American Tobacco, supra n. 9, paras. 149-152; ECJ 9 September 2004, Cases C-184 and 223/02, Spain and Finland v European Parliament and Council [2004] ECR I-7789.

133 See above in the section ‘Analysis – why does Spain v Council provide an appropriate standard of review?’.

134 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 437-438, 592-593.

135 This division seems to be generally accepted for courts engaged in judicial review: see A.L. Young, ‘In Defence of Due Deference’, 72 Modern Law Review (2009) p. 554, 556-559.

136 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 434-436.

137 Art. 13(2) TEU.

138 Coenen, supra n. 32, p. 2887-2888.

139 See Toth, AG, ‘Is Subsidiarity Justiciable?’, 19 European Law Review (1994) p. 269 Google Scholar, 283-284, for an argument on how the application of subsidiarity may result in substitution of judgment.

140 Craig, supra n. 15, p. 433-34.

141 See above in the section ‘Analysis – why does Spain v Council provide an appropriate standard of review?’.

142 ECJ 5 October 2000, Case C-376/98, Germany v European Parliament and Council (Tobacco Advertising) [2000] ECR I-8419, paras. 84, 86, 98-99, 106-107.

143 Volker und Martin Schecke and Eifert, supra n. 69, paras. 65-89.

144 Association belge des Consommateurs Test-Achats, supra n. 69, paras. 25-32.

145 See n. 49 for reference to literature supporting this proposition.

146 Baker, L.A. and Young, E.A., ‘Federalism and the Double Standard of Judicial Review’, 51 Duke Law Journal (2001) p. 75, 133-162 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

147 Kaiafa-Gbandi, M., ‘The Importance of Core Principles of Substantive Criminal Law for a European Criminal Policy Respecting Fundamental Rights and the Rule of Law’, 1 European Criminal Law Review (2011) p. 7 at p. 17-21Google Scholar; Melander, S., ‘Ultima Ratio in European Criminal Law’, 3 European Criminal Law Review (2013) p. 45 at p. 52Google Scholar.

148 British American Tobacco (Investments) and Imperial Tobacco, supra n. 9, paras. 68-73, 84-87, 124, 134-135, 181-184; ECJ 12 December 2006, Case C-380/03, Germany v Parliament and Council [2006] ECR I-11573 paras. 46-48, 62, 66, 85-86; ECJ 10 February 2009, Case C-301/06, Ireland v Parliament and Council [2009] ECR I-00593, paras. 66-72, 83.

149 Germany v Parliament and Council, supra n. 12, paras. 26-28.

150 Swedish Match, supra n. 9, paras. 36-41.

151 Vodafone, supra n. 9, paras. 38-47, 76-79.

152 Alliance for Natural Health, supra n. 14, paras. 35-40, 105-107.

153 Alemanno, supra n. 68, p. 501.

154 See the Court of Justice’s case-law referred to in n. 11.

155 ECJ 15 November 2007, Case T-310/06, Hungary v Commission [2007] ECR II-4619, paras. 144-167; ECJ 14 May 2002, Case T-126/99, Graphischer Maschinenbau GmbH v Commission [2002] ECR II-2427; Craig, supra n. 15, p. 425, 438-439, 442.

156 Bar-Siman-Tov, supra n. 32, p. 287-288; Craig, supra n. 15, p. 439-440.

157 Leczykiewicz, supra n. 62, p. 12-13.

158 See above in the section ‘Analysis – why does Spain v Council provide an appropriate standard of review?’.

159 ECJ 1 October 2009, Case C-370/07, Commission v Council [2009] ECR I-8917, paras. 46-49; A. Von Bogdandy and J. Bast, ‘The Federal Order of Competences’, in A. Von Bogdandy and J. Bast, Principles of European Constitutional Law (Hart Publishing 2009) p. 279 at p. 301.

160 Azoulai, supra n. 24, p. 2, 5-6; Weatherill, supra n. 3, p. 863.

161 See text to nn. 57-67 supra.

162 Herzog, R. and Gerken, L., ‘Stoppt den Europäischen Gerichtshof’, Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, 8 September 2008 Google Scholar; Beck, G., ‘The Court of Justice, Legal Reasoning, and the Pringle Case: Law as Continuation of Politics by Other Means’, 39 European Law Review (2014) p. 236 Google Scholar, 238, 244.

163 Leczykiewicz, supra n. 62, p. 4, 8, 12-13.

164 Protocol (No 1) On the Role of National Parliaments in the European Union OJ [2010] C 83/203.

165 Protocol (No 2) On the Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality OJ [2010] C 83/206.

166 Art. 4(2) TEU.

167 In addition to Art. 5(2) TEU, there are a number of other provisions which expressly or implicitly reinforce the principle of conferral: Art. 1(1) TEU; Art. 3(6) TEU; Art. 4(1) TEU; Art. 13(2) TEU; Art. 48(6) TEU; Art. 2(1) TFEU; Art. 2(2) TFEU; Art. 4(1) TFEU; Art. 7 TFEU; Art. 19 TFEU; Art. 130 TFEU; Art. 207(6) TFEU; Art. 226 TFEU; Art. 314(10) TFEU; Art. 351(3) TFEU.

168 Azoulai, supra n. 24, p. 10-11.

169 Bermann, supra n. 28, p. 340-344; Kumm, supra n. 49, p. 518; Young, E.A., ‘Two Cheers for Process Federalism’, 46 Villanova Law Review (2001) p. 1349 Google Scholar, 1354, 1370-1374, 1387-88.

170 Young, supra n. 169, p. 1391.

171 Art. 5 TEU.

172 Young, supra n. 56, p. 1631, 1641; Lenaerts, supra n. 48, p. 747.

173 Tobacco Advertising, supra n. 142, para. 84.

174 Young, supra n. 169, p. 1367-1373

175 Lenaerts, supra n. 34, p. 3-4, 15-16; Hart Ely, J., Democracy and Distrust (Harvard University Press 1980); United States v Carolene Products Company Google Scholar, 304 U.S. 144 (1938) n. 4.

176 Young, supra n. 169, p. 1354, 1358, 1366; Young, supra n. 56, p. 1646-1653.

177 Schütze, supra n. 19, p. 261-262, 266; Tribe, L.H., ‘The Puzzling Persistence of Process-Based Constitutional Theories’, 89 Yale Law Journal (1980) p. 1063 Google Scholar.