INTRODUCTION
Recent years have witnessed a surge of interest in work and its futures within political theory and philosophy. Motivated in part by the 2008 global financial crisis and longer-term transformations in the form, stability, and rewards of paid employment, this scholarship grapples both with how to make work more equitable (Anderson Reference Anderson2023; Appiah Reference Appiah, Sobel, Vallentyne and Wall2021; Deranty Reference Deranty2022; Ferreras, Battilana, and Méda Reference Ferreras, Battilana and Méda2022; Frega, Herzog, and Neuhäuser Reference Frega, Herzog and Neuhäuser2019; Landemore and Ferreras Reference Landemore and Ferreras2016), and with whether it is possible to think beyond work as an organizing feature of social life (Benanav Reference Benanav2020; Chamberlain Reference Chamberlain2018; Frayne Reference Frayne2015; Hester and Srnicek Reference Hester and Srnicek2023; Srnicek and Williams Reference Srnicek and Williams2015; Weeks Reference Weeks2011). Adopting differing views on how best to respond to the challenges faced by contemporary workers—including stagnant wages, declining job security, and labor market polarization—this literature nevertheless agrees that work is a central locus of political, social, and economic integration and a vital object of political and philosophical concern (Geuss Reference Geuss2021; Turner and Van Milders Reference Turner and Van Milders2021).
To the extent that disabilityFootnote 1 is mentioned in this scholarship, it is either as an unintended consequence of work (Apostolidis Reference Apostolidis2019, 149–58; Frayne Reference Frayne2015, 148–52), or as a justified exception to the work imperative (Chamberlain Reference Chamberlain2018, 6). This article develops an alternative account of the relationship between disability and work, revealing the ways that disability and the figure of the disabled worker have been used—especially in the United States—to both contest and reaffirm the primacy of work and its role in anchoring citizenship and political belonging. Most evident in periods of crisis and transformation in the meaning and function of work, disability serves as a convenient repository for broader anxieties about the distance between the material conditions of work, on the one hand, and its idealization, on the other. Insofar as the figure of the independent worker-citizen continues to hold political and ideological weight, its resilience is due at least in part to the availability—but also the marginality and relative invisibility—of disability and disabled labor. Surfacing this relationship clarifies the significance of disability to questions of citizenship, not merely as the excluded other that lends coherence to the modal citizen, but as central to its very construction.
While this investigation has implications for recent debates concerning work and its futures, my focus will be on the mid-nineteenth to early twentieth century—a period credited both with the emergence of contemporary ideologies of work (Applebaum Reference Applebaum1992; Fraser and Gordon Reference Fraser and Gordon1994; Glickman Reference Glickman1997; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Roediger Reference Roediger2007; Shklar Reference Shklar1991) and with the exclusion and institutional confinement of the so-called defective, feebleminded, and unfit—terms that encompassed everything from sexual deviance, criminality, and vagrancy, to conditions we might now classify as disabilities (Carey Reference Carey2009; Ladd-Taylor Reference Ladd-Taylor2017; McWhorter Reference McWhorter2009; Trent Reference Trent2017). These developments are not unconnected. Though the term “disability” only came into widespread use in the early twentieth century,Footnote 2 the pathologization of bodily and mental abnormality is often linked to the social and economic upheaval that accompanied industrialization (Davis Reference Davis1995; Gleeson Reference Gleeson1999; Oliver Reference Oliver and Barton1989; Russell Reference Russell and Rosenthal2019; Ryan and Thomas Reference Ryan and Thomas1980). Transforming both the nature of work and the ability of families to care for less productive members, the expansion of wage labor and factory production in the latter half of the nineteenth century left many disabled Americans without the means of self-support (Baynton Reference Baynton2011; Garland-Thomson Reference Garland-Thomson1997, 46–9; Rose Reference Rose2017). This, along with the emergence of hereditarian and eugenic thought, drove the precipitous growth of state custodial institutions, which, by the turn of the twentieth century, frequently housed upward of one thousand inmates (Trent Reference Trent2017, 122).Footnote 3
That disabled people were often excluded from paid employment during this period is well documented (Baynton Reference Baynton2011; Bernstein and Leonard Reference Bernstein and Leonard2009; Holdren Reference Holdren2020; Rose Reference Rose2005; Reference Rose2017). This did not mean, however, that disabled people did not work.Footnote 4 Indeed, large-scale institutionalization would have been impossible without the unpaid labor of so-called higher-grade inmates, many of whom were responsible for the daily upkeep of the very institutions in which they were confined (Rose Reference Rose2017; Trent Reference Trent2017). Where this article departs from prior scholarship on this period is in linking the rhetoric used to describe disabled labor—by prominent social reformers, institutional superintendents, and hiring managers—to broader concerns about the changing nature of work and its implications for citizenship. Tracing the evolution of disabled labor from early experiments with school-based workshops to custodial institutions’ later reliance on inmate labor, and finally to limited efforts to hire disabled workers into paid, competitive positions, I demonstrate how the exclusion of disabled people and their marginalization within the burgeoning industrial economy obscured the ways that the concept of disability and the figure of the disabled worker became critical to sustaining the myth of workingmen’s independence in the midst of profound social and economic upheaval. Embodying the traits most suited to industrial labor—including docility, obedience, and a tolerance for repetitive tasks—the disabled worker became a tool for labor management and a repository for those elements of wage work that least aligned with the ideal citizen-worker of the national imaginary. Returning to contemporary debates over the present and future of work, this analysis attunes us to the ways disability continues to be deployed to shore up the primacy of work against the degradations of late capitalism. It is by paying attention to the way disability operates within these discourses, I argue, that we can begin to understand why attempts to resolve the contradictions between work’s necessity, its characteristic inequalities and unfreedoms, and its role in securing political belonging, have been so unsuccessful.
The stakes of this argument are threefold. First, by foregrounding the concept of disability and the figure of the disabled worker, I model an alternative approach to disability in political science. Relatively understudied within the discipline (Arneil and Hirschmann Reference Arneil, Hirschmann, Arneil and Hirschmann2016; Heffernan Reference Heffernan2024), existing research tends to focus on disability rights and policy (Pettinicchio Reference Pettinicchio2019; Stone Reference Stone1984), or on disabled people as constituents and voters (Evans and Reher Reference Evans and Reher2022; Johnson and Powell Reference Johnson and Powell2024; Miller and Powell Reference Miller and Powell2016; Schur, Ameri, and Adya Reference Schur, Ameri and Adya2017). While political theorists have been more attentive to the ways that disability and ability operate within dominant theoretical approaches, their efforts have largely been directed toward “challeng[ing] negative beliefs” about disability and remedying the exclusionary assumptions that structure the canon of political thought (Hirschmann Reference Hirschmann2020, 85; cf. Afsahi Reference Afsahi2020; Arneil Reference Arneil2009; Arneil and Hirschmann Reference Arneil, Hirschmann, Arneil and Hirschmann2016; Clifford Reference Clifford2012; Clifford Simplican Reference Clifford Simplican2015). This is vital and important work, but it can miss the generative—rather than oppositional—force of disability. Returning to the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, I examine the ways that disability was deployed to fortify and sustain emergent constructions of citizenship against the changes wrought by industrial capitalism.
This article also contributes to scholarship at the intersection of political theory and American political development that looks to the ways that the marginalization and subordination of ethnic, racial, and sexual “others” is not just constitutive of the boundaries of liberal citizenship, but foundational to American democracy (Beltrán Reference Beltrán2020; Hooker Reference Hooker2023; Kramer Reference Kramer2017; Olson Reference Olson2004; Shklar Reference Shklar1991). It is no accident, in other words, that the exclusion and institutionalization of disabled people proceeded alongside the transition to industrial production and related concerns about what this meant for a democracy that idealized self-employment and economic independence. Attending to the striking parallels between industrial and disabled labor reveals what is otherwise obscured by institutionalization and confinement; namely, the importance of disability to maintaining work as “an act of virtue” and a hallmark of American citizenship (Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014, xi).
Finally, this article intervenes in ongoing debates about work and its futures. Focusing on the emergence of contemporary ideas about work and the role of disability in consolidating the relationship between wage labor and American citizenship, I provide one answer to the question powerfully raised by Kathi Weeks—that is, “why we work so long and so hard” (Reference Weeks2011, 37). Specifically, this account attunes us to the peripheral figures that help manage the tension between the diminishing rewards of work and its continued moral and civic significance.
My argument will proceed in three parts. Beginning with mid-nineteenth-century experiments with school-based workshops at the Perkins Institution for the Blind in Boston, Massachusetts, I show how leading social reformers and superintendents like Perkins founder Samuel Gridley Howe addressed the shifting labor requirements of a rapidly industrializing economy. If school-based workshops laid the groundwork for custodial institutions’ later dependence on the unpaid labor of their inmates, their liminal status—neither fully of the market nor entirely separable from its demands—served as a convenient conduit through which reformers like Howe could critique the decline of artisanal and craft production while still appearing agnostic as to the merits of industrialization writ large. Never rising to the level of an outright attack on industrial capitalism, Howe’s efforts to make the more coercive aspects of wage labor congruent with the moral imperative to work illustrate how disabled workers were implicated in efforts to fortify the emergent market economy against concerns that it was inimical to the freedom and independence necessary for full citizenship.
Turning, in the second section, to the expansion of custodial institutions in the latter half of the nineteenth century and their growing reliance on inmate labor, I show how the segregation and “permanent sequestration” of disabled people helped obscure the similarities between institutional and industrial labor (Carson Reference Carson1899, 303). Defining the limits of what counted as legitimate work, the language used to defend inmate labor found its counterpart in the imagined ideal worker of the industrial factory. Leaving the confines of the institution, the final section looks to late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century efforts to recruit disabled workers into low- and semi-skilled factory-based positions. Exceptions to the widespread exclusion of disabled people from paid employment, these examples are notable for what they disclose about the changing nature of work at the turn of the century and the disparity between the still dominant small producer ideal and the reality of waged labor and factory production.
Drawing upon institutional records and annual reports from some of the nation’s oldest and most established schools and custodial institutions, as well as the proceedings of the National Conference of Charities and Correction—a professional organization that brought together leading social reformers, superintendents, correctional officers, and physicians from across the United States—this article pays particular attention to how these archives of institutionalization and social reform located disability within the rapidly shifting socioeconomic milieu of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.Footnote 5 Often addressed either to potential donors and state funding bodies (in the case of annual reports), or to social reformers and policymakers (in the case of the National Conference of Charities and Correction proceedings), these sources are particularly useful for what they convey about the regulatory structures, discourses, and beliefs that subtended institutionalization.
Taken together, the sites of disabled labor addressed here—the school-based workshop, the custodial institution, and the industrial workplace—offer a unique perspective on the ideologies and rhetorics that upheld (and, in many ways, continue to uphold) normative ideals of work and citizenship. Neither fully exempt from the work imperative nor easily assimilable within dominant understandings of productive citizenship, disabled workers acted as a hinge between a burgeoning market economy and an ideology of work grounded in an earlier era.
“TO RENDER USEFUL TO SOCIETY THEIR HANDS”: REHABILITATING THE WORK ETHIC
The first school-based workshop in the United States, founded by Samuel Gridley Howe in 1840 at the Perkins Institution for the Blind in Boston, Massachusetts, was intended to provide graduates with remunerative employment after efforts to secure competitive positions in the community failed (Klages Reference Klages1999, 34–46; tenBroek Reference tenBroek1966). Modeling Perkins on the Institut National des Jeunes Aveugles, founded in Paris in 1785 by Valentin Haüy, Howe, following Haüy, challenged the assumption that blind people were “consigned by destiny to idleness, languor, and dependence,” instead seeing education as a means of “render[ing] useful to society their hands” (Haüy Reference Haüy1793, 222, 227). Aided by developments in tactile printing technology, students received a vocational as well as an intellectual education with the hope that the focused development of their individual strengths—rather than an emphasis on handicrafts and manual labor alone—would “ensure…them a competent livelihood” (Howe Reference Howe1833, 48).
Despite their well-rounded education, however, students struggled to find employment once they left the institution. If Howe had initially argued for the relative insignificance of sight for the acquisition of knowledge—extolling the “tenaci[ty],” attentiveness, and even “superiority” of blind students as compared with their more “negligent” and “listless[]” sighted peers—the limited prospects of the school’s early graduates prompted a reconsideration of the purpose and aims of education and a reevaluation of the limits imposed by blindness on the moral and intellectual capacities of the child (Howe Reference Howe1833, 28). Evident in the Institute’s annual reports, this transition from the celebratory optimism of the 1830s to the sober pessimism of the 1840s and 1850s tracks a broader shift in medical and scientific understandings of the causes and consequences of blindness. Writing in 1848, Howe admitted that “the powers and capacities of the blind seem to have been overrated” (Reference Howe1848a, 31). Indeed, “but very few…can fully earn their own livelihood” (Reference Howe1848b, 56). Nevertheless, it was imperative that Perkins “provide them with means for putting themselves more nearly upon a footing with others” (Reference Howe1848a, 52). It was out of this desire to provide graduates with paid employment and “a feeling of independence” that the workshop was born (Reference Howe1848b, 56).
One of the earliest schools for the blind in the United States, Perkins became a model for other institutions for the blind as well as for the handful of training schools for “idiots” and the “feebleminded” that were founded in the mid-nineteenth century (Altschuler Reference Altschuler2020; Klages Reference Klages1999; Trent Reference Trent2012). I begin with Perkins in part because it helps map the transformation of the workshop from an experimental supplement to the mid-century institution to a permanent standalone facility—a transformation that laid the groundwork for custodial institutions’ later reliance on inmate labor. More specifically, a focused analysis of the Perkins workshop—and Howe’s and the Perkins trustees’ evolving views about the workshop—illustrates how this aspect of institutional life came to embody broader tensions between the ethical duty to work and the “real conditions of…employment” characteristic of the rapidly industrializing mid-century society (Weeks Reference Weeks2017, 40; cf. Chamberlain Reference Chamberlain2018; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Witt Reference Witt1998). Neither fully integrated into the competitive labor market nor immune to its moral and ideological imperatives, blind workers were expected to exhibit “proper views of the dignity of labor,” even as they were prevented from “earning a livelihood in any common way” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1843, 11; 1846, 8). As such, they provide a unique vantage point from which to examine, first, how institutional labor was distinguished from competitive employment; and second, how this distinction charts broader shifts in the nature of work.
Situating Perkins within a longer history of institutionalization, scholars of disability often emphasize the exclusionary effects of industrialization and the “incompatibility of blindness and market relations” (Klages Reference Klages1999, 8; cf. Davis Reference Davis1995, 86–90; Ryan and Thomas Reference Ryan and Thomas1980). Evident in Howe’s and the trustees’ reports on the progress of the workshop and their dismay at graduates’ unsuccessful efforts to secure competitive employment, these accounts, which focus mainly on what the antipathy between work and disability can tell us about emerging understandings of disability, have less to say about what we might also learn about work and its imperatives. In contrast, I suggest we treat the workshop as significant both for what it conveys about blindness—and disability generally—and for what it can tell us about the effort entailed in preserving the moral significance of work during a period of considerable social and economic upheaval. While the Perkins reports are, by their nature, focused on the challenges and successes faced by the Institution’s students and graduates, they are reflective of the social, political, and economic milieu in which blindness as a focus of reform and rehabilitation took shape.
Writing in Madness and Civilization, Michel Foucault famously links the “great confinement” of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries to the “imperative of labor” and the threat of idleness (Reference Foucault1988, 46). Initially offered as a solution to the economic crises that accompanied the emergence of the market economy, confinement, on Foucault’s reading, did not so much address poverty and vagrancy as instill in inmates the correct attitude toward labor—“a certain ethical consciousness” that was, in effect, disconnected from traditional measures of “utility or profit” (Reference Foucault1988, 55, 57). This separation between the productivity of labor and the particular “ordering of life and conscience” that was its condition of possibility attunes us to a similar dynamic at play within nineteenth-century institutions for the blind like Perkins (Foucault Reference Foucault1988, 63). Certainly, these institutions were less transparently about the need to address vagrancy and idleness than their European antecedents, but they exhibit a similar tension between the need to engage their charges in “honest and honorable labor” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1837, 10), and the recognition that such efforts were unlikely to “be a source of gain to the Institution” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1841, 15). Although Howe certainly hoped that workshop employees would eventually be able to “fully earn their own livelihood,” his belief that the workshop was a necessary adjunct to the institution illustrates the extent to which the moral dimensions of labor—and the need to keep blind people “steadily and industriously at work”—came to outweigh its economic utility (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 56–7).
Here, I draw on Foucault less for his historical account of confinement than for what his analysis of “the organization of a disciplinary space”—and the role of work within such spaces—reveals about the “network of sociopolitical relations” in which the workshop took shape (Foucault Reference Foucault and Davidson2006, 217; Huffer Reference Huffer2010, 26).Footnote 6 If Foucault’s interest in confinement primarily concerns its elaboration of a novel form of disciplinary power, his attention to the “practice of putting patients to work” alerts us to the significance of these spaces of productive confinement for organizing and articulating “a new ethic of work” whose implications extended beyond the walls of the institution (Foucault Reference Foucault and Davidson2006, 127; Reference Foucault1988, 46). “It is in this context,” Foucault writes, “that the obligation to work assumes its meaning as both ethical exercise and moral guarantee” (Reference Foucault1988, 59).
Indeed, it was the specificity of the workshop and its orientation toward blind workers’ “peculiar mode of working,” as well as its relative isolation from the competitive labor market, that made it such a fertile site for negotiating the tension between the moral primacy of work and the threat posed by wage labor (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1843, 13). Less efficient and exacting than their sighted counterparts, and characterized by a “constitutional feebleness of organization,” the blind worker was judged uniquely incapable of adapting to the newly mechanized workplace (Howe Reference Howe1848a, 46). “Nothing about the establishment is calculated for blind persons, to whom rumbling cog-wheels, revolving bands, and whirling saws … are objects of fear and of real danger” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1843, 13). Should blind workers “seek[] employment in a common shop,” the Institute’s trustees warned, they would “find[] nothing adapted to…[their] peculiar way of working” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1845, 5). Agreed Howe: “All the known and practised modes of doing business or of performing handicraft work are adapted to the sense of sight” (Reference Howe1850, 38).
If blind workers were both excluded from the competitive labor market and expected to “exercis[e]…[their] talents in a useful and profitable manner,” it was up to institutions to bridge this gap (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 65). They were to become, in Howe’s words, “capitalists of the blind” (Reference Howe1848b, 65), providing materials and tools, and, if necessary, supplementing workers’ pay “so as to raise them enough to support life in comfort” (Reference Howe1852, 24–5). Institutions, he clarified, “must come to the aid of many of the blind” (Reference Howe1850, 33) and “make such arrangements as will protect…[them] from unfair competition…and give them the same aid which other workmen have from [the] combination of labor and capital” (Reference Howe1848b, 73). As for the workshop’s employees, the challenges posed by competitive employment did not absolve them from the demand that they, too, become “industrious members of society…and useful citizens” (Reference Howe1876, 38). If anything, it was the inability of blind graduates to secure employment outside the workshop that gave added moral weight to their labor. Insisted Howe: “We have to teach them that work is honorable, and that an idle, unproductive life is the truly dishonorable one” (Reference Howe1875, 58).
In stressing the moral necessity of work, Howe and the Perkins trustees echoed a number of mid-century educators and social reformers.Footnote 7 At once educative, therapeutic, and disciplinary, work took on a significance that far exceeded either its economic rewards or the conditions of its performance (Carmody Reference Carmody2022; Hunnicutt Reference Hunnicutt2013; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Thompson Reference Thompson1967; Witt Reference Witt1998). The emergence of an industrial economy notwithstanding, older visions of work, in which moral obligation was balanced by the dignity, independence, and civic standing its performance was thought to confer, still held sway. Far more reflective of the economy of small landholders, merchants, and artisans that characterized the post-revolutionary period, these visions of work—and the ideals of free labor and republican citizenship to which they were joined—were increasingly at odds with the rhythms of factory production (Foner Reference Foner1995; Gourevitch Reference Gourevitch2011; Reference Gourevitch2015; Rana Reference Rana2010; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Shklar Reference Shklar1991; Stanley Reference Stanley1998). At once animated and challenged by the presence of chattel slavery, the expansion of waged work further highlighted the tensions between the independence thought necessary for full citizenship and the perception that “the wage earner was somehow less than fully free” (Foner Reference Foner1995, xvii; cf. Glickman Reference Glickman1997; Foner Reference Foner1994; Roediger Reference Roediger2007). Speaking to the effort needed to uphold the moral significance of work absent “the network of economics and values that had given it birth,” Daniel Rodgers contends that the relationship between work and work values during this period was not challenged so much as “reinforce[d]” and “pitched at a new level of abstraction” (Reference Rodgers2014; xii–xiii). That is, rather than calling into question the continued usefulness of a work ethic forged in the pre-industrial period, men like Howe instead attempted to graft earlier visions of work—and the moral commitments they inspired—onto a world in which even “the simplest trades…[were] becoming subdivided; and independent artisans…[were] becoming hirelings” (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 60).
Within this context, the workshop took on a dual, if contradictory, role. On the one hand, it recalled an earlier era in which “the province of handicraft”—in this case, the manufacture of doormats, cane chairs, baskets, and mattresses—hadn’t yet been “usurp[ed]” by machinery (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1846, 12). Here, in other words, was an “industrious community” in which work, though waged, still retained a connection to the “dignified and productive labor [that] served as the foundation of personal and national virtue” (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1841, 16; Witt Reference Witt1998, 1471). At the same time, it was the workshop’s relative isolation and distinctiveness—its cultivation of “a peculiar kind of training” through which workers might be made to “feel” (but not be) independent—that was essential to maintaining this connection (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 56–7). Protected from the “tireless sinews of iron” that dominated factory production (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1846, 12), this “company of blind persons”—marked as they were by “infirmity,” “abnormal[ity],” and a “constitutional feebleness of organization” (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 59; Reference Howe1851, 12; Reference Howe1848a, 46)—came to embody the relationship between the ideal of work and its execution that was being eroded by industrial production.
Anxious to secure graduates’ ability to “support themselves…by a hard, but honest and honorable labor,” Howe and the trustees remained wary of the effects of industrialization and mechanization on both blind and sighted workers (Perkins Institution for the Blind 1837, 10). Noting that even the “strong man has been pushed aside by the stronger steam engine” and “outdone by fingers and pickers of wood and iron,” they attempted to reassert the dignity of labor in the context of the workshop’s emphasis on the “simplest trades” and handicrafts (Howe Reference Howe1848b, 59–60).
Turning in the next section to the expansion of custodial institutions for the “feebleminded” in the latter half of the nineteenth century, I show how the conflicting justifications offered for school-based workshops—that they were uniquely adapted to “the real condition and capacities of the blind,” and necessary for blind persons to “be taken as equal, independent and useful members…[of] general society,” laid the groundwork for the delegitimization of inmate labor as work (Howe Reference Howe1848a, 34; Reference Howe1868, 25). In so doing, they disregarded the affinities between the unpaid labor performed within institutions and what International Harvester’s H. A. Worman referred to as the “routine muscular effort” required by new production techniques (quoted in Montgomery Reference Montgomery1987, 61). Just as the workshop employee was prevented from entering the competitive labor market “on account of his blindness” and held up as an example of the “habits of regularity and industry” that were essential to the work ethic (Howe Reference Howe1848a, 33; Reference Howe1852, 15), so too did institutional inmates come to embody the kinds of discipline, “order,…and obedience” judged essential to industrial production (Wilbur Reference Wilbur1852, 21).
“WILLING, HAPPY LABORERS”: PRODUCTIVE NONWORK IN THE INSTITUTIONFootnote 8
Remarking, toward the end of his life, on the shrinking “field of simple handicraft in which the blind man could work,” Howe would again stress the importance of cultivating students’ “desire of independence” and “dread of dependence” (Reference Howe1874, 34; Reference Howe1875, 109, 57). And yet, if workshops helped “sustain ideas about the dignity of work and the moral value of labor” during a period of extraordinary economic and social transformation, they also provided a rationale for institutions’ reliance on inmate labor (Witt Reference Witt1998, 1468). Abandoning an earlier emphasis on rehabilitation and educability, new understandings of the heritability of degeneracy and deviance demanded a different approach, one that was less oriented toward inmates’ eventual “restora[tion]…to their friends and to society” (Wilbur Reference Wilbur1852, 19), and more toward what Walter Fernald, superintendent of the Massachusetts School for the Feeble-Minded, described as “retention and guardianship” (Reference Fernald1893, 210).
If the resulting expansion of state institutions signaled a shift in the treatment of mental and physical abnormalities, it also placed increasing demands on state budgets, forcing superintendents to find new ways to contain costs while maintaining quality of care. Inmate labor—both in the institution and on separate farm colonies—offered a solution to both these problems, not only reducing per-capita expenses but also aiding in the “daily routine work of a large institution” and the care of the so-called lower-grade residents (Fernald Reference Fernald1893, 218; cf. Arneil Reference Arneil2017, 111–34; Rose Reference Rose2017, 49–90; Trent Reference Trent2017).
Addressing the tension between the widespread exclusion of disabled workers from the wage labor market, on the one hand, and custodial institutions’ dependence on unpaid inmate labor, on the other, Sarah Rose credits the unrelenting speed and physical demands of industrial labor. Privileging workers with “intact, interchangeable bodies” that could be easily fitted to the machines they were called upon to attend, there was little room for disabled workers in this new economy (Rose Reference Rose2017, 2). “Made unproductive” by the demands of the “modern, mechanized, and efficient workplace,” the exclusion of people with disabilities from the wage labor market facilitated both the precipitous growth of inmate populations and institutions’ dependence on the labor of these supposedly “unproductive burdens” (Rose Reference Rose2017, 2, 12, 14; cf. Oliver Reference Oliver and Barton1989; Ryan and Thomas Reference Ryan and Thomas1980). Broadly concurring with Rose’s assessment, Lennard Davis focuses on the machine itself, showing how ability—specifically, the ability to work—was defined relative to an individual’s capacity to “operate machines” (Reference Davis1995, 87). Insofar as the worker’s body (and, by association, the body politic) was “reshap[ed]” by its interaction with the machine and mechanized labor, the consolidation of the link between work and citizenship depended upon the denial of work’s disabling effects (Davis Reference Davis1995, 88).
If our earlier engagement with the Perkins archive clarified the ways that workshop labor was used to both address the diminished conditions of competitive employment and uphold work as foundational to citizenship, it also illustrated the need to interrogate the assumed opposition between disability and industrial labor. When nineteenth and early twentieth-century commentators expressed misgivings about the effects of industrialization on workers, they were not only referring to industrial accidents and illnesses. Worrisome, too, were the moral and psychological consequences of industrialization, particularly for unskilled and semi-skilled laborers.Footnote 9 However, industrial labor did not just cause disabilities—it also demanded a different kind of worker, one that could withstand repetitive, minutely subdivided, and simplified tasks (Glenn Reference Glenn2002; Montgomery Reference Montgomery1987; Moore Reference Moore2002; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Slavishak Reference Slavishak2008; Wolkowitz Reference Wolkowitz2006). Consider, for example, Reverend R. Heber Newton’s concern that the once-skilled worker had been “reduced” to “feeding and watching the great machine which ha[d] been endowed with the brains that once was in the human toiler” (U.S. Congress 1885a, 549). Or Francis Amasa Walker’s observation that the “habits of labor and mental attention” required of the factory operative had left them without the “varied experience or acquirements…[of] the farmer, or country carpenter, or country blacksmith” (U.S. Congress 1885b, 328). Arguing that “industrial aptitudes” were both inherited and “made,” Walker—superintendent of the 1880 census and president of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology—called attention to the risks posed by mechanized production in a society that still held fast to the belief that work was both requisite for citizenship and a mark of independence (U.S. Congress 1885a, 545; cf. Bernstein and Leonard Reference Bernstein and Leonard2009, 184). Insofar as the health and well-being of the worker were often taken as proxies for national efficiency and vitality, the deleterious effects of industrialization presented an acute problem. Simply put, what if the ideal worker was not the independent small producer but instead the minutely managed and highly choreographed machine tender?
Faced with this prospect, custodial labor emerges as a rhetorical foil in debates over the changing economy—at once distracting from the degradations of mechanized production and propping up older agrarian and craft-based ideals that linked the moral significance of work to visions of independent proprietorship. Indeed, many of the disciplinary techniques used to spur inmates’ productivity—techniques superintendents argued were proof of the necessity of life-long custodial care—bear a striking resemblance to those deployed within the industrial workplace. This was especially true with the introduction of new managerial practices aimed at the intelligent direction and control of the worker. Placing the growing dominance of wage labor alongside—rather than in opposition to—custodialization shows how these parallel histories worked together to uphold earlier ideologies of work amidst a rapidly shifting economic reality. “Withdrawn from the community,” and thought incapable of being “restore[d]…to safe citizenship” beyond the institution, the inmate laborer found its double in the imagined ideal worker of the industrial factory (Kerlin Reference Kerlin1886, 296; Powell Reference Powell1898, 293). Clarifying this relationship helps explain how work was maintained as “an act of virtue” and “vital center of living” even as its real conditions underwent a radical transformation (Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014, xi). Viewed alongside the emergence of managerial practices directed toward “reengineering the labor process itself,” the place of inmate labor within the institution—and its delegitimization as “real” work—helped postpone uncomfortable revelations about the shifting terrain of competitive employment and its implications for citizenship (Salzinger Reference Salzinger2003, 18; cf. Welke Reference Welke2010).
Drawing out the connections between inmate and paid work requires, first, understanding the process by which inmates were judged “unfit to be sent into the general community” despite their (sometimes considerable) productive capacities (Kerlin Reference Kerlin1885, 162). Insisting on the necessity of custodial confinement—particularly for inmates of childbearing age—superintendents were hardly circumspect in their praise of inmates’ capacity for labor when retained under “careful protection and guardianship” (Wilbur Reference Wilbur1888, 110). Speaking at the 1885 National Conference of Charities and Correction, superintendent Isaac Kerlin boasted of the “four thousand dollars in wage labor annually saved” by the Pennsylvania Training School by using inmate labor, allowing “the institution to retain about thirty inmates on the non-paying list; that is, thirty free patients” (Reference Kerlin1885, 162, emphasis in original). Agreeing with Kerlin, Walter Fernald was careful to specify that any reduction in “the average running expenses of these institutions” achieved by the “utilization of the industrial abilities of the trained inmates” ought to be considered secondary to the therapeutic and moral benefits of their labor (Reference Fernald1893, 218–9). “These simple people,” he clarified, “are much happier and better off in every respect when they know they are doing some useful and necessary work” (Reference Fernald1893, 218). Nevertheless, the sheer scope of the tasks performed by inmates—including farming, groundskeeping, cooking, cleaning, sewing, laundry, and caregiving—suggests that the turn to inmate labor was not motivated purely by the need to give inmates “the impression that they…[were] accomplishing something” (Wilbur Reference Wilbur1877, 141, my emphasis). To the contrary, admitted Arthur Curtis Rogers, superintendent of the Minnesota School for the Feeble-Minded: “Scores of feeble-minded persons are to-day performing the work of regular employees in public institutions”—even, in some cases, building the institutions where they would be confined (Reference Rogers1888, 102).Footnote 10
The enthusiasm expressed by superintendents in promoting the productive capacities of their charges to trustees, donors, and state charity boards is belied, however, by their equally energetic attempts to discount inmates’ fitness for independence. Certainly, inmates were “practically useful and helpful,” but this conveyed little about their ability “to be safely trusted, either for their own good or the good of society, out from under…[the] strict and judicious surveillance” of the institution (Fernald Reference Fernald1892, 16; Rogers Reference Rogers1888, 103). Whereas the productive confinement of the Perkins workshop relied on a distinction between the ethic demanded of its workers and their utility, here we see a separation between the “productive value of [the] work performed” and inmates’ right to liberty (Kerlin Reference Kerlin1884, 252). Gone, in other words, was an earlier emphasis on industrial training as the key to securing the inmates’ eventual release. Instead, many superintendents saw labor as not only compatible with but even requisite for the “arbitrary but legal isolation of the unfit”—a way to keep inmates from “reproduc[ing] their kind” while also recovering some of the cost of their care (Kerlin Reference Kerlin1884, 257; Barr Reference Barr1902, 163). Very often it was the qualities believed to be characteristic of an inmate’s diagnosis that made them especially well suited to become “faithful domestics,” caregivers, or agricultural laborers in the institution (Winspear Reference Winspear1895, 163). For George H. Knight, the superintendent of the Connecticut School for Imbeciles, it was only by increasing inmate populations that institutions would be able to find willing caretakers for the “most unfortunate and helpless among the defective classes.” Indeed, “even for money,…[superintendents] cannot get suitable people who are willing to come in contact with the lowest grade in the right spirit,—a spirit which demands patience, cheerfulness, and affection.” The “imbecile,” on the other hand, “will share his pleasures and attainments with his weaker brother with a sense of high privilege in being allowed so to share it.” “None,” he continued, “make tenderer care-takers, nor, under supervision, more watchful ones” (Knight Reference Knight1892, 160).
The ease with which reformers could at once acknowledge the economic benefits reaped from the use of inmate labor and deny the possibility of those same inmates finding suitable competitive employment, was predicated on the assumption that their labor could only be extracted under certain conditions. “Outside of an institution,” Fernald asserted, “it would be impossible to secure the experienced and patient supervision and direction necessary to obtain practical, remunerative results from the comparatively unskilled labor of these feeble-minded people” (Reference Fernald1893, 218). Though perhaps “deft in handicraft,” inmates lacked the “higher powers of the intellect” necessary to navigate such a “busy, practical, money-getting age” in which even the “normal” worker was struggling to keep pace (Powell Reference Powell1898, 295; Rogers Reference Rogers1888, 102). Remarking on the unusual skill of a 16-year-old boy employed in the shoe shop of the Iowa Institution for Feeble-Minded Children, the Institution’s superintendent explained that it would be a mistake to presume (as some visitors apparently had) that “prodigies of this character are wrongfully detained” and ought therefore to be allowed their freedom (Powell Reference Powell1887, 256). Instead, it was incumbent upon the institution to cultivate and direct these abilities toward their desired (institutional) ends. Inmates, reformer Frederick H. Wines specified, were “useful under direction, just as a horse is. But you cannot make a horse useful except under direction….You may correct bad habits, you may develop and improve them; but they must remain under control, in order to be of any real service to the world” (Wines in response to Dechert Reference Dechert1889, 321).
Concerned as they were to justify the necessity of inmates’ long-term institutionalization and their need for “kindly but firm oversight and direction,” superintendents’ descriptions of inmate labor bear a striking resemblance to the ideal factory worker imagined by managers and efficiency experts during the same period (Fernald Reference Fernald1897, 16). But while inmates’ need for “intelligent direction” and “proper guardianship” was considered reason enough for their continued confinement (Kerlin Reference Kerlin1885, 160; Wilbur Reference Wilbur1888, 110), these same “mental and moral qualities” were also central to the success of new “scientific” management techniques (Taylor Reference Taylor1911a, 96). Consider the case of “Schmidt,” the yard worker at the Bethlehem Steel Company whose ability to load over 47 tons of pig iron per day (nearly three times the average loaded by his coworkers) figured prominently in Frederick Winslow Taylor’s Principles of Scientific Management. Footnote 11 Chosen from among 75-yard workers, Schmidt exemplified the characteristics necessary for withstanding the “grinding monotony” of pig-iron handling (Reference Taylor1911b, 59). Capable of “do[ing] exactly as he’s told from morning till night,” he was described by Taylor as being “so stupid and so phlegmatic that he more nearly resembles in his mental make-up the ox than any other type” (Reference Taylor1911b, 45, 59). And yet, far from being a detriment to his productivity, it was Schmidt’s stupidity—his mental “heav[iness]” and “sluggish[ness]”—that made him an ideal pig-iron handler (Reference Taylor1911b, 137, 46).
The pig-iron loading experiments undertaken by Taylor and his associates were meant to illustrate how even the most rudimentary tasks could be made more efficient through the application of scientific management techniques (Aitken Reference Aitken1960; Esch and Roediger Reference Esch and Roediger2009; Kanigel Reference Kanigel1997; Nelson Reference Nelson1977; Wrege and Perroni Reference Wrege and Perroni1974). Relying on the “substitution of a science for the individual judgment of the workman,” was, Taylor believed, the only effective way to overcome “soldiering”—the deliberate slowing-down that resulted when workers were left to “regulate…[their] own way of doing the work” (Reference Taylor1911b, 114, 63). Practically, it allowed employers to replace “more intelligent”—and higher paid—skilled mechanics with men like Schmidt, who, though “too stupid properly to train [themselves],” were capable of “promptly obey[ing] orders and instructions” without complaint (Reference Taylor1911b, 59, 63; Reference Taylor1911a, 139). Speaking to the proper relationship between management and labor under scientific management, Taylor was explicit: “All we want of…[the men] is to obey the orders we give them, do what we say, and do it quick” ([1907] Reference Taylor1995, 9).
And yet, scientific management was not just about improving efficiency or cutting costs. If Taylor’s pig-iron experiments “symbolized the development of modern business management” (Nelson Reference Nelson1977, 487), they were equally concerned with how best to secure workers’ “acquiescen[ce]” to this “new order” (Taylor Reference Taylor1911a, 132). The success of the planning departments charged with assuming the “brain work” of a particular task hinged on the worker’s ability to “receiv[e] and obey[] directions covering details, large and small, which in the past ha[d] been left to his individual judgment” (Reference Taylor1911a, 98, 133). Relinquishing control in this way demanded, Taylor wrote, “a complete revolution in…[the workers’] mental attitude toward their employers and their work” (Reference Taylor1911a, 130). To the extent that “Taylorism told workers not only what to do but exactly how to do it,” then, it required both physical capacity and compliance (Corwin Reference Corwin2003, 139, emphasis in original).
Insisting that workers were “not only willing, but glad” to “change from their old easy-going ways to a higher rate of speed,” Taylor nevertheless conceded that “a certain percentage” would resist these changes and need to be let go (Reference Taylor1911a, 25, 132). The notion that management would instruct the worker in “new working habits” was, he admitted further, “directly antagonistic to the…idea that each workman can best regulate his own way of doing the work” (Reference Taylor1911b, 63). In this regard, the “scientific selection of the workman” that Taylor espoused was as concerned with the workman’s ability to do the work as it was with his willingness to do it in the precise way set forth by management (Taylor Reference Taylor1911b, 43). Indeed, “the workman who is best suited” to a particular task, Taylor believed, was “incapable, either through lack of education or through insufficient mental capacity, of understanding th[e] science” behind its correct performance (Reference Taylor1911b, 97). “Entirely relieved of the work of planning,” Schmidt’s stupidity was a necessary condition of his success (Reference Taylor1911a, 98).
That a worker’s physical or “mental make-up” suited them to a particular task or profession was not a novel observation (Taylor Reference Taylor1911b, 59). Nor, as we have seen, were critics of the changes wrought by industrialization the first to express concern over its potentially degrading effects. Writing more than a century earlier, Adam Smith worried that the division of labor would, if left unchecked, result in the “corruption and degeneracy of the great body of the people” ([1776] Reference Smith and Cannan1976, 302). But what set Taylor and his contemporaries apart was their willingness to treat the “stupid and ignorant” laborer less as a regretful consequence of industrialization than as evidence of the successful fit between available manpower and the needs of a growing economy (Smith [1776] Reference Smith and Cannan1976, 303). Where critics of industrialization bemoaned the “purely mechanical and unintelligent character of much that…[was] required” of the new factory worker, proponents of scientific management were more concerned with selecting the best workers for a job (Potter Reference Potter1897, 388). Confronting the debilitating consequences of industrial production, management experts inverted the relationship between disability and laboring capacity, exposing an alternative ideal subtending the figure of the free, independent citizen-worker. Imagined as a “human machine”—capable and industrious, but also pliant and docile—this figure referenced its institutionalized counterpart, highlighting the tension between work as a constitutive element of democratic citizenship and the shifting demands of the new industrial order (Biggs Reference Biggs1996).
Viewed against the threat posed by mechanized and subdivided labor to the intelligence and skill of the worker, inmate labor emerges both as a response to the economic strain of growing institutional populations and as a bulwark against the degradation of labor by industrial capitalism. To this end, inmates’ lifelong confinement and segregation within the institution helped assuage mounting concerns about the changing conditions of work by obscuring the likeness between the “machine-like qualities characteristic of…the feeble-minded” and the traits required of the ideal industrial worker (Brown Reference Brown1886, 404).
Placing the increased dominance of wage labor alongside—rather than in opposition to—custodialization shows how these parallel histories worked together to uphold the vision of free labor against the rapidly shifting reality of waged work. Displaced by the rise of factory production, the independent citizen-worker gave way, over the course of the nineteenth century, to the tightly managed and fractionalized wage laborer. And it was amidst this “crisis of free labor” and the dissonance between an older labor ideal and the reality of wage labor, that the figure of the disabled worker emerged, serving as the unspoken background that both defined and delimited the semi-skilled industrial operative (Witt Reference Witt2001, 713; cf. Foner Reference Foner1994; Forbath Reference Forbath1985; Stanley Reference Stanley1998). At the same time that disabled workers were being excluded from the competitive labor force, in other words, it was the qualities that defined the exemplary worker within the custodial institution that were made central to creating a disciplined workforce.
“APPROXIMATELY USEFUL CITIZENS”: REFIGURING LABOR IN THE NEW CENTURYFootnote 12
Narrated as the gradual stigmatization of people with cognitive and physical abnormalities and their exclusion from the labor market, scholars often trace the emergence of contemporary understandings of disability to the transformations wrought by industrial capitalism (Gleeson Reference Gleeson1999; Oliver Reference Oliver and Barton1989; Rose Reference Rose2017; Ryan and Thomas Reference Ryan and Thomas1980). But the affinities between inmate and semi- and unskilled labor suggest an alternative account, in which the presence of—and institutional reliance upon—inmate labor helped preserve the myth of the free, independent citizen-worker against its erosion by industrialization. If advocates of scientific management like Taylor were more willing to acknowledge the conditions (both intellectual and functional) required of new work forms, some companies took this demand for an obedient and disciplined labor force to its logical conclusion, explicitly seeking out disabled workers on the assumption that their disabilities made them uniquely suited to the new industrial order. Although these practices were not widespread, they are nevertheless instructive for what they disclose about the changing norms of work at the turn of the twentieth century.
Challenging the presumption that illness and disability “ma[de] ordinary work out of the question” (Hall and Buck Reference Hall and Mertice1915, viii), managers who sought out disabled workers were often required to justify their hiring decisions, and it is here that the shifting terms of wage labor are made clear. Consider, for example, Joseph Goldberg’s insistence that “deaf-mutes” employed in the bottling department of his father’s New York City liquor store were “more faithful” and less given to “dissipation” than “men in possession of all their faculties” (New York Times 1907). Or the assertion by Reno, Nevada tailor H. N. Greenfield, that the “crippled worker is steady, competent, and ambitious,” and possessed none of the “migratory” tendencies that afflicted his able-bodied employees (Reno Gazette-Journal 1919). Notable in both cases is the emphasis on the dispositions and habits necessary for securing worker compliance with managerial oversight. Like Taylor’s attention to the worker’s “mental attitude”—and not just their efficiency or speed—Goldberg and Greenfield’s comments make legible the transformations demanded of low- and semi-skilled wage laborers as industrialization took hold. And, like inmate laborers within the custodial institution, it is the relative infrequency of these targeted hiring practices that make them such convenient repositories for broader worries about the changing nature of work at the turn of the century.
If Goldberg and Greenfield cited the reliability and loyalty of their disabled employees, it was also the case that companies would hire disabled workers on the assumption that their disabilities made them more productive, not less. Indeed, between 1916 and 1920, Firestone and Goodyear tire companies together employed over one thousand deaf workers, enough that a so-called Silent Colony was established near the companies’ headquarters in Akron, Ohio (Buchanan Reference Buchanan1999, 76–83; Schowe Reference Schowe1940). Driven in part by a wartime shortage of available manpower, these positions did not, for the most part, survive the post-war collapse of the rubber industry. Even still, the rhetoric surrounding the recruitment of deaf workers frequently cites their deafness as the reason for their efficiency and diligence. Neither easily distracted nor given to “needless conversation,” deaf workers were thought to be especially suited and even “favored” by what Benjamin Schowe—the manager (himself deaf) in charge of Firestone’s recruiting efforts—referred to as the “regimen…of mass production” (quoted in Morton Reference Morton, Bauman and Murray2014, 310; Schowe Reference SchoweN.d., 4).
Credited with being among “the sturdiest and the steadiest in the plant,” it was deaf workers’ loyalty and compliance as much as their efficiency that drove their increased employment (Indianapolis Star 1916; cf. New York Times 1907). Acknowledging the monotony of what often amounted to semi-skilled piecework, managers assumed that pervasive discrimination and a dearth of other employment opportunities would prevent deaf and disabled employees from participating in the kinds of labor unrest that characterized the early twentieth century (Schowe Reference SchoweN.d., 1). They would, in other words, be grateful for what work they were able to find. Reporting on Chicago’s Automatic Electric Company for the Silent Worker Magazine (a monthly, student-run newspaper published by the New Jersey School for the Deaf), one contributor suggested that when “given an opportunity to prove their ability, the deaf workmen are if anything even more industrious, reliable, quick to learn, and painstaking than their so-called more fortunate hearing brother” (The Silent Worker 1902, 49). Indeed, by 1903, the company had hired nearly 150 deaf workers after a more limited trial employment found that their dexterity gave them a particular advantage in assembling “the delicate mechanism of the modern telephone” (New York Times 1905).
Valuable, too, was the deaf worker’s superior focus and attentiveness. As one “manager Keith” explained to a reporter from the St. Paul Globe, “We find [deaf mutes to be]…better workmen than a good many men who have all other senses. They attend strictly to their own business.” Able-bodied boys and men, on the other hand, “play too much.” It was for this reason, he continued, that companies like Automatic Electric had “replac[ed] all…[their] boys with these able substitutes” (St. Paul Globe 1903). F. L. Avant, the general superintendent of the Curlee Clothing Company in St. Louis, reached a similar conclusion. “The deaf mutes,” he observed, “do not hang around the water coolers and talk as much as others do; they are not eternally ‘spoofing’ at one another, but they go along hour in and hour out, paying attention only to their work, undistracted by anything in the plant” (St. Louis Post-Dispatch 1921).
Unfortunately for Keith, the diligence and reliability of the deaf Automatic Electric employees proved short-lived. On April 22, 1903, 150 deaf employees joined the Telephone and Switchboard Workers’ Union strike in support of a shorter, 9-hour workday (Chicago Tribune 1903). Expressing a mixture of shock and amused bewilderment, the Chicago Daily Tribune declared it “the quietest strike on record,” noting the incongruity of the “enthusiastic but noiseless” picketers lining Morgan and Van Buren Streets. Although the company agreed to the union’s demands, this victory was bittersweet. By joining their hearing colleagues in the week-long strike, these “speechless but gesticulating” workers had shattered the illusion of their solitary diligence (Chicago Daily Tribune 1903). By the following year, only around 30 deaf employees remained at the company (Rose Reference Rose2017, 120).
What are we to make of these cases? Exceptions to the widespread exclusion of disabled people from the workforce, they might be dismissed as anomalies in a period better known for its preoccupation with organizational efficiency and new techniques of managerial control. Certainly, disabled workers addressed some of these concerns—being at times more attentive, reliable, and industrious than their nondisabled counterparts—but in many respects, they remained largely unfitted for the speed and intensity of new labor forms. Illustrating the lengths companies were willing to go to maintain productive capacity and avoid labor unrest, these examples do not fundamentally challenge the more widespread exclusion of people with disabilities from paid employment.
But here I want to suggest an alternative account, one that treats disability—and specifically the disabled worker—as a locus through which the contradictions between earlier visions of free labor and the dawning reality of industrial production, might be resolved. Put differently, rather than viewing the targeted hiring of disabled workers by companies such as Automatic Electric, Goodyear, and Firestone as aberrations within a longer arc of disability exclusion, we might see them instead as offering a lens onto the shifting meaning of work and labor at the dawn of the twentieth century. Placing the demand for willing and obedient workers into stark relief, these examples illustrate the effort involved in upholding the ideals of liberty and independence that continued to animate understandings of free labor (Forbath Reference Forbath1985; Glickman Reference Glickman1997; Gourevitch Reference Gourevitch2015). If disability was “becoming inextricably linked with personal immorality and economic dependency,” it was characteristics that had long defined abnormal bodies and minds—docility, passivity, simplicity—that were called upon to shore up the fantasy of the free, independent laborer against the threat posed by industrial capitalism (Rose Reference Rose2017, 4). Coinciding with the exclusion of people with disabilities from the paid workforce and their widespread confinement in custodial institutions, it was this relative invisibility and marginality that obscured their figuration in the low- and semi-skilled wage laborer.
Surfacing the affinities between the qualities required of low- and semi-skilled wage laborers and characteristics that, in a different setting, were signs of degeneracy, constitutional abnormality, and feeblemindedness, also contributes to scholarship that has sought to explain how American workers came to terms with wage labor. Citing the emergence of consumer society and the veneration of contract in the postbellum period, Lawrence Glickman (Reference Glickman1997) and Amu Dru Stanley (Reference Stanley1998) chart the shift from thinking of wage work as “a dangerous, demeaning, and debilitating departure from traditional modes of financial reward” (Glickman Reference Glickman1997, 1), to a “voluntary relation[] of exchange” that was compatible with—and even emblematic of—autonomy and freedom (Stanley Reference Stanley1998, 4; cf. Forbath Reference Forbath1985; Rodgers Reference Rodgers2014; Shklar Reference Shklar1991). “This change in perspective,” as Glickman observes, “was born of necessity.” Faced with the dominance of wage labor and a legal landscape increasingly hostile to labor organizing, workers “learned to accept wages and to identify themselves as wage earners because they had no alternative” (Reference Glickman1997, 2). At the same time, the abolition of slavery and the equation of freedom with contract and self-ownership offered a conceptual vocabulary by which even wage labor could be construed as free. But tensions remained between the exploitative and unequal dimensions of wage labor and the belief that work was not just necessary for—but also central to—the full exercise of citizenship.
Attending to the role of disability within these narratives, both its explicit appearance in the disabled worker and its rhetorical invocation in debates over new managerial techniques, testifies to the energy required to uphold work as “an essential element of citizenship” (Shklar Reference Shklar1991, 68). Even if “wage earners…had no alternative” but to accede to wage labor, maintaining a belief in work as both necessary and civically meaningful required a good deal of mythmaking about the conditions and rewards of wage labor (Glickman Reference Glickman1997, 2). At once shoring up the free labor ideal and serving as its antithesis, the disabled worker exposed the instabilities in the meaning of work at a moment of extraordinary social, political, and economic change. Whether laboring within the custodial institution or gainfully employed as more dedicated, loyal, and efficient “substitutes” for their able-bodied peers, these workers helped sustain the ideal of free labor even as they revealed fissures in its central presumptions. It was the liminal place of the disabled worker—neither wholly excluded from, nor entirely suitable for, paid employment—that made them such fertile sites for negotiating the boundaries and defining features of work.
CONCLUSION
Revisiting the emergence of industrial labor in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the foregoing analysis has sought to illuminate the role of disability in upholding the belief in work as requisite for full citizenship even as the conditions of work were radically transformed. Through an investigation of three sites of disabled labor—the school-based workshop, the custodial institution, and the industrial factory—I have shown how the disabled worker came to embody those qualities that were most demanded by new systems of production but least congruent with the still-dominant belief in work as figured in the independent craftsman and agrarian landholder. In the case of the custodial inmate, it was often the very qualities that disqualified them from freedom—that is, their simplicity, passivity, and need for constant “supervision and direction”—that became central to this new industrial ideal (Fernald Reference Fernald1893, 218). “Unfit for free, social life” (Johnson Reference Johnson1898, 326), the custodial inmate helped secure “the work ethic…as a political ideology” against the threat posed by wage labor (Shklar Reference Shklar1991, 85).
And yet, the ideological work performed by the disabled laborer is not purely oppositional. Indeed, it is by attending to the specific contours of disabled labor as it emerged in the school-based workshop, custodial institution, and industrial workplace that we can begin to understand how and why work persists as an essential component of citizenship. Illuminating the tension between work as “a social convention and disciplinary apparatus,” and work as an organizing feature of American citizenship and belonging, the disabled worker clarifies the effort entailed in upholding the “independent citizen-worker…[as] a dominant ideal of public discourse” (Weeks Reference Weeks2011, 7–8; Gourevitch Reference Gourevitch2015, 52).
Moving beyond the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, this investigation also gestures toward the continued significance of disability for contemporary engagements with, and critiques of, work. Consider, for example, our stubborn attachment to work—an attachment that persists despite the recognition that our current “systems of income distribution and labor organization,” are, as Kathi Weeks puts it, “utterly broken” (Cole and Marasco Reference Cole and Marasco2021, 743). Addressing the demand that we “love” our work (whatever its content or day-to-day rhythms), Weeks shows how “familiar cultural tropes of love and happiness” are leveraged to “prescribe[] a certain subjective orientation to waged work” (Weeks Reference Weeks2017, 41; cf. Jaffe Reference Jaffe2021; Tokumitsu Reference Tokumitsu2015). More than just a supplement to the Protestant work ethic, this romanticization of work helps secure workers’ “eager obedience” to employers’ demands while obscuring the inequalities at the heart of the employment relationship (Weeks Reference Weeks2017, 44).
But here again, I want to suggest the potential uses of disability as an analytic, especially insofar as it helps discern the relationship between work as a social obligation and ethical imperative, on the one hand, and work as the “key to citizenship,” on the other (Pateman Reference Pateman1988, 136). Warning against the danger of treating such contradictions as incidental—rather than intrinsic—to American understandings of citizenship, Judith Shklar puts it bluntly: “We are citizens,” she writes, “only if we ‘earn’” (Reference Shklar1991, 67). That is, rather than registering the obligation to work as intervening on a deeper commitment to civic equality, Shklar clarifies the compulsions and exclusions that remain essential to American citizenship (cf. Beltrán Reference Beltrán2020; Olson Reference Olson2004). It is these aspects of work, I suggest, that are made legible through disability. By this, I mean both the ways that disablement is naturalized as an expected consequence of work, and the ways that impairment and disability are implicated in contemporary formulations of the “good” worker. Whereas critical interrogations of post-Fordist work forms often stress the effects of job insecurity and flexibilization—and, in particular, the ways that workers are enjoined to “cultivate a spirit of self-entrepreneurialism and adaptation” (Chamberlain Reference Chamberlain2015, 98)—this analysis suggests something different. Namely, by deploying disability as an analytic, we can begin to appreciate how “the moral fortification of work in neoliberalism” (Frayne Reference Frayne2015, 16) has produced a new kind of ideal worker, one who is expected to aggressively monitor and optimize their productivity as well as their health, even as the conditions of their employment—precarious, poorly paid, and often lacking benefits—increase the likelihood of their eventual disablement.Footnote 13
Following in the footsteps of Firestone and Automatic Electric, a number of employers—among them, Microsoft, JPMorgan Chase, and Dell—have explicitly sought out workers whose disabilities make them uniquely suited to the task demands of the digital economy (Austin and Pisano Reference Austin and Pisano2017; Casselman Reference Casselman2019; Kurutz Reference Kurutz2024; Lu Reference Lu2020; Murawski Reference Murawski2019). Consider Auticon, an “autistic-majority” consulting firm that advertises its employees’ capacity to “focus over extended periods with little mental fatigue” (Auticon N.d.), or SAP’s “Autism at Work” program, which “leverages the unique abilities and perspectives” of its autistic employees (SAP N.d.). Without downplaying the importance of efforts to increase disability employment, these programs highlight the ways in which disability appears both as a consequence of employment and a condition of its realization.Footnote 14 Specifically, the disabled worker embodies what is frequently obscured by the emphasis on “wellness optimization” and self-management within the contemporary workplace—that perhaps the ideal worker of the post-Fordist digital economy is not best captured by the “entrepreneurial, self-directed, flexible,” and—above all—fit worker (Cederström and Spicer Reference Cederström and Spicer2015, 3; Duffy Reference Duffy2017, 226; cf. Ajunwa Reference Ajunwa2023; Hull and Pasquale Reference Hull and Pasquale2018). Instead, these hiring practices clarify the debilitating aspects of new work forms while also hinting at the limits of upholding work as both a condition and realization of citizenship. And, as with the work performed by the disabled laborer in sustaining older visions of free, independent labor, here too, we might note the ways that disability has been deployed to uphold the imperative of labor in the context of its transformation.
More generally, this investigation models an alternative approach to disability in political science and political theory by focusing less on disability as an identity or a condition that is visited upon individuals than as an analytic category that can be used to discern and interrogate aspects of our social and political worlds. Looking at the ways disabled labor was used to fortify the emergent connection between work and citizenship in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, this article reveals the centrality of disability to our notions of political belonging.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
I would like to thank Mark Golub, Demetra Kasimis, Patchen Markell, Claire McKinney, Sue Schweik, Agatha Slupek, Karen Tani, Lena Zuckerwise, and especially David Temin, Liz Wingrove, and Linda Zerilli for their comments on earlier drafts. Thank you, too, to participants at the 2018 APSA Annual Meeting, the 2019 WPSA Annual Meeting, the 2019 Cambridge Political Thought and Intellectual History Graduate Conference, the Chicago Political Theory Workshop, and the Michigan Political Theory Workshop. I am particularly grateful to the APSR editors and anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful and detailed feedback.
CONFLICT OF INTEREST
The author declares no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.
ETHICAL STANDARDS
The author affirms this research did not involve human participants.
Comments
No Comments have been published for this article.