Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-r5d9c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-31T20:44:23.214Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The lower cavity: the origins and history of an anatomical idea

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 August 2025

Dmitry Ezrokhi*
Affiliation:
Department of Classical Studies, https://ror.org/03qxff017 Hebrew University of Jerusalem , Jerusalem, Israel
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper examines the history of the ‘lower cavity’ of the gastrointestinal tract, a distinctive anatomical feature in Greco-Roman medicine that described a second stomach-like organ in the large intestine. It traces how a bipartite model of the digestive system emerged in fourth-century bce Greek medical and philosophical thought and persisted in the works of influential figures such as Galen, Vesalius, and Glisson, despite shifts in terminology, anatomical observations, and physiological theories. The study demonstrates that this understanding arose primarily from three complementary factors: a specific terminology that paired the stomach with a lower cavity, systematic animal dissections that revealed pronounced caeca in certain species, and emerging physiological theories that required separate bodily receptacles for digested food and residues. Through this case study, the paper illuminates how premodern anatomical knowledge was articulated by a constant negotiation between animal bodies, human bodies, and past textual authorities, facilitating the surprising longevity of ideas like the ‘lower cavity’ in the gastrointestinal tract.

Information

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is used to distribute the re-used or adapted article and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

The interpretation of Greek and Roman anatomical descriptions is a complex task. Dense technical jargon, reliance on lost visual aids, and attempts to convey sensory experience through limited linguistic tools all contribute to the challenge. Furthermore, some anatomical structures described by ancient authors are not readily identifiable in the human body. For instance, Aristotle famously describes a three-chambered heart (instead of four), and Galen locates a non-existent complex network of arteries, the retiform plexus (diktuoeidēs plegma), at the base of the human brain.Footnote 1 In the past, such inaccuracies puzzled scholars, who struggled to explain how past luminaries could have erred so blatantly. Recent scholarship has thankfully moved beyond simply identifying and explaining these instances as ‘errors’, focusing instead on understanding the historical circumstances that made these descriptions plausible for their authors and audiences.Footnote 2

This paper brings to light another rarely noticed and similarly ‘problematic’ anatomical description: the ‘lower cavity’ of the gastrointestinal tract. Greco-Roman medical texts from the fourth century BCE onward consistently reference two ‘cavities’ (koiliai), an upper and a lower. The ‘upper cavity’ (anō koilia) is readily identified with the stomach. However, the ‘lower cavity’ (katō koilia) lacks a clear anatomical correlate. While early uses of the term might generally refer to the abdomen, after the fourth century BCE, most Greek sources treat it as a distinct anatomical structure within the human gastrointestinal tract. In fact, this bipartite understanding of the digestive system became deeply embedded in subsequent Roman and later anatomical thought.

In this paper, I trace the history of this anatomical idea. The first half examines the reasons for its emergence. In Section 2, I provide evidence documenting its prevalence among fourth-century BCE Greek physicians and philosophers. In Section 3, I argue that three factors contributed to the consolidation of this bicameral understanding of human gastrointestinal anatomy: an older terminological distinction between an ‘upper’ and a ‘lower’ cavity, the new availability of animal dissection data, and the ‘cooking’ theory of digestion.

The second half of the paper examines how this notion survived outside its original context, persisting through three major changes: in anatomical terms, anatomical ideas, and physiological theories. Section 4 explores the idea’s presence in Galen’s works in the second century CE, showing its endurance despite significant shifts in gastrointestinal terminology. In Section 5, I turn to the sixteenth century CE, demonstrating how early modern anatomists maintained this notion while challenging its anatomical underpinnings. Finally, Section 6 focuses on the seventeenth-century philosopher–physician Francis Glisson, who upheld this notion despite being aware of earlier anatomical criticisms, and despite holding a fundamentally different understanding of digestive physiology than his predecessors. In the conclusion, I reflect on the survival of peripheral anatomical ideas and propose that the ‘lower cavity’ persisted precisely because of its marginal status, allowing it to adapt to changing frameworks without attracting critical scrutiny.

The consolidation of the bipartite model

Our earliest Greek medical texts, compiled in the so-called Hippocratic Corpus, do not provide a coherent anatomical account of the gastrointestinal tract. Typically, this labyrinth of tissue, cavities, and tubes was denoted by general terms such as ‘the intestines’ (ta entera), ‘the entrails’ (ta kola), or ‘the cavity’ (hē koiliē).Footnote 3 When the Hippocratic authors employed the division between an upper and lower cavity, it usually referred to the division of the whole torso, or ventral cavity, between the chest and the abdomen, separated by the diaphragm. This began to change in the fourth century BCE, as an important semantic shift occurred in the usage of this division. Now, it no longer primarily referred to a topological division of the torso, but to two distinct anatomical structures within the gastrointestinal tract. The most extensive evidence for this change comes from Aristotle.

In his Meteorology, he states that the upper cavity is the site of heat-induced cooking (pepsis) of food (trophē), while leftover substances excreted from the digestive process undergo putrefaction (sēpsis) in the lower cavity.Footnote 4 ‘Upper cavity’ thus no longer refers to the chest, but to an organ into which food is conveyed and then stored for elaboration, i.e. the stomach. By analogy, we should assume that whatever its identity, the ‘lower cavity’ also no longer refers to the whole abdomen, but to a cavernous anatomical structure within it.

This schema is developed in Aristotle’s description of internal human anatomy in the History of Animals.

T1 ‘The human cavity (koiliē) resembles that of a dog, as it is not much larger than an intestine, but rather appears as a somewhat wide intestine. After this comes a single intestine, coiled and fairly broad. The lower cavity (katō koiliē) resembles that of a pig, for it is wide, and the section extending from it to the anus is thick and short.’Footnote 5

In this passage, Aristotle refers to four structures within the human gastrointestinal tract. The first structure, located directly below the oesophagus, is termed ‘cavity’ and corresponds to what Aristotle refers to elsewhere as ‘the upper cavity’, the stomach. This is followed by a coiled tube, which he identifies as the intestine. Subsequently, there is a second, or lower, cavity, which connects to the anus via another short intestine (Figure 1).

Figure 1. A schematic representation of the gastrointestinal tract according to Aristotle’s History of Animals.

Thus, a certain parallelism emerges between the stomach and this lower cavity, as both are cavernous structures designated for storing substances with an intestinal tube extending from them. This parallel appears again in Aristotle’s other anatomical description of the gastrointestinal tract, in the third book of Parts of Animals. There, he employs somewhat different terms to convey a similar picture: there is a second cavity, this time called ‘the colon’ (to kolon), from which a convoluted intestine called ‘the spiral’ (hē hēlix) extends, thus mirroring the upper cavity and the intestine that extends from it (Figure 2).Footnote 6 In this text, moreover, Aristotle provides an important physiological role and a teleological justification for this intestinal anatomy: digested food is stored in the lower cavity/colon to ensure that no unabsorbed nutrients are left in it and then passes into the coiled spiral ‘so that nature might manage (timieuētai hē phusis) the flow of residue and it will not occur all at once (mē athroos ēi)’.Footnote 7

Figure 2. A schematic representation of the gastrointestinal tract according to Aristotle’s Parts of Animals.

We find similar anatomical ideas in the fragmentary remains of the works of Diocles of Carystus, a fourth-century BCE physician. Despite the scarcity of information about his life and intellectual milieu, Diocles’s contributions to Greek medicine have been widely acknowledged in both ancient and modern times.Footnote 8 His efforts in systematising anatomy and physiology bear remarkable similarities to those of Aristotle and his student-collaborator Theophrastus, suggesting a probable exchange of ideas between Diocles and the Lyceum.

In his scattered comments on gastrointestinal anatomy, Diocles refers to what Aristotle termed ‘the (upper) cavity’ as ‘the (upper) stomach’ ([anō] gastēr), while reserving the term ‘lower cavity’ for the corresponding area lower in the intestinal tract. Adding to the terminological complexity, Diocles uses ‘cavity’ (koilia) to denote the entire ventral cavity, encompassing both the upper stomach and the lower cavity – a region Aristotle himself named gastēr (see Table 1).Footnote 9 The first fragment I examine here, extracted from a treatise on health maintenance regimens, outlines the ideal conditions for waking:

T2 ‘Usually, it is good to wake up when food has already moved from the upper stomach to the lower cavity (methestēkotōn ēdē tōn sitiōn ek tēs anō gastros epi tēn katō koilian). It occurs in the best way, shortly before sunrise, in people who are young and in the prime of life, ten minutes before sunrise and in summer, five. In older people, it occurs closer to sunrise than it does for young people in winter and summer.’Footnote 10

Table 1. Fourth-century BCE terms for gastrointestinal anatomy

In this text, Diocles associates the optimal time for waking up with the progression of ingested food from the ‘upper stomach’ to the ‘lower cavity’. He notes that the specific moment before sunrise when digestion concludes differs among individuals. This variance is particularly evident when comparing the elderly with the young, but even among the youth, it fluctuates with the changing seasons. Diocles’s observations assume an anatomical scheme of the gastrointestinal tract similar to the one seen in Aristotle above. The upper stomach thus serves as a reservoir for unprocessed food, whereas the lower cavity is a depository for digested material.Footnote 11

In a second fragment, Diocles explores the aetiology of flatulence in the stomach within a broader discussion of abdominal ailments.

T3 ‘One should assume that those people who are called flatulent have excessive heat in the vessels carrying food from the stomach, and that the blood in them has congealed. It is clear that there is an obstruction around these vessels since the body does not receive food, but it remains in the stomach unprocessed (en tēi gastri diamenein akatergaston). Earlier [sc. before flatulence], these blood vessels took in [food], while most of the material was secreted to the lower cavity (ta de polla apokrinantōn eis tēn katō koilian).’Footnote 12

The fragment suggests that flatulence arises from an obstruction surrounding the blood vessels near the stomach, preventing them from receiving and absorbing food. The obstruction occurs due to excessive heat in the stomach area, which causes the blood in these vessels to congeal. This blockage leads to food accumulating in the stomach, unlike the typical process where these vessels absorb nutrition while secreting residues into the lower cavity, presumably via the connecting intestinal tract. While the precise physiological mechanisms described in this fragment remain unclear,Footnote 13 T3 again displays the views encountered in T1 and T2: the digestive tract comprises two interconnected cavities, an upper and a lower. The upper stomach houses undigested food while the lower cavity serves as a reservoir for disposable residues, with a connecting intestinal tube between them. There is also a hint of another physiological principle common to him and Aristotle, on which I elaborate below, namely that digestion occurs when the body’s innate heat cooks the food in the upper cavity.

Thus, an anatomically consistent but terminologically diverse picture emerges from the fourth-century BCE sources we examined so far. As G.E.R. Lloyd observed, the state of anatomical terminology throughout antiquity was ‘a situation bordering on terminological anarchy’, with no institutional guidelines or universally recognised norms. Thus, this remarkable similarity of anatomical content can be obscured by differences in terms.Footnote 14 Aristotle’s koilia is equivalent to Diocles’s gastēr, and Diocles’s katō koilia corresponds to Aristotle’s kolon (See Table 1 below).

We should bear the fluctuating state of Greek anatomical terminology in mind when approaching our next source, taken from Mnesitheus of Athens, another fourth-century BCE physician who is generally, though not uncontroversially, considered Diocles’s younger contemporary.Footnote 15 Here, for the first time, we encounter a direct acknowledgement of the confusing nature of gastrointestinal anatomical terms and the ideas they describe. The quotation is part of a general anatomical survey:

T4 ‘Those with a swollen abdomen, their upper cavity is full and large, while the intestines are small (plērēs toutōn ē men anō koilia megalē, entera de mikra). This is why many such people suffer from ailments around their upper cavity, whether full or hungry. Let no one think that I speak of an upper and a lower cavity without knowing that humans have only one stomach (monokoilios). But a thick lower intestine lies underneath it – this is indeed what I call the lower cavity (to de katō enteron upokeitai pachu, touto dē legō katō koilian).’Footnote 16

T4 highlights the fact that during the period in question, the fourth century BCE, the notion of a secondary, lower cavity within the gastrointestinal tract was not universally recognised, and its precise definition may have been unclear to many. Mnesitheus addresses a potential point of confusion arising from his use of the terms ‘upper’ and ‘lower’ cavities. His concern is that readers might mistakenly infer that he considers humans not to be monokoilioi, that is, to possess multiple stomachs, like ruminants. This misunderstanding stems from another ambiguity in Greek anatomical terminology, where the various stomachs of ruminants were also referred to as koliai (cavities), together with a host of other anatomical structures that could have also been reasonably described as cavities.Footnote 17 To clarify this point, Mnesitheus, likely drawing upon terms from previously mentioned authors, emphasises that humans are categorically monokoilioi, meaning they possess only a single stomach, i.e. a single cavity below the oesophagus for digesting food. In the context of this adjective, however, ‘cavity’ specifically denotes the stomach or the ‘upper cavity’. Although humans have just this one type of cavity, Mnesitheus asserts the existence of a second, lower one, which he identifies as the thick intestine situated beneath the stomach.Footnote 18

The audience of Mnesitheus’s defence, whether laypersons unfamiliar with the technical connotations of ‘lower cavity’ or fellow physicians who contested his terminology, remains uncertain. However, it seems that such relatively recent nomenclature was part of an emerging attempt by various thinkers and professionals to accurately describe and name a hitherto uncharted area of the body’s interior. This is consistent with how Aristotle broached the subject of this lower cavity, referring to it as ‘that which is called the kolon’ (to kaloumenon kolon). In technical Greek literature, qualifiers such as the middle-passive participle kaloumenon often flag specialised terms, signalling to the reader that these terms diverge from their everyday usage.Footnote 19 Thus, we have evidence suggesting that this anatomical differentiation, while building on the prior segmentation of the torso into upper and lower cavities, was a technical distinction introduced by professional physicians and natural philosophers during the fourth century BCE.

Why two cavities?

The prevalence of bipartite descriptions of the human gastrointestinal tract among fourth-century BCE physicians and philosophers raises the question of what led these authors to think of the digestive system in this way. This question is particularly striking since such a model is notably absent from earlier medical texts like the Hippocratic Corpus, and more significantly, because human anatomy lacks any structure resembling the second cavity described in these accounts. I propose that this anatomical model emerged from the intersection of two key developments in fourth-century BCE Greek medicine. First, the rise of systematic animal dissection provided anatomists with observations of certain animals, particularly pigs, whose digestive tracts actually do display a more pronounced bipartite structure. Second, and crucially, this particular anatomical model gained wide acceptance because it aligned with broader theories of digestion physiology that were gaining prominence during this period. That is, while ancient anatomists encountered various animal digestive systems that could have served as models for human anatomy, the bipartite structure observed in some proved especially compelling because it corresponded with emerging physiological frameworks.Footnote 20

The rise of comparative animal dissection in fourth-century BCE Greek medicine and natural philosophy had far-reaching effects on Greek biomedical thought. Footnote 21 The reasons for this shift, being part of a broader and formative change in the intellectual Zeitgeist of Greek thinkers in this period, lie beyond the scope of this paper.Footnote 22 What is significant, however, is that all the authors surveyed in Section 2 above demonstrated a serious interest in mapping the human body’s interior with unprecedented descriptive and terminological precision, relying on insights probably gained from such dissections. The attempt to map the gastrointestinal tract, as evidenced above, was part of this undertaking. Thus, new anatomical ideas emerging in this period are better examined in relation to this novel investigative endeavour.Footnote 23

Our sources make clear, however, that in fourth century BCE Greece, physicians and philosophers did not perform human dissections. Instead, they reconstructed internal human anatomy primarily through extrapolation from animal dissections. The most compelling testimony comes from Aristotle. In the introduction to his survey of human anatomy in the first book of the History of Animals, he admits: ‘The internal parts (ta entos) of humans are mostly unknown. So, we must examine them in reference to the parts of other animals with a similar nature (echei paraplēsian tēn phusin)’.Footnote 24

This reliance on animal models is particularly significant for understanding the bipartite description of the digestive system. The human digestive system lacks any structure that could be considered a true second cavity comparable to the stomach—the small intestine is markedly smaller in diameter, and the large intestine is essentially a wide tube rather than a stomach-like cavity with a coiled intestine extending from it. However, such bipartite structures are observable in many other animals.

Here, Aristotle provides another valuable clue. In T1, he draws specific comparisons between human and animal anatomy, noting that the human upper cavity resembles that of a dog, while the lower cavity resembles that of a pig.Footnote 25 He elaborates on this comparison by observing that both humans and pigs share wide (plateia) lower cavities.Footnote 26 Modern anatomical knowledge helps illuminate why Aristotle might have drawn this parallel. In pigs, the initial portion of the large intestine—what we now identify as the caecum and parts of the ascending colon—differs markedly from the small intestine in both size and structure. This section is substantially larger, wider, and more distinctly articulated than the preceding intestinal tract (see Figure 3). Beyond this enlarged portion, the intestine narrows into a coiled tube before connecting to the thick, straight rectum. It is not hard at all to conceive of the porcine caecum and the stomach as a pair of protruding, inflated cavities in an otherwise more or less uniform intestinal tract. This anatomical pattern is not unique to pigs but appears in various other non-human animals, including horses.Footnote 27

Figure 3. Left: Porcine large intestine, view from above. C = The first bulky part of the large intestine, which was identified as the lower cavity (katō koilia), the colon (to kolon), or the blind intestine (to tuphlon enteron) in the examined authors. D = the part identified by Aristotle as ‘the spiral’ (hē hēlix). Right: Porcine large intestine, side view. Adapted with permission from Singh, op. cit. (Footnote note 27), Fig. 34.12.B, D.

I propose, therefore, that fourth-century BCE anatomists mapped an anatomical feature observable in some animal bodies, namely a gastrointestinal anatomy that lends itself to a bipartite description, onto their imagined reconstruction of internal human anatomy. Besides explaining the observational basis of the lower cavity, having the animal, and specifically porcine, model in mind also helps explain why Aristotle used the term ‘spiral’ in Parts of Animals (see Figure 2) to describe the narrowing and twisting tube connecting the lower cavity to the anus. The term precisely captures the winding path of the latter part of a porcine large intestine.

Animal dissections made a bipartite gastrointestinal model available, but why was it adopted for human anatomy when other animal models showed different arrangements? I propose that this particular model prevailed, at least in part, because it aligned with emerging physiological theories about digestion. While these theories existed in rudimentary form earlier, they gained a new prominence and coherent expression in the fourth century BCE. The key ideas of this digestion theory were that digestion occurs through the action of internal bodily heat, producing both nutrients and a variety of residues, and that each type of residue requires its own proper place in the body.Footnote 28

From the earliest days of Greek speculation about the body, analogies between internal anatomical structures and artificial containers were ubiquitous. The body was thought of as assembled from vessels, cups, containers, and receptacles, not unlike their clay, skin, and glass counterparts.Footnote 29 This overarching conception of the body significantly influenced all areas of medico-biological thought. For example, the author of the Hippocratic treatise Humors used processes observed in real-life containers, such as seepage or percolation, to explain the passage of food from the stomach into the rest of the body: ‘As a new water jar seeps through but keeps [liquids] when older, so the stomach lets food pass and holds sediments as a vessel’.Footnote 30 This container-based understanding of the body naturally gives rise to the idea that in properly functioning bodies, each substance has its own designated receptacle. Perhaps the most famous early articulation of this notion is found in the Hippocratic Diseases 4, where vital bodily functions are attributed to the interplay of phlegm, blood, bile, and water, with their natural sources (pēgai) identified as the head, heart, liver, and spleen, respectively.Footnote 31 Diocles’s explanation of flatulence in T3 also reflects similar reasoning: naturally, there exists one location for incoming food and another for excrement.

This ‘physics of the container᾽, as Robert Joly termed it, provided a flexible framework for various physiological and anatomical theories.Footnote 32 Within this framework, physicians and philosophers could then specify, each according to their view, which cavities exist in the body, what substances they contain, and how these substances move and transform. Yet Aristotle, Diocles, and Mnesitheus shared a specific view of how bodily materials are produced during digestion and placed it within the framework of the body as a set of containers with a proper place for each natural substance. They all maintained that the body’s innate heat cooks or digests (pettein) food, dividing it into nutritious material and residues (perittōma)—the latter term notably absent from earlier medical texts.Footnote 33 This process mirrors common observations of heat’s effects on materials, where heating creates two distinct layers: a useful portion and refuse. Aristotle explicitly draws this parallel, comparing digestion to how milk separates into curd and whey.Footnote 34

Aristotle also offers the clearest account of this new understanding of natural residue production. He defines residue (perittōma) as the surplus (hupoleimma) of food—specifically, those components of ingested food that the body does not absorb after a process of heat-induced elaboration.Footnote 35 In his view, faeces are just the first of several residues produced as food moves through the body. He thus applies this same model of heat-induced separation between thicker and thinner layers to explain how the body generates most of its substances, including bile, phlegm, milk, marrow, and semen, with each process yielding both nutritional elements and residues. Although long physiological descriptions by Diocles and Mnesitheus do not survive, they employed the new term perittōma with a similar meaning, as suggested by what appear to be direct quotations rather than later interpolations.Footnote 36 Given that the term is both new and theoretically charged, it is yet another testimony for a common theory of digestion shared by the three.

The idea that digestion works through heat-induced separation between nutriment and residues, coupled with the broader conception that each substance in the body requires its own designated container, made the anatomical model of two digestive cavities compelling. This connection between physiological theory and anatomical understanding is most clearly articulated in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals:

T5 ‘There must be different places for undigested food and residue (te apeptou kai tou perittōmatos), and there should also be a place where the food changes (en ōi metaballei). So, one part will hold incoming food, while the other useless residue. And just as there is a different time for each process, they should also differ in their places.’Footnote 37

Aristotle subscribes to the notion that each bodily substance has a natural container or receptacle, such that two substances entail the existence of two separate containers. He also employs two theoretically specific terms to describe food before and after digestion. The food in the stomach is ‘undigested or ‘uncooked’, while faeces are residues. Thus, Aristotle postulates a ‘proper place’ (oikeios topos) for each residue, a site for both their generation and storage.Footnote 38 Drawing analogies from pairings like ‘stomach: food’ and ‘bladder: urine’, it seems reasonable that observing wide and cavernous caeca in animals would lead to the conclusion that it serves as a similar cavity, specifically for dry excrement. Conversely, it is reasonable to suppose that, like uncooked food and urine, the dry residues of the body will have a cavity proper to them.

Given the complex and variegated nature of intestinal anatomy in different animals, it is hard to imagine that the bipartite description would gain such wide purchase on the anatomical imagination of fourth-century BCE physicians and philosophers were it not aligned with the theoretical exigencies of their theories.Footnote 39 The anatomical observation of somewhat pronounced second cavities in animal gastrointestinal tracts reinforced physiological theories postulating a proper cavity for each substance, including faeces. Conversely, these physiological theories directed observers to identify and emphasize certain anatomical features in animals that might otherwise have gone unremarked. Once one knew to look for a second cavity because theoretical principles suggested it should exist, it became readily identifiable in enough animals to substantiate its anatomical reality and support inferences about human anatomy.

To conclude this first part of the paper, we see that by the end of the fourth century BCE, a new understanding of the human gastrointestinal tract emerged, which rested on three complementary legs. First, there was an older terminological tradition where the torso housed or was divided into an upper and a lower cavity. Second, observations originating from animal dissection facilitated the identification of animal caeca as a lower cavity also in humans. Finally, there was a physiological view that the caecum functions as a residue receptacle, storing it and sometimes even digesting some of it, as does the stomach. In the following sections, I will show how this idea survived in later centuries, although these three legs gradually faltered. First, Galen will abandon the terminology but keep the anatomy and physiology. Later, Vesalius will dismiss the anatomical basis of this vision but nonetheless adopt its physiological premises. Finally, in the seventeenth century, the bipartite description will outlive shifts in its physiological underpinnings.

Galen’s new terminology

The Hellenistic period witnessed an exponential accumulation of Greek knowledge about the body. The process was fuelled by several factors, including the increasing systematicity of animal dissections conducted upon a wider array of animals and, for the first time in antiquity, the practice of human dissections and probably also vivisections. This enabled the differentiation of internal substructures previously barely distinguishable to the naked eye.Footnote 40 Such a shift in anatomical knowledge also considerably impacted the understanding of the gastrointestinal system. Two prominent figures in Hellenistic medicine, Herophilus of Chalcedon and Erasistratus of Ceos, made significant contributions in this area. Herophilus identified the ‘duodenum’, the first straight and uncoiled section of the small intestine extending from the stomach, naming it the ‘twelve-finger part’ (dōdekadaktulon enteron). Erasistratus, for his part, provided the earliest recorded reference to the jejunum or ‘the fasting’ (nēstis) as the second anatomical subdivision of the small intestine, distinguished by its numerous coils.Footnote 41

Changes in this period likely led to the adoption of a new anatomical nomenclature for the gastrointestinal tract during the Roman era, though the fragmentary nature of the evidence necessitates some speculation. Be that as it may, both Rufus of Ephesus (first century CE) and Galen of Pergamon (second and third centuries CE), our primary sources for anatomical terminology in the Roman period, utilise a new division of the intestinal tract into six parts: duodenum, jejunum, ileum (or thin intestine), colon, caecum, and rectum (Figure 4).Footnote 42 The ‘lower cavity’ does not appear as a proper name for any of the parts of the intestine.

Figure 4. A schematic description of the gastrointestinal tract according to Galen.

However, although the influx of anatomical knowledge derived from animal and human dissections led to abandoning the ‘upper cavity’ and ‘lower cavity’ terminology, it did not eliminate the bipartite conception of the gastrointestinal tract. For example, while Galen avoids the term ‘lower cavity’ as a reference to a swollen pouch in the large intestine that functionally resembles the stomach, he surprisingly posits the existence of such an organ in the first section of the large intestine, referring to its as ‘that which is called the blind intestine’, or caecum.

T6 ‘The caecum is, in fact, like some thick stomach suitable for the reception of residues (oion gastēr tis esti pacheia eis hupodochēn perittōmatōn epitēdeios), and the colon is analogous to it. In most birds, the caecum is double (ditton esti) because of their strong [sc. digestion] activity. Even if something has escaped absorption in the passage through the thin intestine, it is all completely extracted during the longer stay (epi pleon monē) in the caecum. And since the activity of the parts around the stomach and intestines are strong in almost all birds, there are two deposits of residues (apotheseis tōn perittōmatōn egenonto dittai), so nothing undrained (anexikmaston) might be left behind if the food passed through quickly, and the evacuation might occur all at once and not continuously and in small amounts (athroan eisapax, mē sunechōs kai kata brachu). But nature, having made one caecum for all humans and all terrestrial animals, placed it on the right side of the loin […].’Footnote 43

Galen does not discuss the lower cavity here. However, he describes the same anatomical structure that I proposed should be identified as such—the caecum.Footnote 44 His depiction of this part of the intestine is consistent with how sources from the fourth century BCE portray the lower cavity. Galen characterises it as a receptacle akin to the stomach, highlighting both its anatomical and functional–physiological similarities. That is, unlike other intestinal sections that primarily act as conduits for waste, the caecum, much like the stomach, is adapted for prolonged retention of faeces. This suggests, in its turn, an anatomical structure more akin to a cavity than a narrow tube.

Furthermore, Galen echoes the same teleological justification for this structure that we encountered earlier in Aristotle. This is unsurprising given Galen’s deep familiarity with Aristotle, his commitment to teleological reasoning, and even further elaboration of the ‘cooking’ theory of digestion and the logic of residue production.Footnote 45 Although Galen refers to a gastēr and a tuphlon enteron, the relationship he describes between them mirrors that of an anō koilia or anō gastēr to its lower counterpart.

Moreover, the persistence of this bipartite description serves as a reminder that human dissection was never the standard practice in Greco-Roman antiquity. Although our sources acknowledge that both Herophilus and Erasistratus engaged in such procedures, it remains evident that even they relied heavily on animal models for understanding human anatomy.Footnote 46 It is also clear that the vast majority of Galen’s first-hand dissection experience came from animals.Footnote 47 Unlike fourth-century BCE sources, who worked with multiple and often unreported animal anatomical models when discussing human anatomy, Galen formulated a developed hierarchy of reliable animal sources for human anatomy. His preferred model organism was the monkey (pithēkos).Footnote 48 This term refers, in all probability, to the Barbary macaque.Footnote 49 As with pigs, the caecum of the Barbary macaque is significantly larger than that of humans.Footnote 50 Therefore, it is reasonable to consider it a somewhat enlarged stomach. When combined with the heat-based digestion model and reinforced by the prestige of Aristotle’s authority, Galen had compelling grounds to adhere to the bipartite conceptualisation. Thus, the bipartite understanding of the gastrointestinal tract persisted through the significant transformations Greek medicine underwent between the classical and Roman periods, supported by similar theoretical commitments and zoocentric dissection practices.

Early modern anatomy

In late antiquity, Galen’s anatomical and physiological thought underwent progressive systematisation and regularisation by successive generations of teachers and commentators. The resulting medical theory, which came to be known as ‘Galenism’, was accepted by most physicians in the Byzantine, Arabic, and Latin medical traditions.Footnote 51 The significant variations between the different systematisations of Galen’s immense corpus need not concern us here. Suffice it to say that with regard to both the anatomy of the gastrointestinal tract and the physiology of digestion, there were no radical deviations from what we have briefly described above until the early modern period.

Sixteenth-century Europe, and particularly Italy, witnessed the revival of human and animal dissection on a scale unseen since the heyday of Ptolemaic Alexandria.Footnote 52 The emerging evidence from dissections, especially those conducted on human bodies, drew renewed attention to Galen’s description of the gastrointestinal tract. This was particularly the case in light of Andreas Vesalius’s (1514–64) explicit critique of Galen in his seminal 1543 work On the Fabric of the Human Body (De humani corporis fabrica libri septem). However, even shortly before this, Italian anatomists grappled with the challenge of reconciling Galen’s account with their first-hand experience, since it increasingly suggested the absence of an intestinal structure ‘like some stomach’. To understand this controversy, it is crucial to recognise that Galen’s description not only ascribes a structure to the human body that early modern anatomists failed to find—a stomach-like caecum—but it also overlooks a structure they readily identified: the vermiform appendix (commonly known simply as the appendix), a worm-like extension of the large intestine unique to humans.Footnote 53

A reasonable approach to resolving this discrepancy was to equate the ‘blind intestine’ Galen observed in animals with the human vermiform appendix. For instance, in his 1536 Introduction to Anatomy (Liber introductorius anatomiae), Venetian anatomist Niccolò Massa (1489–1589) commences his ninth chapter on the caecum by replicating Galen’s anatomy and physiology. He describes the caecum as storing faeces ‘so that its power might extract complete nourishment from the food. This intestine occupies the space on the right between the kidney and the thigh’. However, Massa’s personal observations diverge from Galenic orthodoxy. He notes the variability in the size of this structure across different bodies and then concedes:

T7 ‘And its size [sc. of the caecum] is not the same in everyone, as it is less in some and more in others […] [In some] its size exceeds that of the stomach […] I myself have dissected many (ego seccaui multos) in whom I did not find this large intestine. Indeed, it seemed to be the same substance as the colon (idem substantia cum colo). But in these [bodies], I found a certain hanging substance of the size of one finger in length, and in thickness like the thickness of the pen with which I write. And since this appendage is not found in those who have a manifest and ample intestinal sac [sc. caecum], I often thought that this appendage is the intestinal sac that was rendered inoperative in infancy.’Footnote 54

In essence, Massa attempts to reconcile dissection evidence with Galen’s descriptions, treating the vermiform appendix and the manifest caecum found in animals as analogous structures. Notice that Massa still operates under the assumption that the normative human body possesses an enlarged Galenic caecum, the underdevelopment of which sometimes results in what we now identify as the vermiform appendix. This is another reminder of Galen’s influence as an early modern anatomical authority.Footnote 55

Six years later, Vesalius’s critique extends Massa’s argument both in substance and anti-Galenic rhetoric:Footnote 56

T8 ‘I know what most people say about the caecum these days. They are surely deceived by the fact that Galen somewhere numbers the caecum among [the parts of the] large intestines, and it is described by him and the anatomists who have followed him as no less than a large pouch and like another stomach (neque aliter quam amplus quispiam saccus, ac ueluti alter quidem esset uentriculus). But nonetheless, what I think should be called the caecum in humans is shorter than all the other [parts of the] intestines and by far narrower and tighter than the tightest parts of all the other intestines, and is more like a thick worm coiled into circles than an intestine (et crassiori lumbrico in orbes conuoluto potius quam intestine simile)… Galen attributes to it a size and a use which it seems to certainly lack, describing his tailed apes (caudata simia) with this appendage rather than humans. Furthermore, had Galen, the greatest admirer of nature, ever observed human intestines as he had those of dogs, he would have described this protruding appendix at the beginning of the human colon, its contiguity with the ileum, and the shape of the colon very differently.’Footnote 57

Vesalius rejects the notion that some humans possess a Galenic caecum while others have an appendix. He argues that no human has an actual blind intestine akin to ‘another stomach’ (ueluti alter quidem uentriculus). Galen’s misdescriptions are attributed to his excessive reliance on animal bodies for understanding human anatomy. Vesalius, therefore, chooses outright rejection over reconciling the traditional bipartite conception with newly uncovered anatomical evidence.Footnote 58

In T8, Vesalius asserts that in human anatomy, the term ‘blind intestine’ (caecum intestinum) should refer to what we today call the appendix and not to the caecum. Although ultimately rejected by anatomists, this suggestion was debated during early modernity. Gabriele Fallopio (1523–62), in his Anatomical Observations (Observationes anatomicae), explicitly concurs with Vesalius, adding only minor details.Footnote 59 Conversely, Realdo Colombo (1516–59) rejects the identification of the animal caecum with the human appendix, arguing instead that these are distinct structures, with the human caecum being very small and inconspicuous. Juan Valverde (c. 1525–c. 1587), in his 1560 Research on the Composition of the Human Body (Historia de la composicion del cuerpo humano), dismisses the debate as irrelevant semantic squabbles.Footnote 60 However, all the authors agree that Galen’s descriptions of human bodies are inadequate. This not only shows Vesalius’s significant influence on subsequent early modern anatomical discussions, but it also highlights the enduring impact of the Greco-Roman bipartite descriptions in negotiating anatomy during this era, when inherited traditions, the original context of which was long gone, were combined with new technologies, techniques, and observations in articulating the insides of the human body.

Finally, the rejection of Galen’s depiction of the caecum did not yet prompt a revision of his broader physiological theories. Vesalius remains largely aligned with Galenic digestive principles, even after critiquing Galen’s anatomical description of the digestive tract.Footnote 61 Just pages after arguing that the caecum and the stomach are nothing alike, Vesalius adopts a now familiar intestinal physiology and teleology:Footnote 62

T9 ‘[The large intestine] mainly helps so that we do not evacuate continuously but at long intervals (ne continuo, sed per longa interualla). For these [intestines] are furnished as a kind of stomach (tanquam uenter aliquis) for dry excrements, as the bladder is for urine. And for this reason, some have called them the lower stomach (inferiorem uentrem).’Footnote 63

While rejecting the caecum’s anatomical resemblance to the stomach, Vesalius embraces broader functional similarities between the large intestine and the stomach as receptacles and storage organs. His physiology of the large intestine explicitly echoes Galen’s idea of a ‘second stomach’ (tanquam uenter aliquis; compare to ‘oion gastēr tis’ in T6) and Aristotle’s teleological reasoning that the lower cavity exists to prevent continuous evacuation. As I have argued, this view was originally rooted in the anatomical observation of the caecum’s cavity in non-human animals that naturally led to comparisons with the stomach. However, Vesalius’s own anatomical observations revealed the intestinal tract as a complex, winding maze without a clear and articulated cavity below the stomach. Despite this divergence from Galenic anatomy, Vesalius retains the idea of the ‘second stomach’ in his understanding of intestinal function.

Francis Glisson and new ideas about digestion

The concept of a ‘second stomach’ demonstrated remarkable resilience amidst not just shifting anatomical terminology and knowledge but also changing physiological theories. In the seventeenth century, dominant perspectives on digestion underwent a significant transformation. Although Galen acknowledged the role of acidity and fermentation in digestion, he primarily attributed the process to innate bodily heat.Footnote 64 Early in the sixteenth century, the polymath Paracelsus (c. 1493–1541) and the Dutch physician–chemist Jan Baptist van Helmont (1580–1644) began redefining digestion not as cooking but as acid-based fermentation (fermentatio).Footnote 65 Consequently, the body was reimagined not as a kitchen processing food but as a chemical or alchemical laboratory transforming substances. Thus, not only was the anatomical framework underpinning the bipartite model of the gastrointestinal tract dismantled, but so too was the accompanying physiological theory.

As a final example, I will briefly consider one figure from this period, the anatomist and natural philosopher Francis Glisson, who served as the Regius Professor of Physic at Cambridge from 1636 until he died in 1677.Footnote 66 Like many of his contemporaries, Glisson adhered to a fermentative digestion theory. His extensive anatomical knowledge and familiarity with previous anatomical literature made him acutely aware of the small size of the human caecum. Nevertheless, in his final publication from 1677, titled Treatise on the Stomach and Intestines (Tractatus de ventriculo et intestinis), he explicitly argues against a previous suggestion by Italian anatomist Fabricius d’Acquapendente (1533–1619) that the small size of the caecum in humans renders it functionless.Footnote 67 Glisson presents a comprehensive defence of the caecum’s functionality as a secondary or auxiliary stomach, albeit in non-human animals.Footnote 68

He begins his discussion of the caecum by addressing the elephant in the room, the ‘diversitatis ratio’—the reason why the human caecum is relatively tiny compared to its significantly larger counterparts in other animals. He explains that while humans consume easily digestible food, necessitating only one stomach (unus ventriculus sufficit), animals with a coarser diet require additional digestive mechanisms. Ruminants possess multiple stomachs, whereas non-ruminants utilise ‘another cavity serving as a stomach’ (alia cavitas quasi ventriculo vicaria). In animals with an enlarged caecum, a division of labour exists between the stomach and the caecum: ‘[W]atery and raw chyle is extracted from the stomach and small intestines, whereas fatty and succulent chyle is derived from the caecum’. Thus, this concept of a secondary stomach persisted well into the seventeenth century.

Conclusion

Initially, in the fourth century BCE, an anatomical understanding of the human gastrointestinal tract as having two cavities emerged from a convergence of three elements: a specific terminology that paired the stomach with a lower cavity, an anatomical perception derived primarily from animal dissection, and a physiological theory of digestion as cooking that required distinct receptacles for food and residues. The interaction between these elements was complex—anatomical observations of enlarged caeca in animals like pigs provided a structural basis that aligned with theoretical requirements for separate containers in the body, while the terminology of ‘cavities’ helped articulate this understanding.

In Galen’s work, while the terminology shifted away from explicit reference to two cavities, the anatomical and functional parallels between the stomach and caecum remained. The early modern period brought a more dramatic transformation, as Vesalius’s human dissections challenged the anatomical basis of the ‘second stomach’. Yet even as anatomists like Vesalius rejected the existence of a stomach-like caecum in humans, they preserved the functional analogy between the large intestine and the stomach as storage organs. Finally, in Glisson’s work, we see how this conception could be reframed within new theories of digestion while being restricted primarily to non-human anatomy.

The existence of the ‘lower cavity’ as an operative anatomo-physiological idea was always dynamically negotiated between three complementary poles: the animal body, the human body, and the authoritative texts of the past (Aristotle and others for Galen, Galen and Aristotle for the early moderns). More to the point, the animal body and the authoritative texts that transposed it onto the human frame have exerted a remarkable influence on the way human anatomy was imagined, even in the face of systematic human dissections. Messa, Vesalius, and Glisson, and to a limited extent also Galen, give witness to the malleability of the human body before the other poles of this triangle. Each in his own way, shaped by their idiosyncratic relationship to past authorities, access to human and non-human dissection subjects, and personal agendas, attempted to resolve the tension between the unobservability of a ‘stomach-like’ anatomical structure in human bodies and its existence in authoritative descriptions and some animal bodies.Footnote 69 Anatomical knowledge in premodern medicine was not simply a matter of observation versus authority, or human versus animal anatomy. Rather, it emerged from a continuous process of negotiation between these different sources of knowledge.Footnote 70

Finally, I would like to suggest a possible reason for this peculiar idea’s longevity. The ‘lower cavity’ is far from being the only defunct scientific notion in the long history of Western science. As Hasok Chang observes, ‘The history of science appears as a graveyard of dead epistemic objects.’Footnote 71 Luminiferous ether, phlogiston, caloric, ‘Hippocratic’ humours, and Empedoclean elements all lie as remnants of obsolete scientific theories. Two characteristics are common to these examples: they are defunct epistemic objects, and they were once grand, contentious, and pivotal in their respective fields. Their emergence and decline trace the trajectories of their associated paradigms and worldviews. Conversely, some concepts, such as temperature, weight, and up and down, which are too fundamental to vanish together with the dominant theory through which they are explained and used in each period, consistently acquire new interpretations and significances as time passes.Footnote 72 However, our subject—the bipartite gastrointestinal tract—does not share the prominence of either category. It was neither crucial enough in Aristotelian, Galenic, or Vesalian systems to figure prominently in debates about them, nor was it essential to any subsequent systems that followed. This relative obscurity allowed the idea of a ‘second stomach’ to circulate freely, almost as if by inertia, detached from its original context. It was not perceived as threatening enough to warrant outright rejection, and it retained a semblance of credibility due to its historical presence and widespread acceptance. At the end of the day, ‘living off the grid’ might be one of the best strategies for surviving, even thriving, in the dangerous marshes of the history of science and medicine.

Acknowledgements

This paper is based in part on the author’s MA dissertation, written at the Department of Classical Studies at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem under the supervision of Orly Lewis and funded by the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (Project ATLOMY, GA 852550). The author thanks both Project ATLOMY and the Jack, Joseph and Morton Mandel School for Advanced Studies in the Humanities at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem for generous support during the research for this paper. The author thanks Orly Lewis, Marco Vespa, Pavel Gregorić, Donna Shalev, and Orna Harari for their comments on the dissertation and previous versions of the paper. The author thanks Elsevier Health Sciences for permission to reproduce Figure 3, Aviv Keshet for all other figures and illustrations in the paper, and Tim DeBold for his editorial services.

Financial support

Research for this paper was funded by the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (Project ATLOMY, GA 852550; PI Orly Lewis) and by the Jack, Joseph and Morton Mandel School for Advanced Studies in the Humanities at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem.

References

1 For these examples, see, most recently, Rocca, J., Galen on the Brain: Anatomical Knowledge and Physiological Speculation in the Second Century AD (Leiden: Brill, 2003), esp. 202–1910.1163/9789047401438CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Dean-Jones, L., ‘Aristotle’s Heart and the Heartless Man’, in Wee, John Z. (ed.), The Comparable Body: Analogy and Metaphor in Ancient Mesopotamian, Egyptian, and Greco-Roman Medicine (Leiden: Brill, 2017), 122–41Google Scholar.

2 See the introductory remarks in Bubb, C., ‘Blood Flow in Aristotle’, The Classical Quarterly, 70, 1 (2020), 137–5310.1017/S0009838820000531CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Benveniste, É., ‘Termes Gréco-Latins d’anatomie’, Revue de philologie, de littérature et d’histoire anciennes, 35 (1965), 713 Google Scholar; Roig, C. Roura, ‘Aproximaciones al lenguaje cientifico de la coleccion Hipocratica’, Emérita, 40 (1972), 318–29Google Scholar; Chantraine, P., ‘Remarques sur la langue et le vocabulaire du Corpus Hippocratique, in La Collection Hippocratique et son rôle dans l’histoire de la médicine (Leiden: Brill, 1975), 3540 Google Scholar; Oser-Grote, C.M., Aristoteles und Das Corpus Hipocraticum: Die Anatomie und Physiologie des Menschen (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 2004), 310 Google Scholar; Thumiger, C, ‘Guts, Hollows, and Coils: Inside Stories in Ancient Literature’, in Elsner, A.M. and Pietrzak-Franger, M. (eds), Medicine and Literature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2024), 2330 Google Scholar.

4 Mete. 4.3, 381b11–2. More on Aristotle’s understanding of digestive ‘cooking’ below.

5 Aristotle, Hist. An. 1.16, 495b24–29. All translations are my own. References to Greek and Latin texts follow the abbreviations of the Oxford Classical Dictionary, except the treatises of the Hippocratic Corpus, where I follow Craik, E.M., The ‘Hippocratic’ Corpus: Content and Context (London: Routledge, 2015)Google Scholar, and Galen, where I follow Rosen, R. and Singer, P. (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Galen (Oxford – New York: Oxford University Press, 2024)Google Scholar. For Aristotle’s History of Animals, I rely on Balme, D., History of Animals: Books I-X: Text, Vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)Google Scholar, for Parts of Animals on Louis, P., Aristote: Les parties des animaux (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1956)Google Scholar, and Meteorology on Louis, P., Aristote. Météorologiques. Tome II: Livres III-IV (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1982)Google Scholar. References to the Hippocratic Corpus and Galen mention the latest consulted edition in the footnote. Additionally, I adduced a reference to the corresponding pages in the standard editions of É. Littré, Hippocrate - Œuvres complètes, 9 vols. (Paris: J.B. Baillière et Fils, 1839–61) and Kühn, K.G., Claudii Galeni Opera Omnia, 20 vols (Leipzig: Karl Knobloch, 1821–33)Google Scholar, respectively.

6 Part. An. 3.14, 675a31–675b10. This description fits all animals, including humans, ‘whose intestines are not straight (pasi tois mē euthuenterois)’, as in simple organisms like small fish and insects. For an analysis of this passage, see D. Ezrokhi, ‘Aristotle’s Gastrointestinal System: Reconstruction and Interpretation’, in O. Lewis et al. (eds), ATLOMY. Greco-Roman Anatomy Atlas, https://www.atlomy.com/model-details/66 (accessed 16.07.2024). The entry also explains several interpretative and textual choices that cannot be elaborated here.

7 Part. An. 3.14, 675b20–22. This physiological effect has important psychological consequences, as it prevents animals from feeling constant hunger. In my analysis here and below, I focus on the more immediate and ‘purely’ physiological functions of gastrointestinal anatomical structures. The complex ways in which Greek and Roman physicians and philosophers theorised the relationship between nutritional anatomy, physiology, and psychological phenomena such as hunger merit a separate discussion. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

8 See van der Eijk, P.J., Diocles of Carystus: A Collection of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary, Vol. 2 (Leiden: Brill, 2001), xxxixli 10.1163/9789004377509CrossRefGoogle Scholar for discussion and bibliography.

9 Aristotle, Hist. An. 1.18, 493a 17–20.

10 Fr. 182,3–8 van der Eijk, from van der Eijk, P.J., Diocles of Carystus: A Collection of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary, Vol. 1 (Leiden: Brill, 2000)Google Scholar.

11 Van der Eijk translated katō koilia in this fragment as ‘the lower [part] of the belly’ (ibid., ad loc.). However, the pair anō gastēr-katō koilia in Diocles seems to be a version of the anō koilia-katō koilia division in Aristotle, designating two anatomical structures and not two parts of the same structure, which will be more naturally conveyed by the genitive katō tēs koilias. Moreover, Diocles seems here to be describing the trajectory of food in the gastrointestinal tract, referring to its different parts. More broadly, as I make clear in section 3, I assume that fourth-century BCE authors, such as Diocles, are at least attempting to provide precise anatomical descriptions about specific organs.

12 Fr. 109 van der Eijk, from van der Eijk, ibid.

13 This is a problematic fragment with an interesting reception history. See van der Eijk, ibid., 214–26.

14 G.E.R. Lloyd, Science, Folklore and Ideology: Studies in the Life Sciences in Ancient Greece (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 163. See also Roura Roig, op. cit. (note 3); Chantraine, op. cit. (note 3); Lanza, D., ‘Quelques remarques sur le travail linguistique du médecin’, in Lasserre, F. and Mudry, P. (eds), Formes de pensée dans la Collection Hippocratique (Genève: Librairie Droz, 1983), 181–85Google Scholar; Schironi, F., ‘Naming the Phenomena: Technical Lexicon in Descriptive and Deductive Sciences’, in Willi, A. (ed.), Formes et fonctions des langues littéraires en Grèce ancienne: neuf exposés suivis de discussions (Genève: Fondation Hardt, 2019), 227–78Google Scholar.

15 Bertier, J., Mnésithée et Dieuchès, (Leiden: Brill, 1972), 110 10.1163/9789004320406CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Fr. 17 Bertier. Text from Bertier, ibid.

17 In fact, the multivalency of the term koilia is striking even relative to the otherwise chaotic anatomical jargon of Greco-Roman medicine. Consider the following remark by the first-century CE lexicographer Erotian (Erot.Κ.35, 52 Nachmanson = 86 Klein) regarding its use in the Hippocratic Corpus: ‘[T]he whole space beneath the diaphragm, and sometimes also [the space of] the thorax. The stomach. The cavity of wounds’. Text from Nachmanson, E., Erotiani vocum Hippocraticarum collectio cum fragmentis (Upsala: Appelbergs Boktryckeri, 1913)Google Scholar. See also the definition of the same term in Kühn, J.-H. and Fleischer, U., Index Hippocraticus (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1986)Google Scholar, s.v. koiliē.: ‘a cavity in the body […] the belly and its parts, the thorax, the stomach, the womb’.

18 As with Diocles and Aristotle, here as well, Bertier, op. cit. (note 15), 173, translates katō koilia simply as ‘cavity’ (cavité) omitting the reference to a specifically lower cavity.

19 Louis, P., ‘Observations sur le vocabulaire technique d’Aristote’, in Mélanges de philosophie grecque: offerts à Mgr. Diès par ses élèves, ses collègues, ses amis (Paris: Vrin, 1956), 141–49Google Scholar; Lloyd, op. cit. (note 14), 154–57; Fögen, T., Wissen, Kommunikation und Selbstdarstellung: zur Struktur und Charakteristik römischer Fachtexte der frühen Kaiserzeit, Zetemata (München: C. H. Beck, 2014), 50 Google Scholar.

20 I thank an anonymous reviewer for emphasising the importance of choice among various available animal models.

21 Lloyd, G.E.R., ‘Alcmaeon and the Early History of Dissection’, Sudhoffs Archiv, 59, 2 (1975), 113–47Google ScholarPubMed; Bubb, C., Dissection in Classical Antiquity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022), 2537, 181–9310.1017/9781009159494CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Carbone, A.L., ‘Anatomies of Aristotle’s Anatomai’, Anthropozoologica, 58, 11 (2023), 107–1410.5252/anthropozoologica2023v58a11CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Diocles is also attested to have written books on human anatomy, see van der Eijk, op. cit. (note 10), xxvi–xxvii. In the subsequent lines of the fragment from which T4 is taken, Mnesitheus mentions that it is possible to observe (estin orān) the proportions between cavities and intestines in different bodies, possibly alluding to some form of dissection research.

22 On which, see van der Eijk, P.J., ‘Between the Hippocratics and the Alexandrians: Medicine, Philosophy and Science in the Fourth Century BCE ’, in Sharples, R.W. (ed.), Philosophy and the Sciences in Antiquity (London: Routledge, 2005), 91102 Google Scholar.

23 This shift in anatomical practice has significant implications for our analysis of these texts. Since our sources consciously attempt to provide precise anatomical descriptions grounded in dissection evidence, whether firsthand or reported, we can reasonably compare their accounts with contemporary anatomical knowledge, since the ancient authors themselves aimed at an accurate description of the anatomical realia. Such comparison, undertaken with appropriate methodological caution and cultural-historical contextualization, allows us to better understand their descriptions by assuming they were examining fundamentally similar objects – dissected animal or human bodies – albeit in markedly different contexts. Though this comparative approach is just one possible method for analysing ancient anatomical texts, it has recently yielded valuable insights, see for example, Bubb, C., ‘Ancient Conceptions of the Human Uterus: Italic Votives and Animal Wombs’, Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, 79, 2 (2023), 101–1410.1093/jhmas/jrad038CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Arroyave, E. Marroquín and Vespa, M., ‘Aristotle on the Anatomy of the Heart and Lungs (HA 1.17): New Insights from a Multidisciplinary Approach’, Anthropozoologica, 58, 13 (2023), 131–43Google Scholar; Pelavski, A., Marroquin-Arroyave, E., Milgram, J., and Lewis, O.. ‘Dissection Revisited: Deciphering Bodies and Ancient Medical Texts’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 121, 50 (2024) e2416336121 10.1073/pnas.2416336121CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this methodological point.

24 Hist. An. 1.15, 494b21–4.

25 See also Hist. An. 2.17, 507b18–25; Part. An. 3.14, 675a24–30.

26 Hist. An. 1.16, 495b27–9.

27 Singh, B., Dyce, Sack, and Wensing’s Textbook of Veterinary Anatomy (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2016), 680–83Google Scholar.

28 While the notion that digestion occurs through heat-induced cooking appears in some earlier texts like the Hippocratic Fleshes and Regimen, the fourth century BCE stands out for two reasons. First, such thermal theories achieved a practical monopoly in bio-medical thought during this period. Unlike earlier writers who employed multiple explanatory models, the authors examined here appear to unanimously accept heat as the primary digestion mechanism. Second and relatedly, these ideas of heat-induced cooking underwent rigorous conceptualisation and theoretical development, exemplified by Aristotle’s introduction of the notion of bodily residues (see note 33 and 35 below for bibliography). I thank an anonymous reviewer for this point.

29 Joly, R., Le Niveau de la science hippocratique (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1966), 7580 Google Scholar. See also Demont, P., ‘La terre, le ventre, les vases et l’image du filtre. Remarques sur le chapitre 11 du traité hippocratique de Humoribus’, in Ugo, C. and , M. Riccardo (eds), Synodia. Studia humanitatis Antonio Garzya septuagenario ab amicis atque discipilis dicata (Napoli: M. D’Auria, 1998), 255–64Google Scholar. See also Draycott, J., ‘Roma-Etruscan Materials’, in Thumiger, C (ed.), Comparative Guts: Exploring the Inside of the Body through Time and Space (Kiel: CAU Kiel Exzellenzcluster ROOTS), 133–36Google Scholar; C. Thumiger, ‘Greco-Roman Medical Cultures’, in ibid., 145–50.

30 Hum. 11 (170.5–8 Overwien = V.492 L.), in Overwien, O., Hippocratis De humoribus (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2014)10.1524/9783110362442CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Hippocrates, Morb. 4, 32–37 (84–89 Joly = 7.542–554 L.), in Joly, R., Hippocrate. Tome XI, De la génération - De la nature de l’enfant- Des maladies IV.- Du foetus de huit mois (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1970)Google Scholar. See also Lonie, I.M., The Hippocratic Treatises ‘On Generation’, ‘On the Nature of the Child’, ‘Diseases IV’: A Commentary (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1981), 260–66Google Scholar; Webster, C., ‘Hippocrates’ Diseases 4 and the Technological Body’, in Kazantzidis, G. and Gerolemou, M. (eds), Body and Machine in Classical Antiquity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2023), 155–7810.1017/9781009085786.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 R. Joly, ibid., 27.

33 See Bartoš, H., ‘Aristotle and His Medical Precursors on Digestion and Nutrition’, in Korobili, G. and Presti, R. Lo (eds), Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2021), 127–52Google Scholar; Ezrokhi, D., ‘When Teleology Fails: Aristotle on Bile as a Useless Residue’, Scripta Classica Israelica 42 (2023), 111129 Google Scholar. For Diocles and Mnesitheus see note 38 below.

34 Mete. 4.3, 381a6–8.

35 Gen. An. 1.18, 724b26–27. See Peck, A.L., Aritotle: Generation of Animals (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), lxvii Google Scholar; Thivel, A., ‘La Doctrine des perissomata et ses parallèles hippocratiques’, Revue de philologie, de littérature et d’histoire anciennes, 39 (1965): 266–82Google Scholar.

36 Diocles, fr. 182,49 van der Eijk; Mnesitheus, fr. 38,32–35 Bertier.

37 Part. An. 3.14, 674a14–19; see also Gen. An .2.4, 737b27–38a8.

38 Gen. An. 2.4, 739a2–41a4.

39 On the ‘guts’ as a unitary continuum of tissues in Greco-Roman thought, whose parts are only inchoately and tentatively distinguished, see C. Thumiger, op. cit. (note 3), 26, 31. Although I emphasise here the importance of theory in shaping anatomical ideas, I nonetheless take anatomical realia to be somewhat recalcitrant to physiological and poetic imagination—that is, the anatomical ‘fact’, the way the body looks and is sensed, has some independent influence on how it is conceived and cannot be completely overridden by more abstract theoretical concerns. While physiological and theoretical notions certainly shaped how anatomy was viewed and described, anatomical observations themselves exerted an influence that cannot be reduced to non-anatomical considerations. In our case, there is, in fact, an anatomical basis for understanding some gastrointestinal tracts as having two cavities. See also note 23. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing me on this point.

40 Longrigg, J., ‘Anatomy in Alexandria in the Third Century B.C.’, The British Journal for the History of Science, 21, 4 (1988), 455–8810.1017/S000708740002536XCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Staden, H., ‘Discovering the Body: Human Dissection and Its Cultural Contexts in Ancient Greece’, Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine, 65, 3 (1992), 223–41Google Scholar.

41 Duodenum: fr. 96–98 von Staden, in von Staden, H., Herophilus. The Art of Medicine in Early Alexandria (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar; Jejunum: fr. 289 Garofalo, in Garofalo, I., Erasistrati Fragmenta (Pisa: Giardini, 1988)Google Scholar. On nēstis in Aristotle not being an anatomical structure, see D. Ezrokhi, op. cit. (note 6).

42 Ruf. Onom. 170 (157 Daremberg-Ruelle); Ruf.[?] Anat. 45 (180 Daremberg-Ruelle), in Ch. Daremberg and E. Ruelle, Oeuvres de Rufus d’Ephèse (Paris: Imprimerie Nationale, 1879); Gal. Us. Part. 4.18 (1.245 Helmreich = 3.333 K.); 5.3 (1.253–254 Helmreich = 3.345–347 K.), in G. Helmreich, Galeni De usu partium libri XVII, Vol. 1 (Leipzig: Teubner, 1907); PHP. 8.1 (486–88 De Lacy = 5.658–659 K.), in Ph. De Lacy, Galeni De Placitis Hippocratis et Platonis, Vol 2. (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1980); Ven. Ar. Diss. 23 (80–1 Garofalo = 2.784 K.), in Debru, A. and Garofalo, I., Galien. Tome VIII : L’Anatomie des nerfs. L’Anatomie des veines et des artères (Paris: Belles Lettres, 2008)Google Scholar; Loc. Aff. 6.2 (380–1 Brunschön = 8.386 K.), in C.W. Brunschön, Galeni De locis affectis V–VI (Berlin: Gruyter, 2022).

43 Gal. Us. Part. 4.8 (1.245 Helmreich = 3.333 K.), in Helmreich, op. cit. (note 41). Galen describes the caecum as the only part of the intestine not tied by the mesentery to its place. It is thus free to expand and descend, signalling an additional distinction between it and the other parts of the intestines, which might have helped create the impression that it is a somewhat independent cavity, more akin to the stomach. See In. Hipp. Epid. 6.4.3 (192 Pfaff = 17b.125 K.), in Pfaff, F., Galeni In Hippocratis Epidemiarum librum I commentaria III, In Hippocratis Epidemiarum librum II commentaria V (Berlin: Gruyter, 1935)Google Scholar.

44 Confusingly enough, therefore, what Aristotle dubs the colon is in Galen’s terminology the caecum or the blind intestine.

45 On Galen’s teleology, see R.J. Hankinson, ‘Galen and the Best of All Possible Worlds’, The Classical Quarterly, 39, 1 (May 1989), 206–27; M.J. Schiefsky, ‘Galen’s Teleology and Functional Explanation’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 33 (2007), 369–400. For his physiology of digestion, see O. Lewis, ‘The Mechanics of Galen’s Theory of Nutrition’, in Gerolemou and Kazantzidis op. cit. (note 31), 262–95; D. Ezrokhi and O. Lewis, ‘Galen’s Typology of Organs’, Apeiron 58, 2 (2025), 109–133.

46 See, e.g. about Herophilus’s anatomy of the liver in von Staden, op. cit. (note 40), 163; C. Bubb, op. cit. (note 21), 38–39. On Galen’s zoocentric anatomy of the brain in J. Rocca, op. cit. (note 1), 202–8.

47 For recent discussions of the possibility of Galen dissecting humans, see Dean-Jones, L., ‘Galen and the Culture of Dissection’, in Bell, S.W. and Holland, L.L. (eds), At the Crossroads of Greco-Roman History, Culture, and Religion. Papers in Memory of Carin M. C. Green (Oxford: Archaeopress, 2018), 229–4810.2307/j.ctv1228gbp.23CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bubb, ibid., 110–20.

48 Gal. Anat. Admin. 3.5 (1.167 Garofalo = 2.375 K.); .4.2 (1.215 Garofalo = 2.422–3 K.), in I. Garofalo, Galeni anatomicarum administrationum libri qui supersunt novem, Vol. 1 (Leiden: Brill, 1986). See Garofalo, I., ‘The Six Classes of Animals in Galen’, in López-Férez, J.A. (ed.), Galeno: Obra, pensamiento e influencia (Coloquio internacional celebrado en Madrid, 22-25 de Marzo de 1988) (Madrid: UNED, 1991), 83–7Google Scholar.

49 Vespa, M., Geloion mimēma. Studi sulla rappresentazione culturale della scimmia nei testi greci e greco-romani (Turnhout: Brepols, 2021), 95120 10.1484/M.ASH-EB.5.124755CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Chivers, D.J. and Hladik, C.M., ‘Morphology of the Gastrointestinal Tract in Primates: Comparisons with Other Mammals in Relation to Diet’, Journal of Morphology, 166, 3 (1980), 347 10.1002/jmor.1051660306CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

51 See, for example, in the Latin tradition, the anatomical excursus in Agnellus of Ravenna, In. Gal. Sect. 29, 132,13–136,20 Westerink, in Westerink, L. G., Agnellus of Ravenna: Lectures on Galen’s De sectis (Buffalo, NY: State University of New York at Buffalo, 1981)Google Scholar. For a classical study of Galenism as a medical tradition, see Temkin, O., Galenism, Rise and Decline of a Medical Philosophy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973)Google Scholar.

52 The literature on the topic is vast, see, for example, French, R.K., Dissection and Vivisection in the European Renaissance (Brookfield: Ashgate, 1999)Google Scholar; Shotwell, R.A., ‘The Revival of Vivisection in the Sixteenth Century’, Journal of the History of Biology, 46 (2013), 171–9710.1007/s10739-012-9326-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nutton, V.. Renaissance Medicine (London: Routledge, 2022)10.4324/9781003223184CrossRefGoogle Scholar, esp. Ch 9.

53 May, M.T., Galen and the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1968), 241 Google Scholar, note 97.

54 Massa, N., Liber introductorius anatomiae siue dissectionis corporis humani (Venice: Franciscus Bindonus and Mapheus Pasinus, 1536), 21 Google Scholar.

55 On the role of Greco-Roman medicine in Early Modern anatomy and physiology, see Siraisi, N., ‘Anatomizing the Past: Physicians and History in Renaissance Culture’, Renaissance Quarterly, 53, 1 (2000): 130 10.2307/2901531CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Nutton, V., ‘The Diffusion of Ancient Medicine in the Renaissance’, Medicina nei secoli, 14, 2 (2002), 461–78Google ScholarPubMed; Presti, R. Lo, ‘Anatomy as Epistemology: The Body of Man and the Body of Medicine in Vesalius and his Ancient Sources (Celsus, Galen)’, Renaissance and Reformation, 33, 3 (2010): 2760 10.33137/rr.v33i3.15351CrossRefGoogle Scholar; V. Nutton, op. cit. (note 52), Ch 4.

56 On Vesalius’ relationship with Galen’s anatomical ideas, see Nutton, V., ‘More Vesalian Second Thoughts. The Annotations to the Institutiones Anatomicae Secundum Galeni Sententiam, 1538’, Gesnerus, 72, 1 (2015), 94116 10.1163/22977953-07201006CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nutton, V., ‘1538, A Year of Vesalian Innovation’, Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies, 48, 1 (2018), 4159 10.1215/10829636-4280846CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Vesalius, A., De humani corporis fabricata libri septem (Basle: J. Oporinus, 1543), 500 Google Scholar.

58 See the discussion in Garrison, D.H. and Hast, Malcolm H., The Fabric of the Human Body: An Annotated Translation of the 1543 and 1555 Editions of ‘De Humani Corporis Fabrica Libri Septem’ (Karger: Basel, 2014), 1010 Google Scholar, note 28.

59 Falloppio, G., Observationes anatomicae. Ad Petrum Mannam, medicum cremonensem (Venice: Marco Antonio Ulmo et Gratioso Perchachino, 1562), 105rGoogle Scholar.

60 Valverde, J., Historia de la composicion del cuerpo humano (Roma: Antonio Salamanca et Antonio Lafrerij, 1560)Google Scholar, 62v.

61 For Renaissance and early modern Galenic physiology, see E. Moreau, ‘From Food to Elements and Humors: Digestion in Late Renaissance Galenism’, in Korobili and Lo Presti, op. cit. (note 32), 319–38.

62 On Vesalius’s debt to Galen’s teleological thinking, see Sirasi, N., ‘Vesalius and the Reading of Galen’s Teleology’, Renaissance Quarterly 50, 1 (1997), 137 10.2307/3039327CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63 Vesalius, op. cit. (note 56), 503.

64 See Gal. Nat. Fac. 2.9, 199 Helmreich = 2.135 K., in Helmreich, G., Claudii Galeni Pergameni Scripta minora, Bd. III (Leipzig: Teubner, 1893)Google Scholar, where Galen relates the fermentation of wine to the agency of its innate heat.

65 Clericuzio, A., ‘Chemical and Mechanical Theories of Digestion in Early Modern Medicine’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 2 (2012), 329–3710.1016/j.shpsc.2011.10.025CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Banchetti-Robino, M. P., ‘Van Helmont’s Hybrid Ontology and Its Influence on the Chemical Interpretation of Spirit and Ferment’, Foundations of Chemistry, 18, 2 (2016), 103–1210.1007/s10698-015-9243-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar; Williams, E. A., ‘Digestion in Early Modern Science and Medicine’, in Jalobeanu, D. and Wolfe, (eds), Encyclopedia of Early Modern Philosophy and the Sciences (Cham: Springer, 2022), 460–6510.1007/978-3-319-31069-5_276CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 For general discussions of Glisson’s life and philosophy, see Giglioni, G., ‘Francis Glisson’s Notion of “Confœderatio Naturæ” in the Context of Hylozoistic Corpuscularianism’, Revue d’histoire des sciences, 55, 2 (2002), 239–6210.3406/rhs.2002.2151CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hartbecke, K., Metaphysik und Naturphilosophie im 17. Jahrhundert: Francis Glissons Substanztheorie in ihrem ideengeschichtlichen Kontext (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 2006)10.1515/9783110909258CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rey, A.-L., ‘Anatomie du corps et de l’esprit chez Francis Glisson’, Gesnerus, 71, 2 (November 11, 2014), 308–2110.1163/22977953-07102008CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

67 d’Acquapendente, F.H., De gula, ventriculo, intestinis tractatus (Padua: Lorenzo Pasquato, 1618), 149rGoogle Scholar.

68 Glisson, F., Tractatus de ventriculo et intestinis. cui praemittitur alius, de partibus continentibus in genere; & in specie, de iis Abdominis (Amsterdam: Jansson-Waesberge, 1677), 212–15Google Scholar. Glisson argues that even the small human caecum has a function in preventing the reflux of faeces back into the small intestines due to the peristaltic motion of the large intestine that pushes residues forward and backwards at the same time. The small pouch of the caecum houses the faeces pushed backwards and thus allows them to stay in the large intestine.

69 A reviewer rightly observed that the language of metaphors, or rather constant analogies to the first, ‘real’ cavity of the stomach, abounds in descriptions of the lower cavity; it is always ‘like’ (oion, tanquam) the stomach. This might be a way to flag its problematic status, as one does not find analogies in the opposite direction—since the stomach is very evidently ‘there’, there is no need to liken it or derive its function from other organs.

70 I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising the animal-human dynamics as constitutive for the biography of this anatomical idea.

71 Chang, H., ‘The Persistence of Epistemic Objects Through Scientific Change’, Erkenntnis, 75, 3 (2011): 426 10.1007/s10670-011-9340-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72 Heavy and light, see Lloyd, G.E.R., The Revolutions of Wisdom: Studies in the Claims and Practice of Ancient Greek Science (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1989), 191–98Google Scholar. Temperature: Chang, H., Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar. On additional criteria that promote the longevity of primarily medical ideas, see Thumiger, C., Phrenitis and the Pathology of the Mind in Western Medical Thought (Fifth Century BCE to Twentieth Century CE) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2023), 367–910.1017/9781009241311CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

Figure 0

Figure 1. A schematic representation of the gastrointestinal tract according to Aristotle’s History of Animals.

Figure 1

Figure 2. A schematic representation of the gastrointestinal tract according to Aristotle’s Parts of Animals.

Figure 2

Table 1. Fourth-century BCE terms for gastrointestinal anatomy

Figure 3

Figure 3. Left: Porcine large intestine, view from above. C = The first bulky part of the large intestine, which was identified as the lower cavity (katō koilia), the colon (to kolon), or the blind intestine (to tuphlon enteron) in the examined authors. D = the part identified by Aristotle as ‘the spiral’ (hē hēlix). Right: Porcine large intestine, side view. Adapted with permission from Singh, op. cit. (note 27), Fig. 34.12.B, D.

Figure 4

Figure 4. A schematic description of the gastrointestinal tract according to Galen.