Hostname: page-component-cb9f654ff-k7rjm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-08-23T01:24:44.075Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Between images and concepts: Pherecydes of Syros and figuration in Archaic Greek thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 August 2025

Mikolaj Domaradzki*
Affiliation:
Adam Mickiewicz University, Poznan
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article critically examines the frequent claim that Pherecydes of Syros deliberately composed his treatise to be read figuratively. More specifically, it is argued that mythopoeic images from the sixth century BCE ought to be distinguished from Classical and Hellenistic allegories lest later categories and distinctions be anachronistically projected onto an archaic thinker. Since this study shows how mythopoeic images are used to fill conceptual gaps in abstract discourse, and how philosophical vocabulary arises in the process of metaphorization, its findings might have implications beyond the context of Pherecydes’ contribution to the development of the allegorical tradition.

Information

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

I. Introduction

The sixth-century writer Pherecydes of Syros (fl. ca. 544 BCE) has been repeatedly hailed as the founder of the allegorical tradition.Footnote 1 Thus, he is often credited as being (one of) the first to have allegorically interpreted the ancient poets and/or to have allegorically expressed his original views.

The former honour will not concern us here. While quite a few scholars have suggested that Pherecydes practised allegoresis of Homer,Footnote 2 the only testimony regarding this matter does not ascribe to him any reading of the poet that could be categorized as allegorical: Origen makes it clear (C. Cels. 6.42 = DK 7 B5) that Celsus interpreted the binding of Hera (Il. 15.18–24) and the expulsion of Hephaestus (Il. 1.590–91) as elaborate allegories of the ordering of matter and the chastising of daimones,Footnote 3 but his direct quotation from Pherecydes contains no huponoia (cf. S F83 and LM 4 D13/R27a).Footnote 4 Obviously, we cannot rule out the possibility that Pherecydes put forward allegorical interpretations of Homer and/or Hesiod in the lost parts of his book, but as things stand not much more can be said on the topic of his allegoresis of poetry.Footnote 5 Hence, the focus of the present paper will be on the issue of the Pherecydean allegory (that is, the mode of speaking rather than reading).

The authors of Late Antiquity regularly labelled Pherecydes ‘enigmatic’.Footnote 6 Isidore in Clement of Alexandria captures this common conviction nicely when he asserts that Pherecydes ‘theologized allegorically’ (ἀλληγορήσας ἐθϵολόγησϵν, Strom. 6.6.53.5 = DK 7 B2 = S F76 = LM 4 R28), and Origen similarly counts Pherecydes among those who intentionally composed their works to be ‘interpreted figuratively and allegorically’ (τροπολογῆσαι καὶ ἀλληγορῆσαι, C. Cels. 1.18).Footnote 7 Undoubtedly, it is such ancient assessments that have made numerous modern scholars view various Pherecydean images as carefully crafted allegories.Footnote 8 Laudably, there are scholars who refrain from characterizing Pherecydes’ images as ‘allegorical’ but, less felicitously, opt for other equally anachronistic terms. In his ground-breaking study, Hermann S. Schibli, for instance, deliberately abstains from employing the term ‘allegory’,Footnote 9 though occasionally using ‘metaphor’,Footnote 10 whereas other scholars choose to speak of the Pherecydean ‘symbols’.Footnote 11

Of course, all these scholars who attribute an allegorical (metaphorical, symbolical) mode of thought to Pherecydes do not mean exactly the same thing. While the highly nebulous concepts of allegory, metaphor and symbol have been understood very differently, this paper will suggest that none of them does justice to the specificity of the Pherecydean images. First, it is advisable to note what the three concepts have in common. Most generally, metaphor, symbol and allegory represent one thing in terms of something else, which is why they are frequently taken to shade into one another along the continuum of figurative modes of thought.Footnote 12 Secondly, they are usually assumed to be the product of the author’s uoluntas, that is, they are viewed as intended by the speaker to convey the other meaning.Footnote 13 Thirdly and most importantly, theoretical considerations of metaphor, allegory and symbol are much later than Pherecydes, since they presuppose an awareness of the figurative that Pherecydes did not yet have. Let us briefly clarify the issue.

Aristotle famously defines metaphor as the ‘application of a foreign name’ (ὀνόματος ἀλλοτρίου ἐπιφορά, Poet. 1457b6–7) and explains the trope as a development from ‘simile’ or ‘likeness’ (ϵἰκών, Rhet. 3, 1406b20–24).Footnote 14 Crucially, though, his account of metaphor as a transfer of meaning arising from the comparison between two things is only a later rational explanation of what earlier consciousness perceived as equivalence: at the time of Pherecydes, ‘he is a lion’ used with reference to a man signified that the warrior assumed the nature of this animal.Footnote 15 Thus, while the Aristotelian view of metaphor points to two distinct, easily identifiable fields between which the semantic transfer occurs, there is no awareness of such a contrast in Pherecydes. It is, then, anachronistic and retrospective to apply the term ‘metaphor’ to his images, for Pherecydes operates neither with the distinction between a ‘proper’ (literal) and an ‘alien’ (figurative) use of a word, nor with the concept of simile as an expanded form of metaphor (in which the postulated likeness is signalled explicitly). The same applies to the other two terms. ‘Allegory’ first appears in the Hellenistic period and is regularly defined in quantitative terms as an extended or sustained metaphor (for example, Cic. Orat. 94 or Quint. Inst. 9.2.46).Footnote 16 ‘Symbol’, on the other hand, is not primarily linguistic, has the longest attested history and therefore emerges as the most polysemous of the three concepts, but one should stress that it is also only in the Hellenistic period that Chrysippus employs sumbolon with reference to the hidden meaning of Hesiod’s narrative about Athena’s birth from the head of Zeus (SVF 2.908–09).Footnote 17 While after the Stoics sumbolon and allēgoria are repeatedly used synonymously in various interpretive contexts (for example, Heraclitus the Allegorist, Quaestiones homericae 24), it is, again, anachronistic and retrospective to characterize Pherecydes’ images as ‘allegorical’ or ‘symbolical’ for, to reiterate, this sixth-century BCE thinker did not consciously differentiate between the literal and figurative senses of his semantic inventions.

Accordingly, the aim of the present paper will be to question the frequent claim that Pherecydes deliberately composed his treatise to be read figuratively. It will be argued that mythopoeic images from the sixth century BCE ought to be distinguished from Classical and Hellenistic allegories lest the idiosyncrasies of archaic thought be entirely obliterated.Footnote 18 After all, if an Archaic-period account is classified as ‘allegorical’ or ‘symbolic’, how are we to categorize later figurative accounts? Just as we clearly differentiate Pherecydes’ nascent philosophical reflection from Plato’s full-blown philosophia, so we should distinguish the former’s mythopoeic images from the latter’s carefully constructed eikones employed in the service of his self-conscious muthopoiia.Footnote 19 This should be fairly uncontroversial, but let us quote here two recent studies on the development of allegory. Dirk Obbink stresses that in the early period we do not find allegory as a ‘self-conscious or distinct literary procedure’,Footnote 20 and Glenn Most similarly emphasizes that until the Hellenistic age the technique is ‘philosophically marginal’.Footnote 21 Thus, in what follows, it will be suggested that the Pherecydean ‘enigmacity’ ought to be distinguished from later allegories.

Crucially, this was already sensed by Proclus, who, in his discussion of the Atlantis story, acutely diagnoses that ‘Plato’s teaching is not enigmatic in the same way as Pherecydes’ is’ (ἡ Πλάτωνος παράδοσις οὐκ ἔστι τοιαύτη αἰνιγματώδης οἵα ἡ Φϵρϵκύδου, In Ti. 1.129.15–16 = DK 7 A12 = S F89 = LM 4 R19).Footnote 22 While the point here is that the Platonic doctrines do not require the great deal of hermeneutical deciphering necessary in the case of the Pherecydean riddles, this appraisal can be taken as a useful point of departure for probing the difference between the enigmatic images of Pherecydes and later figurative concepts. As will be discussed, Plato’s use of metaphors is quite explicit and regularly yields an allegory in the Hellenistic sense (see above). In Pherecydes, by contrast, mythopoeic images enter philosophical discourse as abstract concepts but their figurativeness is not yet overt: one could say that the Pherecydean images hint at the emergent figurative meaning (‘embroidery = demiurgy’), but at the same time one should not ascribe to Pherecydes the same awareness of the figurative that Classical and Hellenistic philosophers display, in order to avoid anachronistically projecting later categories and distinctions onto an Archaic-period thinker. Let us briefly consider one such distortion.

When comparing Pherecydes’ cosmology with modern Big Bang theories, Michael Chase proposes that ‘Pherecydes didn’t mean his mythical accounts to be taken literally’, since ‘They were, in all likelihood, intended, not as allegories but as symbols.’Footnote 23 Although from our contemporary perspective it may seem natural to thus differentiate between allegory and symbol, this modern distinction was completely alien to the ancient Greeks. This aesthetic opposition was only created by the Romantics, who championed the superiority of symbol over allegory.Footnote 24 Yet no ancient thinker ever attempted to distinguish systematically between allegory and symbol, let alone oppose them. Consequently, when one embraces the Romantic contrast between symbol and allegory, and retrospectively interprets archaic texts through the prism of this modern dichotomy, one risks doing violence to the thought one strives to reconstruct. Of course, no one can impugn the advantages of reading archaic authors in such a manner that some light is shed not only on their works but also on various contemporary issues. At the same time, however, one should be extremely cautious about explicating archaic cultures in modern terms, for imposing modern concepts onto archaic views frequently results in moulding the object of interpretation in accordance with some preconceived picture of it. Indeed, Chase’s use of the Romantic distinction between symbols and allegories in his discussion of Pherecydes shows that when modern categories are applied to analysing an archaic thinker, the latter may easily end up crammed into the self-imposed confines of a foreign framework. After all, the Romantic denouncement of allegory was a reaction to the Medieval and Renaissance traditions of allegory as a primarily religious mode: in light of the Enlightenment’s challenge to the authority of theology, the Romantics elevated symbol to the position of an attractive alternative to the religious orthodoxy associated with allegory. Hence, when one suggests that Pherecydes intended his mythical accounts as symbols rather than allegories, one assumes that he not only consciously distinguished between the various modes of the figurative (favouring symbol over allegory), but also that he was critical of the theological tradition (much in the spirit of secular modernism). As neither is the case, this paper will approach Pherecydes from a different perspective.

II. Methodological framework

The archaic thought of Pherecydes will be read here through the lens of the framework developed by the eminent classicist and theoretician Olga Freidenberg (1890–1955), whose work has only recently been disseminated to the English-speaking scholarly community,Footnote 25 and fruitfully applied to the study of Pindar’s poetry.Footnote 26 Thus, this paper will suggest that Freidenberg’s insights into the complex process of metaphorization can cast interesting light on the unique and innovative ways in which Pherecydes makes use of traditional mythology, and on his contribution to the emergence of the allegorical tradition. This will also make it possible to avoid the unfortunate ‘developmentalism’ which evaluates the Pherecydean images from the standpoint of the progress from the ‘non-philosophical’ muthos to the ‘philosophical’ logos.Footnote 27

More specifically, Pherecydes’ mythopoeic images will be shown to illustrate how philosophical vocabulary arises in the process of metaphorization, that is, at a stage ‘when the image takes on the function of a concept for the first time’.Footnote 28 This highly compressed statement requires some unpacking. The term ‘image’ refers here to the basic understanding of the world which does not allow any reflection on the abstract or figurative, since it is unable to make sophisticated generalizations and conscious transfers from one genus or species to another. Freidenberg characterizes this early way of perceiving the world as ‘concrete sense-thinking’ and associates its mode with what later Greeks called to aisthēton or to horaton.Footnote 29 The term ‘concept’, by contrast, refers to the more abstract and refined way of grasping reality that is capable of making analytical distinctions between the particular or literal, on the one hand, and the general or metaphorical, on the other. This ‘conceptual thinking’ has overcome the sensual concreteness of the image and its mode is associated with what later Greeks called to noēton.Footnote 30 Finally, a mythopoeic image is a middle stage between the imagistic and the conceptual, since the concrete and the abstract coexist here.Footnote 31 Crucially, this stage is still marked by an incapacity to distinguish consciously between the ‘old’ (concrete, particular, literal) and ‘new’ (abstract, general, figurative) forms. To take one of Freidenberg’s examples, the concrete image of ‘throes of childbirth’ (ὠδῖνϵς) is gradually employed to indicate ‘suffering’ and ‘anguish’ in a more abstract sense: thus, for instance, the ‘bitter pangs’ in Homer (Il. 11.271) can become ‘bitter pain’ in Sophocles (Trach. 41–42). This illustrates how an image from daily life is transformed into a more abstract concept, while retaining its concreteness.Footnote 32 Hence, metaphorization is a process in which concrete meanings increasingly take on figurative meanings, albeit the resulting mythopoeic images do not yet become what only later will be referred to as metaphors, allegories, symbols, etc.

As English-speaking scholars are less familiar with Freidenberg’s framework, it may be helpful to point out here that Geoffrey Lloyd has made highly comparable observations in his discussion of the emergence of the concept of metaphor. He likewise stresses that the use of what would later be recognized as figurative expressions predates the development of the nomenclature to label them as such, which is why he introduces the concept of ‘semantic stretch’ to bypass the need to choose between ‘literal’ and ‘metaphorical’ applications of terms by ancient authors.Footnote 33 Similarly to Freidenberg’s framework, Lloyd’s concept is useful for historians because it allows us to approach cautiously the delicate problem of how sixth-century BCE thinkers viewed their descriptions and how explicitly they recognized issues related to the meanings of the terms they employed. Since Pherecydes operated before the literal/figurative dichotomy was available, the concept of semantic stretch offers an enticing alternative to these anachronistic and retrospective interpretations which all too hastily classify the Pherecydean images as ‘allegorical’, ‘symbolical’ or ‘metaphorical’.

Freidenberg focuses primarily on the origins of Greek lyric, but Pherecydes’ account, which straddles mythical and philosophical thought, similarly shows how mythopoeic images are used to fill conceptual gaps in abstract discourse.Footnote 34 In the process, there are as yet no clearly discernible figurative meanings, let alone elaborate allegories. The gaps are spanned spontaneously, as Pherecydes operates before (Aristotelian) metaphor. Notwithstanding this, Pherecydes’ cosmology significantly contributes to the laborious transition from concrete images to more abstract and figurative concepts which are subsequently utilized in philosophical allegories.Footnote 35

III. The embroidered robe and the winged oak

It is useful to start with this part of Pherecydes’ account not only because it is most frequently cited as an example of the Pherecydean allegory,Footnote 36 but also because we are dealing here with the longest surviving excerpt from his book. As will be shown, Pherecydes’ innovative use of the images of the embroidered robe and the winged oak was conducive to the emergence of concepts that would become a staple of the later metaphysical curriculum.

According to the Grenfell-Hunt papyrus, Pherecydes presented Zas’ demiurgic activity in terms of his making a ‘robe’ (φᾶρος), ‘great and beautiful’ (μέ|γα τϵ καὶ καλόν), on which the god ‘embroiders Earth, Ogenos and the houses of Ogenos’ (π̣ο̣ι̣κ̣[ίλλϵι Γῆν | καὶ ᾿Ωγη[νὸν καὶ τὰ ᾿Ω|γηνοῦ [δώματα], 2.11 = DK 7 B2 = S F68 = LM 4 D9). While Zas and Ogenos must be conscious mutations on Pherecydes’ part, there can hardly be any doubt that they are Zeus and Oceanus, respectively. Naturally, scholars have put forward a plethora of divergent etymologies for these peculiar names.Footnote 37 Yet for the purpose of the present discussion the crucial point is that such deliberate modifications indubitably testify to Pherecydes’ desire to offer a novel account of the cosmos and to signal his departure from the traditional models. Of course, Pherecydes draws heavily on various Homeric motifs,Footnote 38 but, most importantly, his portrayal of the world as a product of a craftsman god has now been recognized as apparently the first Hellenic articulation of the view that the cosmos is a divinely designed artefact.Footnote 39

On the third day of the wedding, Zas bestows the embroidered garment upon Chthonie, which provides an aition for the first ‘festival of unveiling’ (ἀν̣[α|καλυπτήρια) established as a ‘custom’ (νόμος) for both gods and men. While Diogenes Laertius reports further that Chthonie became Ge when Zas gave her the earth as a ‘gift of honour’ (γέρας, 1.119 = DK 7 B1 = S F14 = LM 4 D5), his report is consistent with what the Grenfell papyrus relates: as he presents the goddess with the vestment, Zas says to her: ‘I honour you with this’ (τούτωι σϵ τιμ̣[έω, col. 2).Footnote 40 This means that the reception of the gift of the embroidered robe marks the bride’s transformation from an obscure, barren, subterranean structure (cf. χθόνιος) into the visible, fertile and inhabitable surface that we live on. As Chthonie is honoured with the woven cloth, she changes not only her name but also her status, since now the Earth and Oceanus become her domain of influence. Hence, the demiurgic weaving of the terrestrial garment represents the formation of the world as we know it. Zas is the cosmic artisan, whose embroidering results in the emergence of Ge and Ogenos: the former is the primal mother earth responsible for all generation and regeneration of life (who also presides over the institution of marriage), whereas the latter is the great river encircling the earth and supplying water to springs, rivers and seas. Is this an allegory?

Those who answer affirmatively to this question often rely on Clement of Alexandria, who also quotes the part of Pherecydes’ account that appears in the first column of the Grenfell papyrus (Strom. 6.2.9.4 = DK 7 B2 = S F69). Having stressed the antiquity and ubiquity of ‘the symbolical form’ (τὸ συμβολικὸν ϵἶδος, 6.2.4.2), Clement proceeds to demonstrate how the Hellenes plagiarized not just the prophets but also other Greeks (6.2.4.3–4). It is in this context that he then compares Homer’s description of Achilles’ intricately wrought shield (Il. 18.483, 607) with Pherecydes’ depiction of Ge’s splendidly embroidered robe (Strom. 6.2.9.3–4). As this motif was a commonplace in the allegorical tradition,Footnote 41 many modern scholars followed the ancient allegorists of Homer and assumed that Pherecydes intended his image to be interpreted allegorically.Footnote 42

Nevertheless, it is more accurate to view the robe woven by Zeus and given to his bride as a mythopoeic description that seeks to illustrate more abstract concepts. Thus, the concreteness of the Pherecydean images should not be rashly allegorized away.Footnote 43 It is precisely the specific image of weaving the beautiful mantle that conveys the less tangible idea that the world is a rational work: the meticulously embroidered robe implies that the earth is a purposefully arranged creation. It is not that ‘weaving’ and ‘robe’ are used here metaphorically rather than literally. Instead, the everyday, familiar uses of the terms are extended or, as Lloyd puts it, ‘stretched’ to unfamiliar applications which nonetheless retain sufficient affinity with and similarity to the familiar ones. That is how the mythopoeic image of weaving a cosmic robe can be employed in an informative and even explanatory way. Likewise, the image of donning the garment ornamented with earth and ocean accounts for the emergence of (the surface of) the earth familiar to us: as Chthonie drapes herself in the adorned vestment, she turns into Ge (i.e. our visible world rather than its hidden foundation). Hence, Chthonie wraps the robe around herself as humans do in their everyday life. That is why the cosmological dimension (the generation of the terrestrial surface) is here coalesced with the aetiological one (the establishment of the social institution of marriage). The image of the hieros gamos is invoked to clarify Chthonie’s metamorphosis into Ge and to derive the human wedding rite from the first divine nuptial ceremony (which becomes the confirming model for all anakaluptēria).

As Pherecydes employs his mythopoeic image to articulate the abstract concept of divine intentionality, he also stresses the erotic impulse driving the demiurgy. Proclus relates that Pherecydes had his Zeus transmogrify into Eros when the god was about to ‘create’ (δημιουργϵῖν, In Ti. 2.54.28–30 = DK 7 B3 = S F72 = LM 4 D8). This is confirmed by Maximus of Tyre, who likewise speaks of Eros between Zeus and Chthonie (Dissertationes 4.4.5 = DK 7 A11 = S F73 = LM 4 D3). Hence, the formation of the physical and social order is explained in terms of love and the ensuing sexual act: the world is a divinely arranged creation, whose rational design, however, originates from a passionate act of procreation. Marriage leads to consummation and Zas, accordingly, performs the demiurgic role of Eros, whom Hesiod similarly elevates to the position of a sexual, life-giving and creative power (Theog. 120–22). The abstract concept of a demiurgic force is here conveyed by a concrete character performing specific actions which require both figures to undergo substantial transformations: Zeus metamorphoses into Eros when he produces the cosmos, and Chthonie metamorphoses into Ge when the earth is arranged by divine plan.

Pherecydes’ imagistic dichotomy between Zas (the artisan) and his robe (the artefact) clearly presents the cosmos as the work of divine artistry. Yet although the image of the deity embroidering the robe harbingers the metaphysical concept of demiurgic design, one must be cautious with respect to Pherecydes’ awareness of the status of his mythopoeic image. Plato’s reservations provide an illuminating contrast. In the Timaeus, for instance, the celebrated account of the demiurge begins with a strong emphasis on the ‘impossibility’ (ἀδύνατον) of expounding the maker of the universe to everyone (28c3–5), and concludes with the telling plea that in matters regarding the gods and the generation of the universe one must make do with a ‘probable myth’ (ϵἰκὸς μῦθος, 29c4–d3).Footnote 44 Thus, the eponymous character of the dialogue states in no uncertain terms that he cannot guarantee the veracity of his account and that the best he can come up with is a likely approximation to the truth. The same self-awareness is on full display in the Politicus, where the elaborate discussion of the demiurge is repeatedly characterized as a myth (268d9, 268e4, 272d5, 274e1, 275b1), which, however, the Younger Socrates finds to be ‘very probable’ (μάλα ϵἰκότως, 270b1), and which the Eleatic Stranger initially introduces for ‘amusement’ (παιδιά, 268d8–9), but ultimately hails as ‘useful’ (χρήσιμος, 274e1–4) for identifying the errors perpetrated in the search for the statesman.Footnote 45 By contrast, Pherecydes never offers such disclaimers. His cosmology represents a stage of thinking in which there are yet no deliberate semantic transfers from genera or species but rather straightforward identifications of such things as ‘figurative’ and ‘literal’ weaving, clothing, etc. That is why the Pherecydean Zeus ‘non-metaphorically’ makes the robe of the universe, as he embroiders the exterior surface of the earth, whereas Chthonie ‘non-metaphorically’ puts the terrestrial garment on, as she becomes the earth we know. The same applies to the other image that apparently was closely related to the decorated vestment: that of the winged tree.

Maximus of Tyre only mentions a tree and a peplos (Dissertationes 4.4.5 = DK 7 A11 = S F73 = LM 4 D3), but Isidore in Clement of Alexandria specifies that the tree was a ‘winged oak’ (ὑπόπτϵρος δρῦς) with the ‘embroidered robe upon it’ (ἐπ’ αὐτῇ πϵποικιλμένον φᾶρος, Strom. 6.6.53.5 = DK 7 B2 = S F76 = LM 4 D10). As both authors report on the tree in connection with the adorned garment that turns Chthonie into Ge, the oak must have played an important and conspicuous part in Pherecydes’ description of the formation of our cosmos. Unfortunately, scholars have been unable to agree on what that role was.Footnote 46

While some only gestured at Anaximander and other early Greek thinkers,Footnote 47 Hermann Diels argued that Pherecydes crafted his image as a deliberate allegory of Anaximander’s earth: given that the latter reportedly considered the earth to be (i) ‘cylindrical in shape’ (Ps.-Plut. Strom. 2 = DK 12 A10 = LM 6 D8) and (ii) similar to a ‘stone column’ (Hippol. Haer. 1.6.3 = DK 12 A11 = LM 6 D7), Diels boldly concluded that Pherecydes ‘poured new wine into old wineskins’, that is, he expressed the new physics under the guise of old cosmology.Footnote 48 Diels’ argument was furthered by Kurt von FritzFootnote 49 and, most recently, embraced by Gerard Naddaf.Footnote 50 Nevertheless, this interpretation was vigorously contested by Geoffrey Kirk, who raised doubts as to whether hupopteros ‘is to be given an abstract connotation at all’,Footnote 51 and offered criticisms which made many scholars wary of the interpretations of Diels and von Fritz.Footnote 52 Adopting a middle position, Schibli refused to characterize Pherecydes’ winged tree as a ‘conscious allegorization of Anaximander’s cylindrical earth’,Footnote 53 but at the same time followed the German tradition (Diels, Zeller, von Fritz, Jaeger) in assuming that the fluttering wings of Pherecydes’ tree express ‘in a mythopoeic manner’ what Anaximander presented as the earth suspended in space.Footnote 54 While other scholars have come up with less convincing interpretations of the Pherecydean image of the winged oak,Footnote 55 few have astutely observed that we do not know how literally or how figuratively it was meant to be taken.Footnote 56 This may provide a useful starting point for analysing Pherecydes’ cryptic phrase.

When, for instance, Pindar promises to deliver his message ‘faster than a winged ship’ (θᾶσσον … ναὸς ὑποπτέρου, Ol. 9.24), modern scholarship is unsurprisingly divided as to whether the ‘wings’ denote here sails or oars.Footnote 57 Thus, one could also ponder which part of the Pherecydean tree was to carry the oak as wings: given the prefix hupo- one could try to make the case for the roots.Footnote 58 Yet the prime question is to what extent Pherecydes spoke figuratively of these arboreal wings. The problem is analogous to that of the Hesiodic ‘roots of the earth’. It has long been recognized that Hesiod’s rhizai (Theog. 728, Op. 19) can still be heard in Xenophanes’ errhizōsthai (Arist. Cael. 2, 294a23 = DK 21 A47 = LM 8 R13).Footnote 59 This mythopoeic image of ‘being connected’ by ‘being rooted’ is thoroughly metaphorical to a modern reader, but for these archaic thinkers and their audiences it was probably quite unmarked. Presumably, Pherecydes’ image of ‘being winged’ was no different: the world tree has wings because it glides through space or swings freely in it without any support.

Consequently, it is tantalizing to view the Pherecydean tree as an ingenious contribution to contemporary discussion of the world’s foundation, albeit (i) without insisting on Anaximander’s direct influence and (ii) without attributing to Pherecydes the intention of presenting an allegorical exposition of Anaximander’s theory. With these caveats in mind, one may cautiously juxtapose the Pherecydean image of arboreal wings with Anaximander’s well-known correction of Thales: if the latter maintained that the earth floats on water (see DK 11 A12 = LM 5 D3 or DK 11 A14 = LM 5 D7), then the former claimed it to be suspended rather than supported by anything (see DK 12 A11 = LM 6 D7 or DK 12 A26 = LM 6 D30).Footnote 60 Placed in this context, Pherecydes’ mythopoeic image of arboreal wings can be regarded as representing one of the many steps in the process of metaphorization, where individual thinkers put forward specific, concrete images whose interactions gradually yield more abstract, philosophical concepts. It is therefore not far-fetched to imagine that Pherecydes endowed his world tree with wings so that it could support itself in space: the Pherecydean oak would then be hupopteros, because our cosmos stays aloft without any underpinning substratum. This flying world tree connects the distinct levels of the Pherecydean universe (heaven and underworld), while being wrapped in the embroidered vestment with Ge and Oceanus. Zeus, to whom the oak was sacred (see Hom. Od. 14.328), hangs the robe of the universe on the tree, and Chthonie transforms into Ge when she puts on the woven garment.

IV. The timeless trinity and the battle against Ophioneus

The Pherecydean trinity is also frequently classified as ‘allegorical’.Footnote 61 However, in line with the perspective espoused here, it would be preferable to say that Pherecydes employs his mythopoeic images of ‘gods’ (θϵοί) to articulate what later philosophers will convey with the more abstract concept of ‘principles’ (ἀρχαί). That is why his deities are both personal (concrete divine figures) and impersonal (abstract divine forces).

When Aristotle famously praises Pherecydes’ account for not being entirely mythical, he commends him and other ‘mixed’ (μϵμιγμένοι) theologians (the Magi, Empedocles, Anaxagoras) for positing their first originating principles as being the ‘best’ (ἄριστον) and remaining so (Metaph. 14, 1091b8–12 = DK 7 A7 = S F81 = LM 4 R3).Footnote 62 While he places Pherecydes at the crossroads of Eastern and Greek traditions, these theologoi are lauded for not becoming entangled in interminable debates about the origin and fate of their imperishable principles, because their archai are not created, dethroned or supplanted in any way. Unfortunately, Aristotle does not specify the Pherecydean principle(s), but we know from Diogenes Laertius that at the very beginning of his tract Pherecydes established the reality of three eternal deities: Zas, Chronos and Chthonie, who, as he put it, ‘were always’ (ἦσαν ἀϵί, 1.119 = DK 7 B1 = S F14 = LM 4 D5). Thus, these primeval beings are clearly differentiated from the gods of popular belief, since the latter arose in time. It therefore emerges that in Pherecydes all three pre-existing unbegotten gods perform a function analogous to that of the later archai.Footnote 63 Indeed, this sits well with Aristotle’s emphasis on the ‘eternity’ (ἀΐδιον) of the first principle (Metaph. 14, 1091b16).Footnote 64

Pherecydes’ insistence on the perpetual existence of his divine triad is commonly recognized as a rectification of Hesiod’s Chaos, which ‘came into being’ (γένϵτ[ο], Theog. 116).Footnote 65 What is less frequently emphasized is the persistent concreteness of the Pherecydean image. Conceptually, Pherecydes does not yet have the ‘principles’ but merely Zeuses and Chronoses who have to substitute for the later archai. That is why he clothes his timeless forces in the images of particular deities, while revisiting and recasting the theogonic tradition. Consequently, the Pherecydean divinities are both specific gods and more abstract powers.Footnote 66 Pherecydes modifies the names of his deities to indicate their novel cosmological functions (connected with time, the underworld, etc.). These appellations refer to concrete divine persons who exert causal influence of particular sorts on the world and therefore can be used to explain the world. The altered names signal such philosophically important improvements as the eternity of the deities or their direct involvement in the formation of the cosmos. These improvements are not conscious allegories, but they allow us to appreciate Pherecydes as a pioneering thinker: the issues of uncreated entities that fashion the world and engage intimately in it will become a stock problem in later philosophical reflection.

Aristotle applauds Pherecydes’ eternal trinity, since his first three gods are not derived from anything that precedes them: the Pherecydean account of the origin of the world begins with that which is best (the primordial deities who have existed always) rather than something inferior (for example, the castration and removal of an evil divinity). While Aristotle’s admiration is due to the fact that Pherecydes’ trinity is not dependent on anything else, the account of the battle between Kronos and Ophioneus may seem somewhat astonishing, as it appears to be at variance with Aristotle’s praise that Pherecydes’ cosmology was not completely mythical.Footnote 67 After all, theomachies are common in mythology. Since they are also regularly interpreted allegorically by the apologists of the poets,Footnote 68 the Pherecydean battle of Kronos and Ophioneus has likewise often been assumed to have been composed allegorically.Footnote 69 As will be shown, however, Pherecydes subjects the traditional image of a theomachy to a new, but non-metaphorical use.

Again, Maximus of Tyre only mentions the birth of Ophioneus and the ensuing battle of the gods (Dissertationes 4.4.5 = DK 7 A11 = S F73 = LM 4 D3), but Celsus in Origen reports extensively that Pherecydes ‘constructed a myth’ (μυθοποιϵῖν) of two hostile armies arrayed against each other: Kronos was the ‘commander’ (ἡγϵμών) of one and Ophioneus of the other, the opposing sides had to face various ‘challenges’ (προκλήσϵις) and ‘contests’ (ἅμιλλαι), while the specific ‘terms’ (συνθῆκαι) of the battle were that those who fell into Ogenos would be vanquished and those who defeated them would possess the heavens (C. Cels. 6.42 = DK 7 B4 = S F78 = LM 4 D11). Is this an allegory?

Those who answer in the affirmative often adduce Eudemus in Damascius, who supposes that Pherecydes’ ‘five-nook’ (πϵντέμυχος) generation of gods is ‘probably’ (ἴσως) to be understood as the ‘five world’ (πϵντέκοσμος) generation (De principiis 124b = DK 7 A8 = S F60 = LM 4 R23). Accordingly, the Pherecydean ‘nooks’ (μυχοί) are equated with ‘portions’ (μοῖραι),Footnote 70 Clement’s comparison of Homer’s shield to Pherecydes’ robe (6.2.9.3–4) is invoked as a common ground (both have earth and ocean), and the battle against Ophioneus is seen as leading to the division of the world into five regions (see Hom. Il. 15.187–93). While this interpretation is also typically buttressed by Plutarch (see De def. or. 23.422E–423B and De E apud Delphos 11.389F–390A), the resulting reconstructions of the Pherecydean universe are not only highly conjectural,Footnote 71 they also build on various assumptions of the fully developed tradition of allegoresis (Plutarch, Clement, Origen, Damascius, etc.). As such, they have no textual basis.

It seems, therefore, safer to say that the Pherecydean theomachy is a mythopoeic comparison between a divine battle and a human one: the image establishes the cosmogonic war between the two mighty sovereigns as a precedent and model for all conflicts of immortals and mortals. Given that the wedding of Zas and Chthonie provides an aition for the first festival of unveiling (see above), it is tempting to assume that the battle of Kronos and Ophioneus was similarly intended to provide an aition for the first ‘wearing of a wreath’ (στϵφανηφορία). This may be surmised on the basis of the testimony provided by Tertullian, who, when discussing the origin of the crown, relates that according to Pherecydes Saturn was crowned ‘before everyone’ (ante omnes, De corona militis 7.4 = DK 7 B4 = S F82 = LM 4 D12). Thus, one may hypothesize that it was the victory over Ophioneus that earned Kronos the first wreath, upon which wearing this garland of triumph became the custom for both gods and men (as was the case with the first anakaluptēria).Footnote 72

Once again, the fighting deities are not abstract entities but concrete characters who struggle for power. Kronos is a warrior and protector, whereas Ophioneus incarnates the forces of evil which must be subdued lest the world order fall into a state of anarchy and disorder. The implication seems to be that the preservation of an orderly cosmos requires the subjugation of the forces of chaos embodied in the figure of the monstrous snake.Footnote 73 Pherecydes’ mythopoeic image is deeply rooted in the preceding tradition: his Ophioneus, for instance, is very much like the Hesiodic Typhoeus (see Theog. 821–68).Footnote 74 Yet Pherecydes also creatively reworks the conventional myths: the Pherecydean theomachy does not result in any dethronement (no god is overthrown or superseded), there is no divine succession (the three primeval deities have existed from eternity), there is a rearrangement of the Kronos–Zeus relationship (the divinities are not father and son fighting each other for power), and so on. Hence, what Pherecydes offers is a revolutionary ‘mythology cum theology’ that is conceptually richer, because it represents, as Freidenberg would say, a crucial development in the process of metaphorization.

V. Conclusion

Pherecydes was undoubtedly an exceptional thinker whose outstanding prominence is abundantly reflected in the extant testimonies. Two of these are particularly important for the closing of this discussion. Pherecydes is reported to have been the first to have written ‘about nature and gods’ (Diog. Laert. 1.116 = DK 7 A1 = S F1 = LM 4 D2), and the first to have composed a treatise ‘in prose narrative’ (Suda s.v. Φϵρϵκύδης = DK 7 A2 = S F2 = LM 4 R5a). His actual priority in both matters may be doubted.Footnote 75 Yet the ultimately insoluble question of precedence is not as relevant as is the originality with which the above testimonies credit him: what and how Pherecydes wrote about the issues that many a poet also dealt with distinguished him sufficiently to be awarded the honour of being the first prose theologian.

Of course, scholars will inevitably continue to debate the level of abstraction that Pherecydes can be credited with. This article has argued that Freidenberg’s insights into the complex process of metaphorization can throw light on the ways in which Pherecydes avails himself of traditional mythology and on his role in the development of the allegorical tradition. As has been shown, the Pherecydean images oscillate between the concrete and mythical, on the one hand, and the abstract and conceptual, on the other. Thus, these archaic forms ‘continue to remain concrete, even though their contents are already abstract’.Footnote 76 As such, they definitely pave the way for the allegorical tradition. At the same time, however, one should refrain from assigning to Pherecydes the same awareness of the figurative that the Classical and Hellenistic philosophers exhibit: his mythopoeic images ought to be differentiated from later philosophical metaphors and allegories.

Supplementary material

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit https://doi.org/10.1017/S007542692510030X

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to JHS’s editor, Lin Foxhall, and the anonymous reviewers for their useful comments, helpful suggestions and inspiring criticisms. An earlier version of this paper was presented in May 2022 at the Conference on Pherecydes of Syros held at the Universidad Panamericana in Mexico City. I would like to thank David Lévystone for his kind invitation to the event.

Footnotes

1 The following editions are used: Diels and Kranz (Reference Diels and Kranz1951–1952) (= DK); Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) (= S); Laks and Most (Reference Laks and Most2016) (= LM). The latter two contain excellent English translations on which this article frequently relies. The editions by Sturz (Reference Sturz1824) and Colli (Reference Colli1978) are only occasionally referred to. Pherecydes of Syros is sometimes conflated or equated with Pherecydes of Athens (for example, Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (Reference Wilamowitz-Moellendorff1926); Edwards (Reference Edwards1993) 65 n.3; Toye (Reference Toye1997); Munn (Reference Munn2006) 48 n.125), but the two need to be differentiated (as has been argued by Jacoby (Reference Jacoby1947); Fowler (Reference Fowler1999); and Pàmias (Reference Pàmias2005)).

2 See, especially, Tate (Reference Tate1927) 214–15, (Reference Tate1934) 107–08 and Struck (Reference Struck2004) 14–15, 26–27, 29, but also Griffiths (Reference Griffiths1967) 79 (though cf. p. 80), Svenbro (Reference Svenbro1976) 119 with n.72, Lamberton (Reference Lamberton1992) 391, Boys-Stones (Reference Boys-Stones2001) 31 with nn.7–8 and Ford (Reference Ford2002) 69 with n.6.

3 For a discussion of Celsus’ allegoresis, see Pépin (Reference Pépin1976) 450–52, who cogently argues for its Stoic origins (see SVF 2.1074; Cornutus, Graec. 26.11–27.2, 34.3–6 and Heraclitus the Allegorist, Quaestiones homericae 26–27, 40–41).

4 Moreover, Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 100 n.54 has made a strong case that Origen’s testimony reflects Celsus’ interpretation of Pherecydes’ underworld, since Celsus refers to a passage where Zeus flings gods to earth (Il. 15.21–24), whereas Pherecydes refers to a passage where gods are hurled into Tartarus (Il. 8.10–16). On Pherecydes’ non-allegorical approach to Homer here, see Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2017) 314–17 with further references.

5 The closest Pherecydes comes to allegoresis is in such etymologically based equations as Kronos is Time (DK 7 A9 = S F65–66 = LM 4 R20). That this resembles allegoresis is due to the fact that ancient etumologia brought to light the word’s ‘true’ sense (see, again, Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2017) 318–19 with further references). Yet such etymologically based identifications can be seen as approximating allegoresis if one assumes that, in naming the gods in this way, the thinker performed an interpretive act with respect to the poets. This assumption, however, is by no means obvious. On the complex relationship between allegoresis and etymology, see Most (Reference Most, Grafton and Most2016).

6 See, especially, Porph. De antr. nymph. 31 (= DK 7 B6 = S F88 = LM 4 R26) and Procl. In Ti. 1.129.15–16 (= DK 7 A12 = S F89 = LM 4 R19), but also Pherecydes’ apocryphal epistle to Thales in Diog. Laert. 1.122 (= LM 4 R31b). It is worth noting, too, that when discussing various ‘enigmatic’ utterances Clement of Alexandria (Strom. 5.8.50.2–3) likens Pherecydes’ theology to Heraclitus’ book. While this testimony does not appear in the aforementioned editions (see above n.1), Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 178 includes it in his list of addenda. However, Lamberton (Reference Lamberton1992) 392 is surely right that all such ‘additional’ testimonies ought to be incorporated into the edition of Pherecydes’ fragments.

7 Unfortunately, this testimony is also absent from the aforementioned editions (see above n.1).

8 Thus, for example, Sturz (Reference Sturz1824) 46 states this explicitly in connection with the above-quoted assertion of Isidore. For scholars who (in one way or another) classify Pherecydes’ images as ‘allegorical’, see, among many, Preller (Reference Preller1846) 386–87; Zimmermann (Reference Zimmermann1854) 167, 179, 186; Diels (Reference Diels1897) 147–48, 154–55; Zeller (Reference Zeller1919) 114; von Fritz (Reference Fritz1938) cols 2028–32; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 83–87; Buffière (Reference Buffière1956) 98 n.65; West (Reference West1963) 168–69; Pfeiffer (Reference Pfeiffer1968) 10; Svenbro (Reference Svenbro1976) 118 with n.71; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 61, 65–66 n.2, 69, 71; Lisi (Reference Lisi1985) 275 (but cf. pp. 269–70); Ford (Reference Ford2002) 69 with n.6; Kahn (Reference Kahn and Yunis2003) 144, 153; Gatzemeier (Reference Gatzemeier and Villers2005) 339, 373; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 142; Naddaf (Reference Naddaf and Wians2009) 111, 127 n.55; Sassi (Reference Sassi2009) 92, 133; and, regrettably, Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2017) 317–18 (I now wish I had been more cautious in applying such characterizations to an archaic thinker). Lamberton (Reference Lamberton1992) 391 also suggests that Pherecydes was an ‘allegorical writer’ (as well as an ‘allegorical reader’) but does not point to any particular images.

9 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) especially 56 n.12 but also 70 n.53 and 99 n.54.

10 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 25 with n.28 and 28; see also Classen (Reference Classen1962) 15 and Saudelli (Reference Saudelli2011) 88.

11 See, among others, Conrad (Reference Conrad1856) 22; Colli (Reference Colli1978) 275–77, 281; Breglia (Reference Breglia2000) 186–87; Chase (Reference Chase2013) 31 n.67, 36 and, especially, 38 with n.100.

12 Thus, for instance, Crisp (Reference Crisp2005) has argued that allegory and symbol are large-scale expressions of conceptual metaphor, as they differ only quantitatively.

13 Lausberg (Reference Lausberg1990) discusses the general importance of the concept of uoluntas for ancient hermeneutics (pp. 110–14) and its specific relevance for such concepts as metaphor (p. 288) or allegory (p. 444).

14 Unless otherwise indicated, translations are my own.

15 See, especially, Lausberg (Reference Lausberg1990) 286, but also Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg1991b) 22, 32, 34–35.

16 See further Buffière (Reference Buffière1956) 46–48; Pépin (Reference Pépin1976) 87–92; Whitman (Reference Whitman1987) 263–68; Lausberg (Reference Lausberg1990) 441–46; Blönnigen (Reference Blönnigen1992) 14–19.

17 Although this testimony does not permit the strong conclusion that Chrysippus was actually the first to have used sumbolon in that particular sense, it is, as Müri (Reference Müri and Vischer1976) 27 n.25 rightly points out, the first testimony that we have. See further Gadamer (Reference Gadamer, Weinsheimer and Marshall1989) 63; Struck (Reference Struck2004) 112, 119, 142; Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2022) 154 with n.79 (in what follows, I build on the argument presented there and use some of my earlier findings).

18 The concept of the archaic is difficult to define in an unchallengeable manner, but it is also tremendously useful when contextualizing a thinker as early as Pherecydes. For a good discussion of this issue, see Most (Reference Most1989).

19 Naturally, it would be impossible to cite all works that deal with Plato’s myth-making and emphasize his awareness of the heuristic value of images: see, among others, Brisson (Reference Brisson1994); Murray (Reference Murray and Buxton1999); Rowe (Reference Rowe and Buxton1999); Pender (Reference Pender and Boys-Stones2003); and, most recently, the collection of essays in Destrée and Edmonds (Reference Destrée and Edmonds2017).

20 Obbink (Reference Obbink, Copeland and Struck2010) 16. While Obbink also notes that during this early period one can find ‘quite a number of examples of allegorical reading’ (p. 16), a case can be made that, in one form or another, allegoresis is to be found already in Homer, on which see the seminal paper by Most (Reference Most1993) and now also Kotwick (Reference Kotwick2020).

21 Most (Reference Most, Copeland and Struck2010) 27. Most (Reference Most, Copeland and Struck2010) 33–34 singles out Cleanthes’ Hymn to Zeus (SVF 1.537) but also mentions Plato’s ‘extended mythic narratives, often transparently allegorical in character’ (p. 26).

22 It is probable that Proclus recounts here the view of Longinus, who might have sought to curb Porphyry’s zest for allegorical reading of the Atlantis episode, on which see Tarrant (Reference Tarrant2007) 74–76, 224 n.551 and 225 n.554.

23 Chase (Reference Chase2013) 38.

24 For overviews, see, for example, Sørensen (Reference Sørensen1963); Gadamer (Reference Gadamer, Weinsheimer and Marshall1989) 61–70; Pépin (Reference Pépin1976) 58–61; Todorov (Reference Todorov and Porter1982) 147–221; Struck (Reference Struck2004) 272–76; Halmi (Reference Halmi2007); and the numerous references given in these works.

25 Two of Freidenberg’s works are particularly relevant for the ensuing analyses: her paper on the origins of Greek lyric (first published in 1946) and her book on the mythopoetic roots of literature (completed in 1954 and published posthumously in 1978). These are Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg1991a) and (Reference Freidenberg, Braginskaia, Moss and Moss1997), respectively. For good introductions to Freidenberg and her background, see Perlina (Reference Perlina2002) and, more broadly, Kliger and Maslov (Reference Kliger and Maslov2016).

26 See, especially, Maslov (Reference Maslov2015) but also Maslov (Reference Maslov2012) 70–77 and Martin (Reference Martin, Kliger and Maslov2016) 293–304.

27 For a classic articulation of this perspective, see, obviously, Nestle (Reference Nestle1940), who incidentally labels Pherecydes precisely as a ‘forerunner’ (Vorläufer) of Ionian physics (p. 79). Most (Reference Most and Buxton1999a) and Laks (Reference Laks2006) offer particularly helpful assessments of this teleological perspective, but see also the entire collections of essays in Buxton (Reference Buxton1999) and Wians (Reference Wians2009), as well as the paper by Fowler (Reference Fowler2011).

28 Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg1991a) 6; see also Maslov (Reference Maslov2015) 174 and Martin (Reference Martin, Kliger and Maslov2016) 283.

31 While Freidenberg speaks of ‘mythological’ imagery, Maslov (Reference Maslov2015) 174 rightly, in my opinion, expresses reservations about this label. Accordingly, these images will be referred to here as ‘mythopoeic’.

33 Lloyd (Reference Lloyd1987) 174; see also pp. 175–81, 198–99, 204–08, 212–13 and Lloyd (Reference Lloyd2018) 3–4, 37, 91, 95. Compare further Martin (Reference Martin, Kliger and Maslov2016) 292 with n.46.

34 Besides, Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg1991a) 18 herself points out that ‘the lyric and philosophy arise almost simultaneously as two basic conceptual categories’.

35 The Appendix (Supplementary Material) illustrates the usefulness of Freidenberg’s perspective with two vexed issues in Pherecydean scholarship: his Chronos and his muchoi.

36 Thus, for example, Sturz (Reference Sturz1824) 46; Preller (Reference Preller1846) 387; Zimmermann (Reference Zimmermann1854) 179, 186; Diels (Reference Diels1897) 147–48, 154–55; Zeller (Reference Zeller1919) 114; von Fritz (Reference Fritz1938) col. 2030; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 84–85; West (Reference West1963) 168–69; Svenbro (Reference Svenbro1976) 118 with n.71; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 61, 65–66 n.2, 69, 71; Lisi (Reference Lisi1985) 275; Ford (Reference Ford2002) 69 with n.6; Gatzemeier (Reference Gatzemeier and Villers2005) 373 with n.12; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 142; Naddaf (Reference Naddaf and Wians2009) 111; Sassi (Reference Sassi2009) 92; Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2017) 317.

37 For Zas, see, among others, Eisler (Reference Eisler1910) 357–59; Gomperz (Reference Gomperz1929) 15; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 83; West (Reference West1971) 50–52; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 57; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 145–46. For Ogenos, see, among others, Eisler (Reference Eisler1910) 201–03; Gomperz (Reference Gomperz1929) 21; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 85; West (Reference West1971) 50; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 62 n.2; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 145 with n.33.

38 On the ‘house of Oceanus’ (Il. 14.311), see Gomperz (Reference Gomperz1929) 22 n.15. On the robe that was ‘most beautiful in its embroidery and greatest’ (Il. 6.294), see Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 53 n.6.

39 See already Classen (Reference Classen1962) 15 and 19 but especially Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 56–57. Pherecydes’ priority is now widely acknowledged: thus, for instance, Wright (Reference Wright1992) 66; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 152–53, 160–61; Chase (Reference Chase2013) passim but especially p. 38; Basile (Reference Basile2019) 100; Santamaría (Reference Santamaría and Vassallo2019) 96, 104; (Reference Santamaría, Bernabé Pajares and Martín Hernández2021) 130. Formerly, the honour was given to Plato (for example, Cornford (Reference Cornford1935) 34), although some scholars pointed to the Orient (for example, Eisler (Reference Eisler1910) passim). West (Reference West1971) 54–55 discussed various non-Greek parallels but, tellingly, concluded that they are all ‘too imprecise to be relied on as evidence that Zas’ weaving was more than a spontaneous invention by Pherecydes’ (p. 55). Hence, even if one wants to flirt with the assertion that Pherecydes was inspired by some Oriental myth(s), one should still appreciate his achievement of bringing the image of the artisan demiurge into the Greek world. Most (Reference Most1987) has persuasively argued that Alcman’s Thetis (Page F5 = Calame F81) was allegorized as a cosmogonic demiurge by the anonymous commentator rather than by the poet himself, and his argument is now generally accepted: see Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 54–55 n.8 or Santamaría (Reference Santamaría, Bernabé Pajares and Martín Hernández2021) 125–26; but cf. Sassi (Reference Sassi2009) 98–99.

40 It is noteworthy that in archaic poetry (for example, Hes. Theog. 392–96) the meanings of geras and timē could overlap, on which see Diels (Reference Diels1888) 13; West (Reference West1963) 165 with n.2; (Reference West1971) 17 with n.2; Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 52; Santamaría (Reference Santamaría and Vassallo2019) 96 with n.33.

41 See, for instance, Heraclitus the Allegorist, Quaestiones homericae 43–51 and the discussions by Buffière (Reference Buffière1956) 155–65 or Hardie (Reference Hardie1985), especially 15–17.

42 See the works cited above in n.36.

43 Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg, Braginskaia, Moss and Moss1997) 67 notes that it is the concreteness of such images that calls forth their abstract interpretation. While later cosmological accounts still exploit the concrete meaning of poikillō to convey that the cosmos is divinely adorned and ordered (see, for example, Pl. Ti. 40a6–7), the editor has pointed out to me that this tapestry technique involved a kind of over-weaving in which the decoration was worked into the cloth as it was being made. Thus, the imagery sits well with Chthonie’s transformation from a subterranean structure into the visible surface.

44 The controversy over whether the Timaean creation story is to be taken literally or metaphorically persists since antiquity: for overviews, see among others, Zeyl (Reference Zeyl2000) xx–xxv or Ilievski (Reference Ilievski, Vázquez and Ross2022) 45–61. Most crucially, though, Plato explicitly qualifies (some parts of) his account (for example, 29c5–7 or 29d1–3), whereas Pherecydes does nothing of the sort.

45 Rowe (Reference Rowe1995) 188 aptly stresses that the Politicus myth presupposes the cosmological account of the Timaeus, and Brisson (Reference Brisson and Rowe1995) extensively discusses the former.

46 Over two centuries ago, Sturz (Reference Sturz1824) 46–47 could already bemoan the ‘varias interpretationes’ that had been put forward prior to his edition.

47 See, for example, Zimmermann (Reference Zimmermann1854) 187 and Conrad (Reference Conrad1856) 41.

48 Diels (Reference Diels1888) 15; see also Diels (Reference Diels1897) 148 with n.1. Diels’ interpretation was endorsed by Zeller (Reference Zeller1919) 114 with nn.2–3, 119 with nn.4–5 and Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1936) 215 n.2 as well as (Reference Jaeger1953) 86 with n.74.

49 von Fritz (Reference Fritz1938) col. 2030 stressed that Pherecydes conceived of Oceanus as part of the earth and pointed to DK 12 A6.

50 Naddaf (Reference Naddaf and Wians2009) 127 n.55 believes that, ‘given the dates and the parallels, it could be plausibly argued that Pherecydes is allegorizing Anaximander’.

51 Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 64; see also Edwards (Reference Edwards1993) 66.

52 See, among others, Lisi (Reference Lisi1985) 273; Breglia (Reference Breglia2000) 187; Edwards (Reference Edwards1993) 66 n.7; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 136 n.7.

53 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 70 n.53.

54 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 74 with n.61.

55 See, for example, Gomperz (Reference Gomperz1929) 22; Lisi (Reference Lisi1985) 273; Breglia (Reference Breglia2000) 187.

56 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 73 and, more recently, Saudelli (Reference Saudelli2011) 86.

57 LSJ has ‘whose sails are wings’, but Slater (Reference Slater1969) 523 and Gerber (Reference Gerber2002) 31 opt for ‘oars’.

58 Although branches should not be hastily excluded either, as evidenced by Homer’s ‘sky-reaching’ (οὐρανομήκης) fir or ‘towering’ (ὑψίκομοι) oaks (Od. 5.239, 9.186). One wonders if Pherecydes’ winged oak might be a portrayal of a holm oak (Quercus ilex). The growth habit of holm oaks is to produce a massive rounded, dome-like crown (often umbrella-shaped). Trees of this species frequently grow widespread lateral branches at the lower levels which could be described as wing-like (like sails or oars). This is quite a distinctive growth habit, different from other kinds of Mediterranean oak tree (I thank the editor for suggesting this to me).

59 Breglia (Reference Breglia2000) 187 believes that the image of the earth’s roots is of little value for our understanding of the Pherecydean image, but the overwhelming preponderance of scholars rightly, in my opinion, favour some connection: see, among others, Diels (Reference Diels1888) 15; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1936) 215 n.2; (Reference Jaeger1953) 86 with n.74; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 64; West (Reference West1966) 361; (Reference West1971) 58; Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 70; Saudelli (Reference Saudelli2011) 87.

60 See Diels (Reference Diels1897) 148 n.1 and 154 n.2. Diels points to Aristotle’s third book of On Poetry (Diog. Laert. 2.46 = S F58 = LM 4 R11), where Pherecydes is reported to have ‘engaged in rivalry’ (ἐφιλονϵίκϵι) with Thales, but the Suda also relates that Pherecydes ‘engaged in a jealous rivalry’ (ἐζηλοτύπϵι) with Thales’ teaching (s.v. Φϵρϵκύδης = DK 7 A2 = S F2).

61 Thus, for example, Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 83, 86; von Fritz (Reference Fritz1938) cols 2028–29; Buffière (Reference Buffière1956) 98 n.65; Pfeiffer (Reference Pfeiffer1968) 10; Svenbro (Reference Svenbro1976) 118 with n.71; Boys-Stones (Reference Boys-Stones2001) 31 n.7; Ford (Reference Ford2002) 69 with n.6; Kahn (Reference Kahn and Yunis2003) 144; Gatzemeier (Reference Gatzemeier and Villers2005) 339 with nn.21–22, 373 with nn.12–13; Naddaf (Reference Naddaf and Wians2009) 111.

62 Laks (Reference Laks2009) has cogently argued that the conjunction καί which precedes the phrase τῷ μὴ μυθικῶς πάντα λέγϵιν (1091b8–9) is to be preserved and read adverbially as ‘also’, since Aristotle counts Pherecydes among the mixed theologians who are to be differentiated from the ancient poets. Laks’ interpretation is now widely accepted: see, among others, Saudelli (Reference Saudelli2011) 83 n.13; Santamaría (Reference Santamaría and Vassallo2019) 91 n.2; Gheerbrant (Reference Gheerbrant2021) 48 n.78.

63 See Classen (Reference Classen1962) 15; Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 90–91; Gatzemeier (Reference Gatzemeier and Villers2005) 339, 373; Laks (Reference Laks2009) 640 n.24. Incidentally, this is consistent with those authors who identify all Pherecydean deities with the principles: see Damascius, De principiis 124b (= DK 7 A8 = S F60 = LM 4 R23) and Hermias, Irrisio gentilium philosophorum 12 (= DK 7 A9 = S F66 = LM 4 R30).

64 The eternity of Pherecydes’ gods is corroborated by Eudemus in Damascius (De principiis 124b = DK 7 A8 = S F60 = LM 4 R23).

65 See, among others, Gomperz (Reference Gomperz1929) 16; Jaeger (Reference Jaeger1953) 83; Classen (Reference Classen1962) 15 with n.23; Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 56–57, 71; Lisi (Reference Lisi1985) 264; Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 15; Lesky (Reference Lesky1999) 192; Kahn (Reference Kahn and Yunis2003) 144; Munn (Reference Munn2006) 49; Granger (Reference Granger2007) 147–48; Naddaf (Reference Naddaf and Wians2009) 111; Sassi (Reference Sassi2009) 93; Basile (Reference Basile2019) 100; Gheerbrant (Reference Gheerbrant2021) 34; Santamaría (Reference Santamaría, Bernabé Pajares and Martín Hernández2021) 129.

66 Already in Homer the divine names can signify both concrete figures and ‘forces of nature’: thus Hephaestus is fire (Il. 2.426), Aphrodite is sex (Od. 22.444) and so on; see Freidenberg (Reference Freidenberg, Braginskaia, Moss and Moss1997) 41 and Martin (Reference Martin, Kliger and Maslov2016) 289.

67 However, Aristotle need not be taken to say that ‘everything’ in Pherecydes is not entirely mythical, since the remark can be read as a judgement on Pherecydes’ account as a whole and not necessarily about every portion of it (I thank the anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to me).

68 While Porphyry (Quaestiones homericae 1.240.14–241.12 = DK 8 A2) relates that Theagenes of Rhegium (fl. ca. 525 BCE) was the first to put forward an allegoresis of Homer’s battle of the gods (Il. 20.23–75), this became a topos in the allegorical tradition: see, for instance, Heraclitus the Allegorist, Quaestiones homericae 52–58 or [Plut.] Vit. Hom. 102.

69 Thus, for example, Preller (Reference Preller1846) 386; Pfeiffer (Reference Pfeiffer1968) 10; Domaradzki (Reference Domaradzki2017) 317.

70 On the basis of Origen C. Cels. 6.42 (= DK 7 B5 = S F83 = LM 4 D13/R27a); see also above n.4.

71 Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 21–27 and 38–49 has offered the most elaborate and erudite interpretation, which, however, he himself admits to be ‘conjectural’ (p. 43). For various criticisms of Schibli’s reconstruction, see Sider (Reference Sider1990) §3; Lamberton (Reference Lamberton1992) 388–89; Breglia (Reference Breglia2000) 178–79; Gheerbrant (Reference Gheerbrant2021) 42–44.

72 West (Reference West1971) 70–72 brilliantly points to the Stepterion festival at Delphi, in which Apollo’s victory over the serpent Python was re-enacted by the wearing of crowns (see Plut. De def. or. 15.417F–418C, Quaest. Graec. 12.293C and further West (Reference West1963) 164 n.3 as well as Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 97 n.51, 137).

73 Origen makes it clear that Ophioneus was an ophis, as he argues that the Pherecydean snake-god derives from Moses’ account of the serpent-devil (C. Cels. 6.43 = S F79 = LM 4 R27b).

74 Naturally, scholars remain divided as to whether Pherecydes’ Ophioneus ought to be derived from the Greek tradition (for example, Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 68) or from an Eastern source (for example, West (Reference West1971) 49). Most importantly, though, the topos of a war represented the heritage of early Greek epic that could not have been ignored, on which see Most (Reference Most and Long1999b) 343–44.

75 Thus, for instance, Diogenes Laertius suggests that Thales was the first to have spoken ‘about nature’ (1.24 = DK 11 A1 = LM 5 R11) and Anaximander the first to have published a ‘summary exposition’ of his teachings (2.2 = DK 12 A1 = LM 6 D2), which was probably written in some sort of prose: see Kirk et al. (Reference Kirk, Raven and Schofield1983) 102 and Schibli (Reference Schibli1990) 4 but cf. Most (Reference Most and Long1999b) 349; Laks (Reference Laks2001) 139–40; Sassi (Reference Sassi2009) 129–33.

References

Basile, G.-J. (2019) ‘The early Greek prose-writing tradition: bridging the myth-history divide’, DHA 45, 81112Google Scholar
Blönnigen, C. (1992) Der griechische Ursprung der jüdisch-hellenistischen Allegorese und ihre Rezeption in der alexandrinischen Patristik (Frankfurt am Main)Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G.R. (2001) Post-Hellenistic Philosophy: A Study of Its Development from the Stoics to Origen (Oxford)Google Scholar
Breglia, L. (2000) ‘Ferecide di Siro tra orfici e pitagorici’, in M. Tortorelli Ghidini, A. Storchi Marino and A. Visconti (eds), Tra Orfeo e Pitagora: Origini e incontri di culture nell’antichità (Naples) 161–94Google Scholar
Brisson, L. (1994) Platon, les mots et les mythes. Comment et pourquoi Platon nomma le mythe? (2nd edition) (Paris)Google Scholar
Brisson, L. (1995) ‘Interprétation du mythe du Politique’, in Rowe, C.J. (ed.), Reading the Statesman: Proceedings of the Third Symposium Platonicum (Sankt Augustin) 349–63Google Scholar
Buffière, F. (1956) Les mythes d’Homère et la pensée grecque (Paris)Google Scholar
Buxton, R. (ed.) (1999) From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought (Oxford)Google Scholar
Chase, M. (2013) ‘Discussions on the eternity of the world in antiquity and contemporary cosmology’, ΣΧΟΛΗ 7, 2068 Google Scholar
Classen, C.J. (1962) ‘The creator in Greek thought from Homer to Plato’, C&M 23, 122 Google Scholar
Colli, G. (1978) La sapienza greca, Volume 2: Epimenide, Ferecide, Talete, Anassimandro, Anassimene, Onomacrito (Milan)Google Scholar
Conrad, J. (1856) De Pherecydis Syrii aetate atque cosmologia (Ph.D. Diss. Bonn University)Google Scholar
Cornford, F.M. (1935) Plato’s Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato. Translated, with a Running Commentary (London)Google Scholar
Crisp, P. (2005) ‘Allegory and symbol – a fundamental opposition?’, Language and Literature 14, 323–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Destrée, P. and Edmonds, R.G. (eds) (2017) Plato and the Power of Images (Leiden)Google Scholar
Diels, H. (1888) ‘Zu Pherekydes von Syros’, AGPh 1, 1115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diels, H. (1897) ‘Zur Pentemychos des Pherekydes’, Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 1897, 144–56Google Scholar
Diels, H. and Kranz, W. (eds) (1951–1952) Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (3 vols) (6th edition) (Berlin)Google Scholar
Domaradzki, M. (2017) ‘The beginnings of Greek allegoresis’, CW 110, 299321 Google Scholar
Domaradzki, M. (2022) ‘Stoic allegoresis: the problem of definition and influence’, CPh 117, 139–62Google Scholar
Edwards, M. (1993) ‘Cybele among the philosophers: Pherecydes to Plato’, Eranos 91, 6574 Google Scholar
Eisler, R. (1910) Weltenmantel und Himmelszelt: Religionsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zur Urgeschichte des antiken Weltbildes (2 vols) (Munich)Google Scholar
Ford, A. (2002) The Origins of Criticism: Literary Culture and Poetic Theory in Classical Greece (Princeton)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fowler, R.L. (1999) ‘The authors named Pherecydes’, Mnemosyne 52, 115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fowler, R.L. (2011) ‘Mythos and logos’, JHS 131, 4566 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freidenberg, O. (1991a) ‘The origin of the Greek lyric’, Soviet Studies in Literature 27, 319 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freidenberg, O. (1991b) ‘The origin of the epic simile: on material from the Iliad’, Soviet Studies in Literature 27, 2037 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freidenberg, O. (1997) Image and Concept: Mythopoetic Roots of Literature (ed. Braginskaia, N. and Moss, K.; tr. Moss, K.) (Amsterdam)Google Scholar
Fritz, K. von (1938) ‘Pherekydes (Mythograph)’, RE 19.2, cols 2025–33Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1989) Truth and Method (tr. Weinsheimer, J. and Marshall, D.G.) (2nd edition) (London)Google Scholar
Gatzemeier, M. (2005) Philosophie als Theorie der Rationalität: Analysen und Rekonstruktionen, Volume 1: Zur Philosophie der wissenschaftlichen Welt (ed. Villers, J.) (Würzburg)Google Scholar
Gerber, D.E. (2002) A Commentary on Pindar Olympian Nine (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Gheerbrant, X. (2021) ‘Phérécyde de Syros D6/R23 (LM) réexaminé: la génération des dieux des cinq recoins à partir des trois éléments produits par Chronos’, PhilosAnt 21, 3161 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gomperz, H. (1929) ‘Zur Theogonie des Pherekydes von Syros’, WS 47, 1426 Google Scholar
Granger, H. (2007) ‘The theologian Pherecydes of Syros and the early days of natural philosophy’, HSCPh 103, 135–63Google Scholar
Griffiths, J.G. (1967) ‘Allegory in Greece and Egypt’, JEA 53, 79102 Google Scholar
Halmi, N. (2007) The Genealogy of the Romantic Symbol (Oxford)Google Scholar
Hardie, P.R. (1985) ‘ Imago mundi: cosmological and ideological aspects of the shield of Achilles’, JHS 105, 1131 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ilievski, V. (2022) ‘The demiurge and his place in Plato’s metaphysics and cosmology’, in Vázquez, D. and Ross, A. (eds), Time and Cosmology in Plato and the Platonic Tradition (Leiden) 4477 Google Scholar
Jacoby, F. (1947) ‘The first Athenian prose writer’, Mnemosyne 13, 1364 Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. (1936) Paideia: Die Formung des griechischen Menschen 1 (2nd edition) (Berlin)Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. (1953) Die Theologie der frühen griechischen Denker (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (2003) ‘Writing philosophy: prose and poetry from Thales to Plato’, in Yunis, H. (ed.), Written Texts and the Rise of Literate Culture in Ancient Greece (Cambridge) 139–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, G.S., Raven, J.E. and Schofield, M. (1983) The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts (2nd edition) (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Kliger, I. and Maslov, B. (eds) (2016) Persistent Forms: Explorations in Historical Poetics (New York)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kotwick, M.E. (2020) ‘Allegorical interpretation in Homer: Penelope’s dream and early Greek allegoresis’, AJPh 141, 126 Google Scholar
Laks, A. (2001) ‘Écriture, prose, et les débuts de la philosophie grecque’, Methodos 1, 131–51Google Scholar
Laks, A. (2006) Introduction à la ‘philosophie présocratique’ (Paris)Google Scholar
Laks, A. (2009) ‘Une doxographie d’Aristote (Métaphysique, Nu 4, 1091a33–91b15) et le sens d’un καί (Phérécyde, 7A7 DK, F81 Schibli)’, REG 122, 635–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A. and Most, G.W. (eds and trs) (2016) Early Greek Philosophy (9 vols) (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Lamberton, R. (1992) Review of Schibli 1990, AncPhil 12, 383–93Google Scholar
Lausberg, H. (1990) Handbuch der literarischen Rhetorik: Eine Grundlegung der Literaturwissenschaft (3rd edition) (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Lesky, A. (1999) Geschichte der griechischen Literatur (3rd edition) (Munich)Google Scholar
Lisi, F.L. (1985) ‘La teología de Ferécides de Siro’, Helmantica 36, 251–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (1987) The Revolutions of Wisdom: Studies in the Claims and Practice of Ancient Greek Science (Berkeley)Google Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (2018) The Ambivalences of Rationality: Ancient and Modern Cross-Cultural Explorations (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Martin, R.P. (2016) ‘Against ornament: O.M. Freidenberg’s concept of metaphor in ancient and modern contexts’, Kliger, I. and Maslov, B. (eds), Persistent Forms: Explorations in Historical Poetics (New York) 274313Google Scholar
Maslov, B. (2012) ‘From (theogonic) mythos to (poetic) logos: reading Pindar’s genealogical metaphors after Freidenberg’, Journal of Ancient Near Eastern Religions 12, 4977 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maslov, B. (2015) Pindar and the Emergence of Literature (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Most, G.W. (1987) ‘Alcman’s “cosmogonic” fragment (Fr. 5 Page, 81 Calame)’, CQ 37, 119CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Most, G.W. (1989) ‘Zur Archäologie der Archaik’, A&A 35, 123 Google Scholar
Most, G.W. (1993) ‘Die früheste erhaltene griechische Dichterallegorese’, RhM 136, 209–12Google Scholar
Most, G.W. (1999a) ‘From logos to mythos’, in Buxton, R. (ed.), From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought (Oxford) 2547CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Most, G.W. (1999b) ‘The poetics of early Greek philosophy’, in Long, A.A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge) 332–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Most, G.W. (2010) ‘Hellenistic allegory and early imperial rhetoric’, in Copeland, R. and Struck, P.T. (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Allegory (Cambridge) 2638Google Scholar
Most, G.W. (2016) ‘Allegoresis and etymology’, in Grafton, A. and Most, G.W. (eds), Canonical Texts and Scholarly Practices: A Global Comparative Approach (Cambridge) 5274Google Scholar
Munn, M. (2006) The Mother of the Gods, Athens, and the Tyranny of Asia: A Study of Sovereignty in Ancient Religion (Berkeley)Google Scholar
Müri, W. (1976) ‘ΣYΜBΟΛΟΝ: Wort- und sachgeschichtliche Studie’, in Griechische Studien: Ausgewählte wort- und sachgeschichtliche Forschungen zur Antike (ed. Vischer, E.) (Basel) 144Google Scholar
Murray, P. (1999) ‘What is a muthos for Plato?’ in Buxton, R. (ed.), From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought (Oxford) 251–62Google Scholar
Naddaf, G. (2009) ‘Allegory and the origins of philosophy’, in Wians, W. (ed.), Logos and Muthos: Philosophical Essays in Greek Literature (Albany) 99131Google Scholar
Nestle, W. (1940) Vom Mythos zum Logos: Die Selbstentfaltung des griechischen Denkens von Homer bis auf die Sophistik und Sokrates (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Obbink, D. (2010) ‘Early Greek allegory’, in Copeland, R. and Struck, P.T. (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Allegory (Cambridge) 1525Google Scholar
Pàmias, J. (2005) ‘Ferecides de Siros y Ferecides de Atenas: una nueva aproximación’, CFC(G) 15, 2734 Google Scholar
Pender, E.E. (2003) ‘Plato on metaphors and models’, in Boys-Stones, G.R. (ed.), Metaphor, Allegory, and the Classical Tradition: Ancient Thought and Modern Revisions (Oxford) 5581.Google Scholar
Pépin, J. (1976) Mythe et allégorie: les origines grecques et les contestations judéo-chrétiennes (Paris)Google Scholar
Perlina, N. (2002) Ol’ga Freidenberg’s Works and Days (Bloomington)Google Scholar
Pfeiffer, R. (1968) History of Classical Scholarship from the Beginnings to the End of the Hellenistic Age (Oxford)Google Scholar
Preller, L. (1846) ‘Studien zur griechischen Litteratur. 1. Die Theogonie des Pherekydes von Syros’, Rhm 4, 377–89Google Scholar
Rowe, C.J. (1995) Plato: Statesman (Warminster)Google Scholar
Rowe, C.J. (1999) ‘Myth, history, and dialectic in Plato’s Republic and Timaeus-Critias’, in Buxton, R. (ed.), From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought (Oxford) 263–78Google Scholar
Santamaría, M.A. (2019) ‘Pherecydes of Syros in the papyrological tradition’, in Vassallo, C. (ed.), Presocratics and Papyrological Tradition: A Philosophical Reappraisal of the Sources (Berlin) 91107Google Scholar
Santamaría, M.A. (2021) ‘The emergence of the world in early Greek theogonies from Hesiod to Acusilaus’, in Bernabé Pajares, A. and Martín Hernández, R. (eds), Narrating the Beginnings (Wiesbaden) 117–37Google Scholar
Sassi, M.M. (2009) Gli inizi della filosofia: in Grecia (Turin)Google Scholar
Saudelli, L. (2011) ‘Le chêne et le voile de Phérécyde: note sur un témoignage du gnostique Isidore (7 B 2 DK, F 76 S)’, REG 124, 7992 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schibli, H.S. (1990) Pherekydes of Syros (Oxford)Google Scholar
Sider, D. (1990) Review of Schibli 1990, BMCRev https://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/1990/1990.02.17/ Google Scholar
Slater, W.J. (1969) Lexicon to Pindar (Berlin)Google Scholar
Sørensen, B.A. (1963) Symbol und Symbolismus in den ästhetischen Theorien des 18. Jahrhunderts und der deutschen Romantik (Copenhagen)Google Scholar
Struck, P.T. (2004) Birth of the Symbol: Ancient Readers at the Limits of Their Texts (Princeton)Google Scholar
Sturz, F.W. (ed.) (1824) Pherecydis fragmenta: e variis scriptoribus collegit, emendavit, illustravit, commentationem de Pherecyde utroque et philosopho et historico praemisit, denique fragmenta Acusilai et indices adiecit … (2nd edition) (Leipzig)Google Scholar
Svenbro, J. (1976) La parole et le marbre: aux origines de la poétique grecque (Ph.D. Diss. Lund University)Google Scholar
Tarrant, H. (2007) Proclus: Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Volume 1: Book 1. Proclus on the Socratic State and Atlantis (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Tate, J. (1927) ‘The beginnings of Greek allegory’, CR 41, 214–15Google Scholar
Tate, J. (1934) ‘On the history of allegorism’, CQ 28, 105–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorov, T. (1982) Theories of the Symbol (tr. Porter, C.) (Ithaca)Google Scholar
Toye, D.L. (1997) ‘Pherecydes of Syros: ancient theologian and genealogist’, Mnemosyne 50, 530–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
West, M.L. (1963) ‘Three Presocratic cosmologies’, CQ 13, 154–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
West, M.L. (ed.) (1966) Hesiod: Theogony with Prolegomena and Commentary (Oxford)Google Scholar
West, M.L. (1971) Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient (Oxford)Google Scholar
Whitman, J. (1987) Allegory: The Dynamics of an Ancient and Medieval Technique (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Wians, W. (ed.) (2009) Logos and Muthos: Philosophical Essays in Greek Literature (Albany)Google Scholar
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. von (1926) ‘Pherekydes’, Sitzungsberichte der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 1926, 125–46Google Scholar
Wright, M.R. (1992) Review of Schibli 1990, CR 42, 6667 Google Scholar
Zeller, E. 1919. Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung, Volume 1: Allgemeine Einleitung. Vorsokratische Philosophie (6th edition) (Leipzig)Google Scholar
Zeyl, D.J. (2000) Plato: Timaeus (Indianapolis)Google Scholar
Zimmermann, R. (1854) ‘Über die Lehre des Pherekydes von Syros und ihr Verhältniß zu außergriechischen Glaubenskreisen’, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 24, 161–99Google Scholar
Supplementary material: File

Domaradzki supplementary material

Domaradzki supplementary material
Download Domaradzki supplementary material(File)
File 173.4 KB