Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-r5qjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-09-12T20:08:30.693Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The emerging movement against wild animal suffering and its potential implications for conservation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 August 2025

Ronald Sandler*
Affiliation:
Northeastern University, Boston Campus, Boston, Massachusetts, USA
Clare Palmer
Affiliation:
Texas A&M University System, College Station, Texas, USA
*
*Corresponding author, r.sandler@northeastern.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Historically, conservation has focused on species, ecological communities, systems and processes, rather than on individual animals. Even among advocates for compassionate conservation, the focus on animal welfare or animal rights only relates to conservation activities. However, in recent years the idea of managing ecosystems primarily to improve wild animal welfare has been gaining traction among animal ethicists and animal welfare researchers. Managing ecosystems for animal welfare is generally antithetical to management to support ecological and evolutionary processes, since essential features of those processes, such as predation, privation and competition, are sources of animal suffering. Our aim in this paper is not to defend the proposal that ecosystem management should focus primarily on improving wild animal welfare. It is, rather, to situate this proposal in relation to concerns about wild animal welfare expressed by the public and conservation biologists; to connect it to the rise of subjectivist theories of animal welfare; to introduce the ethical arguments used to support elevating the importance of individual wild animals; to explain the advocacy context; to outline potential implications for conservation; and to review critiques of taking a wild animal welfare focus in ecosystem management.

Information

Type
Review
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Fauna & Flora International

Introduction

A long-running debate in ecosystem management has been whether (or when) the primary goal should be to maintain biological diversity through ecological integrity or, alternatively, to maximize the long-term usefulness of ecological systems and species for people. It has also been argued that these are not alternatives; if a broad enough, long-term view of human interests is adopted, approaches can be found that are good both for nature and for people (Norton, Reference Norton1991).

Here, however, we discuss a goal for ecosystem and species management that is not about nature or people; it is about managing for the improved welfare of sentient wild animals. This goal is gaining traction among animal ethicists and animal welfare researchers, and is generally antithetical to management to support spontaneous ecological and evolutionary processes. Essential features of those processes, for example predation, privation, and competition, are seen as fundamental sources of animal suffering (Tomasik, Reference Tomasik2015; Faria & Paez, Reference Faria and Paez2019; Kianpour & Paez, Reference Kianpour and Paez2022; Faria, Reference Faria2023; Horta, Reference Horta, Burgat and Dardenne2023; Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2023). At present, proposed interventions to reduce wild animal suffering are relatively modest but include vaccinations, fertility control and helping animals harmed by weather events where feasible (Faria, Reference Faria2023; Horta & Teran, Reference Horta and Teran2023). However, as influential philosopher Martha Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum2007, p. 400) has put it, the long-term goal should be ‘the gradual supplanting of the natural by the just’. Other advocates for prioritizing wild animal welfare have referred to the goal as paradise engineering (Kianpour & Paez, Reference Kianpour and Paez2022) or creating an idyllic biosphere (Bruers et al., Reference Bruers, Davis, Hojjat, Koskensilta, Lepeltier and Pearce2024). This could eventually involve using biotechnology to engineer individuals of predatory species so they no longer hunt prey or individuals of r-selected species so they have fewer offspring (McMahan, Reference McMahan2010; McMahan, Reference McMahan, Cuneo and Halteman2015; Johannsen, Reference Johannsen2020; Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2023; Bruers et al., Reference Bruers, Davis, Hojjat, Koskensilta, Lepeltier and Pearce2024).

Our aim here is not to defend the proposal that ecosystem management should focus primarily on improving wild animal welfare. It is, rather, to situate this proposal in relation to concerns about wild animal welfare expressed by the public and conservation biologists; to connect it to the rise of subjectivist theories of animal welfare; to introduce the ethical arguments used to support elevating the importance of individual wild animals; to briefly explain the advocacy context; to outline potential implications for conservation; and to review critiques of a focus on wild animal welfare in ecosystem management.

Animal welfare concerns in conservation

Conservation has historically focused on species, ecological communities, systems and processes, rather than on individual animals. The primary conservation goal has been in situ conservation of populations and assemblages, through the maintenance of co-evolved relationships and the integrity of ecological systems and processes (Leopold, Reference Leopold1949; Soule, Reference Soule1985; Rolston, Reference Rolston1988). Of course, pursuing this goal does sometimes require attending to the welfare of individual animals, such as members of highly threatened species where every individual matters. But conservation practice has accepted some compromise of animal welfare in pursuit of conservation goals, for example in the context of captive breeding or translocation. It has also involved killing members of species perceived to be invasive, sometimes using methods likely to cause significant suffering, for example grey squirrels Sciurus carolinensis in the UK, cats Felis catus and red foxes Vulpes vulpes in Australia, and ship rats Rattus rattus, stoats Mustela erminea and common brushtail possums Trichosurus vulpecula in New Zealand (Littin et al., Reference Littin, Mellor, Warburton and Eason2004; Crowley et al., Reference Crowley, Hinchliffe and McDonald2018; Fleming & Ballard, Reference Fleming and Ballard2019).

Public and professional concerns about conservation rose sharply during the 1960s, in parallel to a similar increase in concern about animal welfare. In 1964, the publication of Ruth Harrison’s Animal Machines raised alarm about animal welfare in intensive farming, rather as Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring (1962) raised alarm about insecticides. Concern about agricultural animal welfare led to the birth of the so-called Animal Liberation movement in the early 1970s, as well as to the development of what is now called Animal Welfare Science. In the UK, the Farm Animal Welfare Council was formed in 1979 and produced the Five Freedoms approach, now the internationally used foundation for the welfare of animals under human care. Animal welfare concerns also led to burgeoning legislation addressing animal neglect and unnecessary suffering in farming, research, zoo/aquarium, sport and household contexts in Europe, the USA and elsewhere, although with considerable variation in regulations across jurisdictions.

Few regulations, however, concerned wild-living animals, as opposed to animals under human care. One exception is hunting, which has been widely regulated but where regulations generally aim at ensuring sustainable yields rather than improving animal welfare (Geist et al., Reference Geist, Mahoney and Organ2001). Some jurisdictions do regulate forms of hunting and trapping thought to be inhumane (for instance, snares were banned in Wales in 2023, glue traps across the UK in 2024, and hunting with dogs in 2004). Research with wild animals in the field, including conservation research, generally requires assessment by Animal Care and Welfare committees, although which activities are regulated and which are exempt again varies by jurisdiction (Palmer et al., Reference Palmer, Fischer, Gamborg, Hampton and Sandoe2023).

While regulations governing wild animal welfare are currently few, there is rising public concern about the issue. The strongest evidence of this is from the USA, where the America’s Wildlife Values project has carried out extensive questionnaire surveys of public wildlife values. This project differentiates between wildlife orientations, including, most significantly, Domination and Mutualist orientations. Those with a Domination orientation maintain that wildlife should be used to benefit humans, whereas Mutualists see wildlife as fellow life forms or companions in one’s social world. Research indicates that Americans, especially in urban areas, have been shifting away from Domination and towards Mutualism (Manfredo et al., Reference Manfredo, Teel and Dietsch2016, Reference Manfredo, Teel, Don Carlos, Sullivan, Bright and Dietsch2020).

There is also growing engagement in wildlife rescue and rehabilitation, with the establishment of organizations such as the International Wildlife Rehabilitation Council, which runs courses and provides lay certification in wildlife rehabilitation. An Australian study of wildlife carers found that volunteer marsupial rescuers spent an average of AUD 5,300 per annum and 31.6 hours per week caring for rescued marsupials (Englefield et al., Reference Englefield, Candy, Starling and McGreevy2019).

There has also been a rise in concern for wild animal welfare in conservation practice, particularly manifest in the discourse around compassionate conservation (Ramp & Bekoff, Reference Ramp and Bekoff2015; Wallach et al., Reference Wallach, Bekoff, Batavia, Nelson and Ramp2018). This view ‘challenges traditional conservation paradigms…by recognising the intrinsic value and rights of all living beings, advocating for more inclusive and ethical conservation actions that acknowledge we live together in multispecies societies, sharing one planet’ (Centre for Compassionate Conservation, 2025). Interpretation of compassionate conservation has varied greatly. More minimalist interpretations promote strategies that cause least suffering, where these are available and effective, for example using quick-killing traps rather than anticoagulant poisons. However, some critics argue that conservationists have long taken animal welfare into account in this way (Hayward et al., Reference Hayward, Callen, Allen, Ballard, Broekhuis and Bugir2019). Stronger interpretations support interventions that are believed to cause little or no suffering, such as pharmaceutical fertility control for problems of over-population, and reject killing animals for conservation goals (Wallach et al., Reference Wallach, Bekoff, Batavia, Nelson and Ramp2018, Reference Wallach, Batavia, Bekoff, Alexander, Baker and Ben-Ami2020). Radical though these commitments may seem, the focus remains on refraining from killing or causing suffering to animals affected by conservation actions. Proponents of compassionate conservation have not suggested that naturogenic suffering should be alleviated or wild animal welfare improved more generally (although see Katz, Reference Katz2024 for evidence of a shift in this direction). Rather, the aim is that alongside protecting wildlife populations, species and ecosystems, compassionate conservation should also include an ethical constraint concerning animal lives and welfare. The role of welfare here is analogous to the role of autonomy in biomedical research and clinical contexts. Respect for subject or patient autonomy (through informed consent) does not change the aim of the activity, such as increasing knowledge (research) or improving health (clinical), but it constrains what can be done in pursuit of these aims, in this case conducting research or treating people without informed consent.

What differentiates the growing wild animal welfare movement is that (1) it is concerned with reducing wild animal suffering irrespective of its origin (anthropogenic or naturogenic); and (2) it advocates for this as the goal of ecosystem management, as opposed to ecological goals associated with biodiversity or integrity.

Subjectivist approaches to animal welfare

This concern about the welfare of wild animals can partly be explained by the rise in subjectivist accounts of animal welfare. Dominant traditions in Western science until the mid-20th century held that non-human animals did not have feelings, meaningful mental lives or agency; they were automata acting on instinct and responding to stimuli (Broom, Reference Broom2011). However, from the 1950s onwards, ethological researchers increasingly discredited these views, arguing that many non-human animals were strongly motivated to fulfil their needs and suffered from frustration if unable to do so (Duncan & Wood-Gush, Reference Duncan and Wood-Gush1971). Animal welfare scientists today work from the premise that many animals consciously experience positive or negative mental states, or feelings, often referred to as sentience (Browning & Birch, Reference Browning and Birch2022). There is general agreement that all mammals and birds are sentient, and strong evidence for sentience in reptiles, amphibians, bony fish and cephalopods (Birch et al., Reference Birch, Burn, Schnell, Browning and Crump2021; Lambert et al., Reference Lambert, Elwin and D’Cruze2022). Evidence is less clear about other animals, although recent research indicates that decapod crustaceans are sentient (Birch et al., Reference Birch, Burn, Schnell, Browning and Crump2021) and there are contested claims about sentience in some insects (Klein & Barron, Reference Klein and Barron2016 and responses). Where the boundaries of sentience are placed may be significant in terms of the conservation implications of the growing movement against animal suffering.

While sentience is generally taken to be sufficient to have welfare, what constitutes animal welfare has not always been understood as being only about conscious experience. Traditionally, conservationists have understood wild animal welfare to be connected to the ability to engage in natural or species-typical behaviour in order to survive and reproduce, with minimal human interference (Rollin, Reference Rollin2016). However, some natural behaviour, such as male competitive fighting, can cause injuries or even be fatal, whereas engaging in apparently unnatural behaviours, such as taking advantage of food provisioning or playing computer games (captive orangutans Pongo spp.; Browning, Reference Browning2020), can be pleasurable and advantageous to physical or cognitive health. So, natural behaviour seems to be an inadequate measure of welfare.

As a result, recent conceptions of animal welfare have focused on the extent to which animals can satisfy their preferences and get what they want (Dawkins, Reference Dawkins2021), as well as the quality of their subjective experiences, their affective state, or how things feel to them from their own point of view (Browning, Reference Browning2020). This reconceptualization of animal welfare towards experience has been adopted by the World Association of Zoos and Aquaria and other zoo accreditation organizations as the Five Domains approach, which broadens and refocuses the Five Freedoms. Nutrition, environment, health and behaviour are taken to be physical/functional domains that all contribute to the fifth domain, an animal’s mental state, which determines the individual’s overall welfare (Mellor et al., Reference Mellor, Beausoleil, Littlewood, McLean, McGreevy and Jones2020). Most significantly, the Five Domains model emphasizes the importance not only of freedom from negative states (the emphasis of the Five Freedoms) but of positive mental states.

This experiential approach to animal welfare casts new light on traditional conservation practices. Many standard conservation activities focus on remediating or preventing anthropogenic threats and protecting critical habitat, thereby promoting species-typical behaviours. They make resources and space available for wild animals to feed, mate, raise offspring and live free of interference from people. However, this does not necessarily mean that they promote animal welfare, in the sense of positive subjective experiences for the animals concerned. Opponents of the traditional conservation approach argue that ‘nature is not a source of well-being for animals…it is a source of permanent suffering and death’ (Faria, Reference Faria2023, p. 86). It follows from this that the welfare of the majority of wild animals is low; that conservation activities do not improve their lives; and conservationists may be increasing suffering by perpetuating predatory and parasitic relationships.

This claim is not in itself sufficient to justify a shift in ecosystem management goals towards promoting wild animal welfare. A sound ethical argument that people ought, morally, to care about wild animal welfare and have a responsibility to improve it is also required. If we accept that many wild animals have rich experiential lives, and those experiences are what constitutes their welfare, how should we take their preferences, desires and suffering into account in our interactions with them, including in ecosystem management contexts?

Ethical arguments in support of promoting wild animal welfare

Over the last 50 years, the view that we do not need to consider non-human animals just because they are not human (variously labelled human exceptionalism, human chauvinism or speciesism) has been widely rejected by ethicists on the grounds that it is unjustifiable (Singer, Reference Singer1973; Regan, Reference Regan1983; Taylor, Reference Taylor1986; Plumwood, Reference Plumwood1993; Hursthouse, Reference Hursthouse2000). It is argued that those defending such a view offer no justification for why humans are morally important and non-humans are not; or they appeal to capacities that are either not exclusive to humans, not possessed by all humans, or irrelevant to deciding whether a being matters morally. The key idea was neatly captured as long ago as 1789 by the Victorian reformer Jeremy Bentham when he wrote:

What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or, perhaps, the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day, or a week, or even a month, old. But suppose the case were otherwise, what would it avail? The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?

Here, Bentham maintains that while there is significant overlap between (some) humans and (some) animals in terms of capacities like language or reason, such capacities are anyway irrelevant for determining whether a being matters. It is sentience that matters. This does not necessarily mean that humans and sentient animals are of equal moral value, but it does mean that animal suffering should be seen as morally significant, if human suffering is.

However, the rejection of human exceptionalism and the assertion of the moral importance of non-human animals is not enough to ethically justify interventions to protect the welfare of wild animals negatively affected by ecological and evolutionary processes. After all, compassionate conservationists are also committed to considering the welfare of wild animals, but they don’t maintain that naturogenic wild animal suffering should be addressed. One way to understand the different views here is in terms of negative and positive responsibilities (or duties). Negative responsibilities are duties to not cause harms or wrongs to others; positive responsibilities are duties to benefit or improve the condition of others. Compassionate conservationists advocate for negative duties to wild animals. Proponents of improving wild animal welfare advocate for positive duties to wild animals, which is the novel and controversial feature of the view.

Two general approaches have been used to argue for positive duties to wild animals: beneficence-oriented and justice-oriented. Beneficence is the moral duty or responsibility to help others when in a position to do so. That there are duties of beneficence to other people, including strangers, is widely accepted. Imagine that you are hiking in remote countryside and come across an injured and dehydrated person, unable to walk. Most people would think that you should assist them, even though they are a stranger, you are not responsible for their situation, and there is some cost to you. The morally relevant facts here are: a person in great need will suffer (and perhaps die) without your assistance, and you are in a position to aid them; that they are a stranger is irrelevant.

Now imagine that instead of another person, you come across a tortoise that has accidentally flipped over and cannot right itself. The tortoise is suffering and will die unless you intervene. The situation appears analogous to the one with the injured person: there is suffering, you are not responsible, but you are in a position to help, in fact at less cost to yourself than in the case of assisting a person. Proponents of extending beneficence to wild animals maintain that you should help in this case as well, both to be consistent and since all the morally relevant conditions are the same. You cannot argue that the relevant difference is that in one case a person is suffering and in another it is a tortoise, because that would be human exceptionalism.

Thinking that one should assist the tortoise does not necessarily imply a commitment to the idea that its interests and those of the injured person should be considered equally. One might think that even where the interests of the tortoise and the human are of similar strength (perhaps each feels thirsty to a similar degree) the human’s interests are more important and should have priority. But proponents of wild animal beneficence generally adopt the principle that like interests should be considered alike, without respect to whose interests they are or the species to which they belong (Singer, Reference Singer1973; Faria, Reference Faria2023). Part of the justification for the principle of equal consideration of interests in interpersonal ethics is that it embodies a commitment to the equal worth of people and explains why differential consideration based on race, sex, religion or nationality are ethically problematic. Proponents of aiding wild animals simply extend equal consideration of similar interests to all sentient, non-human animals. This does not necessarily mean that non-human animals have the same interests as humans; most humans have a greater range and complexity of interests because of their psychological, cognitive, social and imaginative capacities. But it does mean that the interests of non-human animals should be considered without prejudice, i.e. not discounted or dismissed just because they are those of a non-human.

Many proponents of beneficence to wild animals combine the principle of equal considerability of interests with ethical theories that claim that we ought to bring about the best consequences for welfare overall (e.g. utilitarianism). So, for example, if we can eliminate a parasite species, such as the New World screwworm Cochliomyia hominivorax that causes extensive wild animal suffering, without causing more suffering elsewhere (including to the parasites themselves, were they to be sentient), we ought to do so (Rodriguez and Harris, Reference Rodriguez and Harris2023). But not all defenders of benevolence to wild animals are utilitarians, aiming to bring about best consequences. Some endorse duty-based views, arguing that just as we have negative duties not to seriously harm others, so we also have positive duties to help them, and this should be extended to wild animals. Kyle Johannsen (Reference Johannsen2020), for instance, argues that we have a collective duty to aid wild animals, and that beneficence towards them is obligatory, including vaccination against disease and using gene-editing to spread beneficial traits.

Some justice-oriented frameworks also include positive duties towards wild animals. Justice for animals can be understood in different ways, legal or political. In legal terms, it is argued that legal standing should be extended to wild animals, so that they should be regarded as having property rights to their habitat, for example, to protect it from human incursion (Bradshaw, Reference Bradshaw2022). However, we are primarily concerned here with justice understood in the sense of political rights.

There are two obvious objections to bringing wild animals into the sphere of justice: first that the animals are wild (so they fall outside human political arrangements) and second that they are not human. One response to the first objection is to maintain that wildness no longer exists because the world is now ‘dominated, everywhere, by human power and activity’ (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2023). Even places that have been set aside as protected areas only have that protection so long as humans assign it. Moreover, since the world has been carved up into areas where either nations or collections of nations have legal authority and associated responsibilities, all so-called wild animals already reside in some political jurisdiction; so, on this view, it is not a matter of bringing them into the political sphere, but rather, what is owed to them given that they are already there.

The second objection relates back to the issue of human exceptionalism. Of course, animals cannot engage directly in political practices such as democratic decision-making; but then, neither can some humans. This does not mean that the interests of those humans should be discounted in political decision-making. According to Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum2023), for example, a just society is one that secures for each member (human or animal) ‘a decent chance to flourish’. This implies negative duties (for instance, not destroying habitat on which animals depend), but also involves positive duties to every sentient wild animal to ensure that they have a reasonable opportunity to flourish in accordance with their form of life. This means protecting their life, health and bodily integrity, including the provision of medical care and food, where possible, as well as protection against predators and natural disasters. Nussbaum has a particular substantive conception of justice (called the capabilities approach), but the justice case for promoting animal welfare does not depend on it. Any account of justice for wild animals on which they have positive rights or entitlements to the sorts of conditions Nussbaum emphasizes, e.g. health and security, will have similar implications.

Wild animal welfare and the effective altruism movement

Effective altruism has become an increasingly important player in the promotion of wild animal welfare. Effective altruism is based on the idea that philanthropy (and other forms of assistance) should identify and implement the most effective ways to benefit others by promoting overall welfare (similar to utilitarianism) through rational and impartial assessments (Centre for Effective Altruism, 2024). The effective altruism movement has grown rapidly over the past 2 decades. Founded largely by philosophers and ethicists, it has been embraced by several major philanthropic organizations and individuals, which direct hundreds of millions of dollars annually into the movement. Many other philanthropic organizations, while not expressly aligned with effective altruism, have shifted towards the sort of issues and principles of giving for which effective altruism advocates. There is also a strong and growing grass-roots movement, with hundreds of chapters around the world, online communities, conferences, research groups and networks.

Proponents of effective altruism emphasize the importance of identifying opportunities where large, cost-effective welfare gains are possible, particularly when an issue is under-prioritized relative to its significance. In interpersonal ethics, this has meant focusing on issues such as global poverty, neglected diseases and global health challenges. But the movement also has a commitment to impartiality across species, evidenced from the outset by the goal to reduce or eliminate intensive livestock farming, especially battery cages for poultry. In recent years, effective altruist organizations, including the Effective Altruism Foundation and Rethink Priorities, have become more concerned with wild animal suffering (Effective Altruism Foundation, 2017). These organizations maintain that there are far more wild animals than there are farmed animals, that these animals have low levels of welfare, and that wild animal welfare is an under-prioritized issue. For these reasons, funding is being directed towards projects, charities and research groups to study, raise awareness, and develop strategies to address the perceived problem of wild animal suffering.

Prioritizing wild animal welfare in ecosystem management

A primary focus on wild animal welfare in ecosystem management would involve a comprehensive revision of current approaches, a reorientation of theory and practice, and a complete re-evaluation of strategies and guiding principles. It would mean reconsidering traditional conservation values and reassessing the importance of spontaneous ecological and evolutionary processes, as well as the biological diversity and complexity that emerges from them (Horta, Reference Horta2017; Faria, Reference Faria2023). There would need to be a shift away from protecting biological diversity, promoting system integrity, and maintaining ecological relationships and species assemblages, towards improving the welfare of individual animals, with the aim of reducing their suffering and promoting positive experiences. The kinds of questions that would need to be addressed include, for example: Are protected areas an effective way to improve wild animal welfare, or do they instead enable the sorts of processes and conditions that give rise to wild animal suffering? If ecological integrity, historical continuity and biological diversity are less important than welfare, can reintroductions, translocations and captive breeding be justified? Are familiar conservation concepts, such as historical range, ecological integrity and invasiveness, and the guiding principles that make use of them, unhelpful if the goal is to promote wild animal welfare?

This shift in the values, goals, concepts, principles and practices that guide ecosystem management would also involve changes in perspectives and attitudes to the non-human world and our relationship with wild animals. Conservation, even when it involves significant ecological interventions, is largely deferential to the spontaneity of ecological systems and processes, and the biodiversity that results from them. This is often described in terms of respect, wonder, awe, appreciation or love for those processes and their outcomes (Leopold, Reference Leopold1949; Carson, Reference Carson1962; Hill, Reference Hill1983; Taylor, Reference Taylor1986; Bendik-Keymer & Pedersen, Reference Bendik-Keymer and Pedersen2024). In contrast, the ideals (or ultimate goals) that proponents of addressing wild animal suffering endorse are transformational with respect to ecological systems and processes. The goal, again, is ‘the gradual supplanting of the natural by the just’ (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2007) by benevolently and rationally remaking, designing and controlling ecological systems and processes for wild animal welfare, termed paradise engineering. There is considerable interest among proponents in how bioengineering could be used, for example by feeding predators synthetic meat (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2023) or genetically adapting predators to be vegetarian, whilst simultaneously administering fertility control to their former prey so that their populations do not over-expand, leading to suffering (McMahan, Reference McMahan2010; Bruers et al., Reference Bruers, Davis, Hojjat, Koskensilta, Lepeltier and Pearce2024). It has also been proposed that R-selected species could be genetically adapted to have fewer offspring (Johannsen, Reference Johannsen2020).

Proponents of an overriding focus on wild animal welfare recognize that it is not possible to responsibly engage in these sorts of systematic changes at this time. Feasibility, secondary effects, unknown risks, knowledge gaps, and technical limitations are strong reasons to be careful, deliberate and to move slowly when considering large-scale systemic interventions, and perhaps to take an incrementalist approach (Nussbaum, Reference Nussbaum2023). Nevertheless, ‘a massive shift of resources is morally required for the benefit of nonhuman animals…particularly, those living in the wild’ (Faria, Reference Faria2023, p. 159). A large part of this shift in resources involves research and technology development to increase feasibility and effectiveness of interventions. Proponents therefore support biotechnology investment, for example, and advocate for developing the field of welfare biology, focused on improving understanding of what makes wild animals’ lives go well or badly for them and what interventions might promote wild animal welfare (Ng, Reference Ng1995; Faria, Reference Faria2023; Browning & Veit, Reference Browning and Veit2023).

But the fact that systemic interventions and redesign are not imminent should not, in this view, be taken as a reason not to promote wild animal welfare now. Episodic and small-scale interventions to improve the lives of wild animals, including population management, vaccination and contraception programmes, supplementary feeding, rehabilitation and legal protections, are possible and already occur in some forms (Horta, Reference Horta, Burgat and Dardenne2023). These activities could be expanded, with a greater focus on laying the groundwork and gaining the knowledge needed for large-scale transformations.

Critiques of prioritizing wild animal welfare in ecosystem management

As advocacy for a focus on wild animal welfare in ecosystem management has developed, so too have critiques. Here we briefly review emerging conceptual, theoretical, empirical, perspectival and evaluative responses. The justifications for prioritizing wild animal welfare depend on various concepts and theories, many of which are contested. We do not advocate for or against any view; rather, we aim to analyse, develop and situate the rapidly growing discourse.

While it is widely recognized that sentient animals are owed some moral consideration, the strong impartiality embraced by many proponents of wild animal welfare prioritization is contested. Even with respect to interpersonal ethics, the fact that all people have equal worth and are owed moral consideration does not necessarily imply that strangers should be considered equally or in the same ways as family and friends. There are many relational and contextual accounts of what we owe one another that are alternatives to absolute impartiality (Hursthouse, Reference Hursthouse2001; Noddings, Reference Noddings2013). Applied to non-human animals, this would mean that people could have duties and responsibilities to domesticated and companion animals, as well as animals that they have directly interacted with, that they do not have to wild animals in general (Palmer, Reference Palmer2010; Donaldson & Kymlicka, Reference Donaldson and Kymlicka2011; Milburn, Reference Milburn2022). Perhaps, then, there are duties of beneficence to some animals with whom we have special relationships, but only duties of non-malevolence (or weak beneficence) to wild animals.

The conception of animal welfare embraced by advocates is also contested. Whilst it is now widely recognized that many non-human animals have mental lives, including the capacity for suffering and enjoyment, it does not follow that wild animal welfare should be primarily or exclusively concerned with these experiential aspects, or that they are as disconnected from species-typical behaviours and freedom from constraint as advocates propose (Rollin, Reference Rollin2016). Some accounts of animal welfare appeal to autonomy and dignity in ways that are not reducible to subjective experiences (Ortiz, Reference Ortiz2004). Moreover, the quality of an animal’s life may encompass aspects beyond the subjective experience or perspective. In assessments of the quality of human lives we often consider whether people lived well, not only whether they lived pleasantly (Foot, Reference Foot2001; Hursthouse, Reference Hursthouse2001; Aristotle, Reference Irwin2019). Relatedly, there’s a worry that this view involves problematic paternalism and a denial of animal agency, as it implies that people know best how wild animal lives should be lived, and can speak authoritatively about what wild animals want and desire (Vogel & Bendik-Keymer, Reference Vogel and Bendik-Keymer2024).

There are also theoretical critiques of the idea that wild animals should be recognized as having political standing as part of human communities. These maintain that wild animals are already considered in political processes, policies and laws in ways that do not involve their being fully political subjects. Moreover, if the political domain is about how we organize ourselves, and about taking responsibility for that organization, including how it affects the non-human world, then wild animals are not properly political subjects (Bendik-Keymer et al., Reference Bendik-Keymer, Maskit and Sandler2024). Donaldson & Kymlicka (Reference Donaldson and Kymlicka2011) propose a different way of thinking about this altogether, namely that wild animals occupy independent sovereign communities. In this view, humans have no political justification for entering those sovereign communities and reorganizing them in pursuit of better welfare because this would undermine their autonomy.

In addition to conceptual and theoretical critiques, there are questions about the empirical adequacy of the view. One major concern is whether the welfare of wild animals is as poor as advocates claim (Browning & Veit, Reference Browning and Veit2023). Likewise, critics highlight that, given the nature of ecological processes, a benefit to some animals will always be detrimental to others (e.g. competition, predation, scavenging). So even modest interventions, such as vaccination programmes, will not necessarily result in improved wild animal welfare overall. The same is true of approaches such as predator removal or population suppression. In complex ecological systems, where there are high levels of interdependence among populations, animal welfare gains for some individuals or populations will likely bring about simultaneous welfare losses for others. Delon & Purves (Reference Delon and Purves2018) argue that ‘the nature of ecosystems leaves us with no reason to predict that interventions would reduce, rather than exacerbate, suffering.’ Advocates respond by emphasizing that this is why systemic change is needed. However, this suggests that paradise engineering cannot really be accomplished incrementally, and it is difficult to see how an engineered system to maximize wild animal welfare could actually be a functioning ecological system; it would instead be akin to a large zoo that limits interspecific interactions among animals. Thus, another empirical critique is that advocates of managing for wild animal welfare, even though they recognize feasibility and knowledge limitations, nevertheless significantly underestimate the complexity, challenges, uncertainty, tractability and risks involved (Sandler, Reference Sandlerin press), particularly when trying to determine welfare outcomes into the distant future, which temporal impartiality demands.

Perspectival critiques concern the way in which the human–nature or human–wild animal relationship is understood. For example, proposals to engineer ecological systems and the animals that comprise them, for their own benefit, strike some as exhibiting a paternalist or even colonialist logic, whereby a small group of people (probably affluent, highly educated and from the Global North) claim to know what is best for others and to speak on their behalf. Moreover, the project involves embracing domination and humanization of the non-human world (Palmer, Reference Palmer2022). Many view this attitude as a contributory factor to the ecological crisis (White, Reference White1967). The idea that domination will be benevolent and rational is reminiscent of prior claims of wise use that have often resulted in high ecological, wildlife and social costs. These attitudes, particularly in combination with the epistemic and risk critiques above, suggest that paradise engineering is hubristic, lacking the humility that is required when working with complex biological, ecological and climatic systems (Sandler, Reference Sandlerin press).

Evaluative critiques concern the way in which animal welfare considerations override other values, particularly environmental, and eco-social or cultural values. Proponents of a focus on wild animal welfare argue against the value of biodiversity, spontaneity and evolution except in so far as they contribute to welfare. In their monistic view, individual welfare and flourishing, human and non-human, is all that matters. In contrast, advocates of pluralistic positions defend the view that many different things are valuable in many different ways. Environmental ethicists have been particularly adamant that there are numerous ways in which ecological systems are and should be valued, including in cultural, experiential, natural resource, historical and scientific ways, and that these cannot all be reduced to a single type of value, whether it is ecosystem services or animal welfare (Sandler, Reference Sandler2012). Thus, even if wild animal welfare matters, it may not be the only value that needs to be taken into account in ecosystem management, and managing as if it were would result in a massive depletion of other types of ecological goods and eco-social values.

Taking the empirical and evaluative concerns together seems to lead to a reductio ad absurdum of the wild animal welfare view. If wild animal welfare is so poor, it is not tractable to address it, and it has priority over other environmental values, then the implication seems to be that it would be best, so far as possible, to reduce the number of sentient wild animals to reduce overall suffering. Following this logic would appear to make the massive depletion of wild vertebrates in the past 50 years seem like a good thing from a moral standpoint.

Conclusion

We live in a time of re-evaluation of conservation concepts, philosophies and paradigms. Pervasive anthropogenic impacts, rapid climate change, novel technologies (e.g. artificial intelligence, biotechnology) and the scale of the extinction crisis have led many to revisit conservation goals, innovate conservation strategies (e.g. de-extinction, assisted colonization, rewilding) and challenge standard conservation norms, such as native species prioritization and taking a precautionary approach (Sandler, Reference Sandler2020, Reference Sandler2024, Reference Sandlerin press). There are new actors in the conservation landscape, such as well-funded, for-profit, biotechnology companies, and new ideas are being explored. One of those ideas is that ecosystem management should prioritize wild animal welfare, an idea that has found support from a network of researchers, activists and funders.

The aim of this paper is to explore the implications of the movement to prioritize wild animal welfare in ecosystem management, situate it in the history of concern for animals within conservation, and briefly review its core theoretical foundations, its ethical justifications, as well as emerging critiques. These are early days in the development of this discourse around wild animal suffering, and we hope to raise awareness of the challenges being posed to conservation values. We believe that these issues are likely to become a much more prominent component of the future of ecosystem management and conservation discourse.

Author contributions

Project conception, study design, research execution, writing: both authors.

Acknowledgements

We thank Kent Redford for suggesting this project; Martin Fisher for his guidance on orienting it for the Oryx audience; and Ava Pijanowski for her help preparing the text. This research was supported by the United States National Endowment for the Humanities, Award DOC-293796-23, The Ethics of Conservation Biotechnology: A Conceptual Engineering Approach.

Conflicts of interest

None.

Ethical standards

This research abided by the Oryx guidelines on ethical standards.

Data availability

Not applicable.

References

Aristotle (2019) Nicomachean Ethics, 3rd edition (trans. Irwin, T). Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, USA.Google Scholar
Bendik-Keymer, J. & Pedersen, S. (2024) Introducing geological wonder: Planetary thinking as a disruption of narcissism. Environmental Values, 33, 648664.10.1177/09632719241266276CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bendik-Keymer, J., Maskit, J & Sandler, R. (2024) The relevance of Steven Vogel’s work for environmental philosophy today. Environmental Ethics, 46, 353361.10.5840/enviroethics202446486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, J. (1789) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Clarendon Press, Oxford, UK.10.1093/oseo/instance.00077240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birch, J., Burn, C., Schnell, A., Browning, H. & Crump, A. (2021) Review of the Evidence of Sentience in Cephalopod Molluscs and Decapod Crustaceans. London School of Economics, London, UK.Google Scholar
Bradshaw, K. (2022) Wildlife as Property Owners. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, USA.Google Scholar
Broom, D.M. (2011) A History of Animal Welfare Science. Acta Biotheoretica, 59, 121137.10.1007/s10441-011-9123-3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Browning, H. (2020) The Natural Behaviour Debate: Two Conceptions of Animal Welfare. Journal of Applied Animal Welfare Science, 23, 325337.10.1080/10888705.2019.1672552CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Browning, H. & Birch, J. (2022) Animal sentience. Philosophy Compass, 17, e12822.10.1111/phc3.12822CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Browning, H. & Veit, W. (2023) Positive wild animal welfare. Biology and Philosophy, 38, 14.10.1007/s10539-023-09901-5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bruers, S., Davis, A.J., Hojjat, S., Koskensilta, A., Lepeltier, T. & Pearce, D. (2024) Nature without suffering: Herbivorisation of predator species for the compassionate stewardship of Earth’s ecosystems. Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research, 6, 175204.Google Scholar
Carson, R. (1962) Silent Spring. Houghton Mifflin, Boston, USA.Google Scholar
Centre for Effective Altruism (2024) Centre for Effective Altruism. centreforeffectivealtruism.org [accessed 13 November 2024].Google Scholar
Centre for Compassionate Conservation (2025) About the Centre for Compassionate Conservation 2024. University of Technology Sydney, New South Wales, Australia. uts.edu.au/about/td-school/td-research/centre-for-compassionate-conversation/about-us [accessed 18 February 2025].Google Scholar
Crowley, S.L., Hinchliffe, S. & McDonald, R.A. (2018) Killing squirrels: Exploring motivations and practices of lethal wildlife management. Environment and Planning E: Nature and Space, 1, 120143.Google Scholar
Dawkins, M. (2021) The Science of Animal Welfare: Understanding What Animals Want. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.10.1093/oso/9780198848981.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delon, N. & Purves, D. (2018) Wild animal suffering is intractable. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 31, 239260.10.1007/s10806-018-9722-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, S. & Kymlicka, K. (2011) Zoopolis. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.Google Scholar
Duncan, I.J.H. & Wood-Gush, D.G.M. (1971) Frustration and aggression in the domestic fowl. Animal Behaviour, 19, 500504.10.1016/S0003-3472(71)80104-5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Effective Altruism Foundation (2017) The relevance of wild animal suffering 2017. ea-foundation.org/blog/the-relevance-of-wild-animal-suffering-2 [accessed 13 November 2024].Google Scholar
Englefield, B., Candy, S., Starling, M. & McGreevy, P. (2019) The Demography and Practice of Australians Caring for Native Wildlife and the Psychological, Physical and Financial Effects of Rescue, Rehabilitation and Release of Wildlife on the Welfare of Carers. Animals, 9, 1127.10.3390/ani9121127CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Faria, C. & Paez, E. (2019) It’s Splitsville: why animal ethics and environmental ethics are incompatible. American Behavioral Scientist, 63, 10471060.10.1177/0002764219830467CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faria, C. (2023) Animal Ethics in the Wild. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK Google Scholar
Fleming, P.J.S. & Ballard, G. (2019) Yes, killing is sometimes essential for conservation. Australian Zoologist, 40, 512.10.7882/AZ.2018.037CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. (2001) Natural Goodness. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.10.1093/0198235089.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geist, V., Mahoney, S.P. & Organ, J.F. (2001) Why hunting has defined the North American model of wildlife conservation. Transactions of the North American Wildlife and Natural Resources Conference, 66, 175185.Google Scholar
Harrison, R. (1964) Animal Machines. Vincent Stuart Publishers LTD, London, UK.Google Scholar
Hayward, M.W., Callen, A., Allen, B.L., Ballard, G., Broekhuis, F., Bugir, C. et al. (2019) Deconstructing compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 33, 760768.10.1111/cobi.13366CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hill, T.E. (1983) Ideals of human excellence and preserving natural environments. Environmental Ethics, 5, 211224.10.5840/enviroethics19835327CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horta, O. (2017) Animal suffering in nature: the case for intervention. Environmental Ethics, 39, 261279.10.5840/enviroethics201739320CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horta, O. (2023) Wild animal suffering. In Animal Suffering: The Ethics and Politics of Animal Lives (eds Burgat, F. & Dardenne, E.), pp. 141160. Wiley-ISTE, London, UK.10.1002/9781394228935.ch8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horta, O. & Teran, D. (2023) Reducing wild animal suffering effectively: why impracticability and normative objections fail against the most promising ways of helping wild animals. Ethics, Policy & Environment, 26, 217230.10.1080/21550085.2023.2200726CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (2000) Ethics, Humans and Other Animals: An Introduction with Readings. Routledge, London, UK.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (2001) On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.10.1093/0199247994.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johannsen, K. (2020) Wild Animal Ethics. Routledge, New York, USA.10.4324/9780429296673CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, T. (2024) Taking natural harms seriously in compassionate conservation. Biological Conservation, 299, 110791.10.1016/j.biocon.2024.110791CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kianpour, C.K. & Paez, E. (2022) Red in tooth and claw no more: animal rights and the permissibility to redesign nature. Environmental Values, 31, 211231.10.3197/096327121X16081160834777CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, C. & Barron, A.B. (2016) Insects have the capacity for subjective experience. Animal Sentience, 9, 119.Google Scholar
Lambert, H., Elwin, A. & D’Cruze, N. (2022) Frog in the well: a review of the scientific literature for evidence of amphibian sentience. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 247, 105559.10.1016/j.applanim.2022.105559CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leopold, A. (1949) A Sand County Almanac. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.Google Scholar
Littin, K., Mellor, D., Warburton, B. & Eason, C. (2004) Animal welfare and ethical issues relevant to the humane control of vertebrate pests. New Zealand Veterinary Journal, 52, 110.10.1080/00480169.2004.36384CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manfredo, M.J., Teel, T.L. & Dietsch, A.M. (2016) Implications of human value shift and persistence for biodiversity conservation. Conservation Biology, 30, 287296.10.1111/cobi.12619CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Manfredo, M.J., Teel, T.L., Don Carlos, A.W., Sullivan, L., Bright, A.D., Dietsch, A.M., et al. (2020) The changing sociocultural context of wildlife conservation. Conservation Biology, 34, 15491559.10.1111/cobi.13493CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matthews, D. (2022) How effective altruism went from a niche movement to a billion-dollar force 2022. Vox, 8 August 2022. vox.com/future-perfect/2022/8/8/23150496/effective-altruism-sam-bankman-fried-dustin-moskovitz-billionaire-philanthropy-crytocurrency [accessed 13 November 2024].Google Scholar
McMahan, J. (2010) The Meat Eaters. New York Times, 19 September 2010. opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/09/19/the-meat-eaters [accessed 16 June 2025].Google Scholar
McMahan, J. (2015) The moral problem of predation. In Philosophy Comes to Dinner: Arguments About the Ethics of Eating (eds A. Chignell, Cuneo, T. & Halteman, M.C.), pp. 268294. Routledge, New York, USA.Google Scholar
Mellor, D.J., Beausoleil, N.J., Littlewood, K.E., McLean, A.N., McGreevy, P.D., Jones, B. et al. (2020) The 2020 Five Domains model: including human–animal interactions in assessments of animal welfare. Animals, 10, 1870.10.3390/ani10101870CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Milburn, J. (2022) Just Fodder: The Ethics of Feeding Animals. Queen’s University Press, McGill, Canada.10.1515/9780228013235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ng, YK. (1995) Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. Biology and Philosophy, 10, 255285.10.1007/BF00852469CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noddings, N. (2013) Caring: A Relational Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. University of California Press, Berkeley, California, USA.Google Scholar
Norton, B. (1991) Towards Unity Among Environmentalists. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2007) Frontiers of Justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, USA.10.2307/j.ctv1c7zftwCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2023) Justice for Animals. Simon and Schuster, New York, USA.Google Scholar
Ortiz, S.E.G. (2004) Beyond welfare: animal integrity, animal dignity, and genetic engineering. Ethics and the Environment, 9, 94120.10.2979/ETE.2004.9.1.94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C. (2010) Animal Ethics in Context. Columbia University Press, New York, USA.Google Scholar
Palmer, C. (2022) The value of wild nature: comments on Kyle Johannsen’s Wild Animal Ethics. Philosophia, 50, 853863.10.1007/s11406-021-00418-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmer, C., Fischer, B., Gamborg, C., Hampton, J. & Sandoe, S. (2023) Wildlife Ethics: The Ethics of Wildlife Management and Conservation. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, UK.10.1002/9781119611332CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plumwood, V. (1993) Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Routledge, New York, USA.Google Scholar
Ramp, D. & Bekoff, M. (2015) Compassion as a practical and evolved ethic for conservation. BioScience, 65, 323327.10.1093/biosci/biu223CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, T. (1983) The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press, Berkeley, California, USA.Google Scholar
Rodriguez, L. & Harris, K. (2023) Kevin Esvelt on cults that want to kill everyone, stealth vs wildfire pandemics, and how he felt inventing gene drives. 80,000 Hours, 2 October 2023. 80000hours.org/podcast/episodes/kevin-esvelt-stealth-wildfire-pandemics/#crispr-based-gene-drive-022318 [accessed 13 November 2024].Google Scholar
Rollin, B. (2016) A New Basis for Animal Ethics: Telos and Common Sense. University of Missouri Press, Columbia, Missouri, USA.Google Scholar
Rolston, H. (1988) Environmental Ethics: Duties To and Values In the Natural World. Temple University Press, Philadelphia, USA.Google Scholar
Sandler, R. (2012) The Ethics of Species: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.10.1017/CBO9781139151221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, R. (2020) The ethics of genetic engineering and gene drives in conservation. Conservation Biology, 34, 378385.10.1111/cobi.13407CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sandler, R. (2024) Conservation philosophy after the end of ‘nature’? Environmental Ethics, 46, 379400.10.5840/enviroethics2024123186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, R. (in press) In defense of deference. The Monist: An International Quarterly Journal of General Philosophical Inquiry, in press.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (1973) Animal Liberation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.10.1007/978-1-349-25176-6_1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soule, M. (1985) What is Conservation Biology? A new synthetic discipline addresses the dynamics and problems of perturbed species, communities, and ecosystems. BioScience, 35, 727734.Google Scholar
Taylor, P. (1986) Respect for Nature. Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, USA.Google Scholar
Tomasik, B. (2015) The importance of wild animal suffering. Relations: Beyond Anthropocentrism, 3, 133152.10.7358/rela-2015-002-tomaCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogel, S. & Bendik-Keymer, J. (2024) What do we want the environment to be? An interview with Steven Vogel on the metaphysics of practice. Environmental Ethics, 46, 363377.10.5840/enviroethics202446487CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallach, A.D., Bekoff, M., Batavia, C., Nelson, M.P. & Ramp, D. (2018) Summoning compassion to address the challenges of conservation. Conservation Biology, 32, 12551265.10.1111/cobi.13126CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wallach, A.D., Batavia, C., Bekoff, M., Alexander, S., Baker, L., Ben-Ami, D. et al. (2020) Recognizing animal personhood in compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 34, 10971106.10.1111/cobi.13494CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, L. (1967) The historical roots of our ecologic crisis. Science, 155, 12031207.10.1126/science.155.3767.1203CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed