Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-9xpg2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-09-21T13:38:27.858Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Naturalistic Neopragmatism and Conceptual Connections

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 September 2025

Abstract

Neopragmatists – some of whom might be called ‘global expressivists’ – reject metaphysics and take talk of concepts to be talk of the mastery of contingent linguistic practices that have been shaped by human nature. As a result, it may seem much harder for them to account for the sorts of necessary connections – whether conceptual or metaphysical – defended in so much of contemporary analytic philosophy. In some cases, this is right: the connections are really there, and neopragmatists will have to rise to the challenge of explaining them. But in other cases, it may turn out that the putative necessary connections are illusions that neopragmatist lenses can help one see through. In this paper, I try to reveal the workings behind one illusion and to rise to one challenge. In each case the point is a double one; to shed light on the first-order issue and to illustrate the virtues of neopragmatism as a general approach to philosophical problems. And there is a third point: that in some cases the philosophically interesting conclusion about a set of related concepts will only be that there are some ‘for the most part’ connections between them.

Information

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Robert, Adams, ‘Motive Utilitarianism’, The Journal of Philosophy 73:14 (1976), 467481.Google Scholar
Robert, Brandom, Making It Explicit (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
Robert, Brandom, ‘Explanatory vs. Expressive Deflationism about Truth’, in Shantz, R. (ed.), Current Issues in Theoretical Philosophy, Volume 1: What is Truth? (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2002), 103119.Google Scholar
James, Brown, ‘A Plea for Prudence’, Analysis 83:2 (2023), 394404.Google Scholar
Bukoski, Michael, ‘A Critique of Smith’s Constitutivism’, Ethics 127:1 (2016), 116146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudolf, Carnap, ‘Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4 (1950), 2040.Google Scholar
Stephen, Darwall, Welfare and Rational Care (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Dale, Dorsey, A Theory of Prudence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021).Google Scholar
Guy, Fletcher, Dear Prudence: The Nature and Normativity of Prudential Discourse (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021).Google Scholar
Joshua, Gert (ed.), Neopragmatism: Interventions in First-Order Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2023).Google Scholar
Robert, Kraut, ‘Varieties of Pragmatism’, Mind 99:394 (1990), .Google Scholar
Stephen, Laurence and Margolis, Eric, ‘Concepts and Conceptual Analysis’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67:2 (2003), 253282.Google Scholar
John, Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, Sher, G. (ed.), (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002 [1861]).Google Scholar
Cheryl, Misak, The American Pragmatists (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).Google Scholar
Thomas, Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1970).Google Scholar
Thomas, Nagel, ‘Moral Luck’, in his Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979). 2438.Google Scholar
Derek, Parfit, On What Matters, Volume 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Huw, Price, ‘Truth as Convenient Friction’, The Journal of Philosophy 100:4 (2003), 167190.Google Scholar
Huw, Price, Expressivism, Pragmatism and Representationalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013).Google Scholar
Huw, Price, ‘Global Expressivism and Alethic Pluralism’, Synthese 200:386 (2022). 55pp.Google Scholar
Huw, Price, ‘Gibbard on Quasi–realism and Global Expressivism’, Topoi 42 (2023), 683697.Google Scholar
Huw, Price, Facts and the Function of Truth: New Expanded Edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).Google Scholar
Richard, Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).Google Scholar
Richard, Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Richard, Rorty, ‘Is Truth a Goal of Inquiry? Donald Davidson versus Crispin Wright’, in his Truth and Progress (Philosophical Papers : Volume 3) (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 1941.Google Scholar
Jonathan, Schaffer, ‘Laws for Metaphysical Explanation’, Philosophical Issues 27 (2017), .Google Scholar
Samuel, Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Ted, Sider, Writing the Book of the World (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Henry, Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981 [1907]).Google Scholar
Smith, Michael. 2013. ‘A Constitutivist Theory of Reasons: Its Promise and Parts’, Law, Ethics and Philosophy 1, 930.Google Scholar
Amie, Thomasson, Ontology Made Easy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015).Google Scholar
Amie, Thomasson, ‘What Can Global Pragmatists say About Ordinary Objects?’ in Cumpa, J. and Brewer, B. (eds.), The Nature of Ordinary Objects (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2019). 235259.Google Scholar
Robert, Westbrook, Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2005).Google Scholar
Ludwig, Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Anscombe, G.E.M. (trans). (New York: Macmillan, 1953).Google Scholar