Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-09T14:11:03.279Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Legal Proof Should Be Justified Belief of Guilt

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 January 2025

Mario Günther*
Affiliation:
Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians University, Munich, Germany
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article argues that legal proof should be tantamount to justified belief of guilt. A defendant should be found guilty just in case it is justified to believe that the defendant is guilty. My notion of justified belief implies a threshold view on which justified belief requires high credence, but mere statistical evidence does not give rise to justified belief.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

I. Introduction

Imagine you are a fact-finder in a court of law. A prisoner is accused of having murdered a prison guard. You have to find the accused guilty or innocent. Your decision is governed by a standard of proof and the available and admissible evidence. Out of fairness, you seek truth: you aim to establish the facts as you believe they are. So you find the prisoner guilty just in case you believe he is guilty based on the available and admissible evidence.

Your beliefs follow certain norms. Primarily, your beliefs aim at truth. You believe a proposition only if you believe it to be true. Inconsistent propositions cannot be true. Hence, you do not believe any inconsistencies. If you believe that a proposition is true, you do not believe that its negation is true as well. As you strive for true beliefs and truth is closed under logical consequence, you believe what logically follows from your beliefs. In sum, your beliefs are rational: consistent and deductively closed. Indeed, your beliefs are even justified—they are rational and sufficiently supported by the admissible evidence available to you. Or so we assume.

In this article, I argue for the thesis that legal proof should be tantamount to justified belief of guilt. A defendant should be found guilty just in case a fact-finder is justified in believing that the defendant is guilty.Footnote 1 This thesis has the ring of truth, whereas its negations do not. “The defendant should be found guilty, but the fact-finder is not justified in believing that he is” sounds just as odd as “The defendant should not be found guilty even though the fact-finder is justified in believing that he is.”

I have put forth the thesis and made clear that I assume the perspective of an ideal truth-seeker. It remains to explain how the beliefs of a fact-finder can be justified by the available and admissible evidence. I do so by improving upon the idea of justified belief as high enough credence in light of the evidence. I show that the notion of justified belief solves the problem posed by statistical evidence—evidence that supports a high credence but no justified belief. The upshot is a rather unifying view of legal proof in terms of evidence-based credence.Footnote 2

II. The Simple Threshold View

When is it justified to have a belief? On one view, you are justified in believing a proposition if and only if (iff) you have a high enough credence in that proposition given your total evidence. And your credence is high enough iff it exceeds a certain threshold.Footnote 3 On this simple threshold view, your credences or “degrees of belief” are rational: they satisfy the Kolmogorov axioms of probability and the ratio definition of conditional probability.

The simple threshold view translates your evidence-based credences into what it deems justified beliefs. When your credence in a proposition $ A $ , given your whole body of evidence, surpasses the threshold, your belief in $ A $ is justified. Your credences, in turn, are justified by the total evidence you received, which is summarized by the strongest proposition of which you are now certain. To be clear, your credences at time t are represented by a probability function conditionalized on the total evidence you received up to time t. Typically, your total evidence leads to non-extreme credences: subjective probabilities strictly in-between 0 and 1. You would have only few justified beliefs if you were to set the threshold for them to 1—too few.

The exact threshold for justified belief, if there is any, is of course subject to debate. But there is a natural lower bound: justified belief in a proposition requires a credence in that proposition strictly above $ 1/2 $ . Suppose for reductio that the threshold were equal to $ 1/2 $ or less. Then you could be justified in believing a proposition $ A $ and its negation ¬ $ {A} $ to be true at the same time. But you are never justified in believing such a contradiction to be true. The resulting inconsistent belief state is irrational and so unjustified.

The simple threshold view can explain how your beliefs are supported by your evidence. Imagine you look out of the window and you see it raining. Based on this evidence, your credence in rain goes up so that it seems to be high enough for a justified belief in rain. Conversely, if you are justified in believing that it rains, your credence in rain must be high enough in some sense. The view is not too implausible. But there are issues.

A—if not “the”—problem for the simple threshold view is posed by statistical evidence, which supports a high credence but no justified belief. For example, suppose there are 100 prisoners in a yard under the supervision of a guard. Ninety-nine of them join a pre-planned attack to kill the guard. One prisoner clearly refrains, standing alone in a corner. We know this from a reliable video recording. However, the video footage does not allow us to discern the individual prisoners—they all wear the same uniforms and the quality is not good enough to identify faces or other characteristics. There is no other evidence. Each prisoner is tried in a court of law.Footnote 4

Are you justified in believing that the prisoner standing trial is guilty? On the simple threshold view, you are because your credence in his guilt is high enough. If legal proof should be tantamount to high enough credence of guilt, this would also mean that we should find the prisoner guilty. But many are not willing to endorse this consequence.Footnote 5 Lara Buchak, for example, says:

We never think it justified to blame an individual on the basis of merely statistical evidence … And this is best explained by the fact that we need a belief in someone’s guilt to blame her, and that merely statistical evidence cannot give rise to a belief in these cases.Footnote 6

On this, I agree with Buchak. However, Buchak also argues that justified belief cannot be reduced to credence. And so “threshold views of the relationship between licensed court verdicts and rational credence are false.” I disagree. In what follows, I offer a threshold view on which justified belief requires high credence, but purely statistical evidence does not give rise to justified belief.

III. A Threshold View of Justified Belief

I develop now the notion of justified belief in terms of credence. As on the simple threshold view, your credences are determined by your total evidence. This means you consider all the pieces of evidence you received. If you are a fact-finder, you exclude the inadmissible pieces of evidence. But there is more. Your total evidence also determines the possibilities you consider overall. You consider all and only those possibilities your credences assign a definite positive probability value. The total evidence you received partitions the underlying set $ W $ of all logical possibilities into possibilities $ {\pi}_i $ that are assigned a positive credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\left\{{\pi}_i\right\}\right)>0 $ . Such a possibility is a maximally specific way things might be with respect to the partition Π induced by your total evidence. A partition Π on $ W $ is a set of pairwise disjoint and non-empty subsets $ {\pi}_i $ of $ W $ so that $ \cup {\pi}_i=W $ . If you are a fact-finder, your initial partition includes the possibilities that the defendant is guilty and innocent.

Propositions are understood relative to a partition. Any subset of a partition Π is a proposition. A proposition $ A\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ is consistent iff $ A\ne \varnothing $ . A proposition $ A $ is consistent with a proposition $ B $ iff $ A\hskip0.3em \cap \hskip0.3em B\ne \varnothing $ . $ A $ entails $ B $ iff $ A\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em B $ . The negation ¬ $ {A} $ of a proposition is given by its complement $ \Pi \hskip0.3em \backslash \hskip0.3em A $ , the conjunction $ A\hskip0.3em \wedge \hskip0.3em B $ of two propositions by their intersection $ A\hskip0.3em \cap \hskip0.3em B $ , and the disjunction $ A\hskip0.3em \vee \hskip0.3em B $ by their union $ A\hskip0.3em \cup \hskip0.3em B $ . The probability distribution $ {P}_{\Pi} $ is defined for all and only subsets of $ \Pi $ .

We are now in a position to define justified belief in terms of credence:

You are justified to believe a proposition $ A\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ iff $ {B}_{\theta}\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em A $ , where $ {B}_{\theta } $ is chosen among the propositions you assign a high credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right) $ and you expect $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not.

The conjunct “you expect $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not” means you consider no relevant proposition that would lower your credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right) $ to $ 1/2 $ or below. You consider a proposition $ B $ to be relevant to $ {B}_{\theta } $ iff your credence in it is non-zero and it is consistent with $ {B}_{\theta } $ . In symbols, you consider a proposition $ B\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ to be relevant to $ {B}_{\theta}\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ iff $ {P}_{\Pi}(B)>0 $ and $ {B}_{\theta}\hskip0.3em \cap \hskip0.3em B\ne \varnothing $ . In sum, you expect $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not iff your conditional credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta }|B\right)>1/2 $ for any proposition $ B\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ you consider relevant. Equivalently, you expect $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not iff you consider no relevant proposition $ B\hskip0.3em \subseteq \hskip0.3em \Pi $ which would lower your credence $ {P}_{\Pi}({B}_{\theta }|B) $ to $ 1/2 $ or below.Footnote 7

My notion of justified belief is synchronic: you are justified in believing a proposition at time t iff you have a high credence in it at t and you expect it to remain more likely than not at t. In what follows, the reference to a point in time is left implicit.

Let us revisit the prisoners example. Your total evidence is that 99 out of 100 prisoners killed a prison guard. Each of the 100 prisoners may be innocent and you have no reason to believe that any one is more or less likely to be guilty than any of the others. All the 99:1 statistic says is that there are 100 equiprobable possibilities that each prisoner is innocent and all the others are guilty. So your total evidence assigns to only 100 possibilities a definite positive probability value, and so partitions the underlying set of possibilities into exactly 100. Let $ {\pi}_i $ be the possibility where prisoner i ( $ 1\le i\le 100 $ ) is innocent and all the other prisoners are guilty. Your total evidence makes you consider the partition $ \Pi =\left\{{\pi}_1,\dots, {\pi}_{100}\right\} $ of mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive possibilities. Moreover, you assign to each possibility the same definite credence: $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\left\{{\pi}_1\right\}\right)=\dots ={P}_{\Pi}\left(\left\{{\pi}_{100}\right\}\right)=1/100 $ .

Let us name the prisoner standing trial “prisoner 1.” Are you justified to believe that prisoner 1 is guilty? Well, your credence in the guilt of prisoner 1 is high: $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_1\right\}\right)=99/100 $ . However, you do not expect any non-empty $ {B}_{\theta}\subseteq \Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_1\right\} $ to remain more likely than not:

$$ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta }|\left\{{\pi}_1,b\right\}\right)=\frac{P\left(\left\{b\right\}\right)}{P\left(\left\{{\pi}_1,b\right\}\right)}=1/2\hskip0.62em \mathrm{for}\hskip0.5em \mathrm{any}\hskip0.52em b\in {B}_{\theta }. $$

For illustration, let $ {B}_{\theta }=\Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_1\right\} $ . You assign the proposition that prisoner 1 or prisoner 2 is innocent a positive credence and the proposition is consistent with the proposition that prisoner 1 is guilty. Hence, you consider the proposition relevant. And your credence that prisoner 1 is guilty given that prisoner 1 or prisoner 2 is innocent does not strictly exceed $ 1/2 $ :

$$ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_1\right\}|\left\{{\pi}_1,{\pi}_2\right\}\right)=\frac{P\left(\left\{{\pi}_2\right\}\right)}{P\left(\left\{{\pi}_1,{\pi}_2\right\}\right)}=1/2. $$

This means you do not expect $ \Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_1\right\} $ to remain more likely than not. A similar argument applies to each prisoner. Hence, you are not justified in believing of any prisoner that he is guilty—even though your respective credence is very high. My notion of justified belief solves this paradigmatic example of statistical evidence.

My notion can also deliver justified belief where appropriate. To see this, consider a modification of the prisoners example. There is no video recording, but the prison director walks by. She then testifies about prisoner 1: “I saw him killing the guard!” Let’s suppose you think that the director is very reliable but not perfectly so: she raises your credence that prisoner 1 is guilty to $ 99/100 $ .

Your total evidence is the prison director’s eyewitness testimony “I saw prisoner 1 killing the guard.” This testimony is only about prisoner 1; it does not say anything about another prisoner. It does not answer at all the question of how likely it is that prisoner 2 is guilty. As you deem the prison director not perfectly reliable, her testimony makes you assign a definite positive credence to exactly two possibilities: the testimony is true and so prisoner 1 killed the guard, or else the testimony is false and the prisoner is innocent. Indeed, all the testimony bears on is the question whether or not prisoner 1 is guilty of having killed the guard. So your total evidence makes you consider the partition $ \Pi '=\left\{\pi {'}_1,\pi {'}_2\right\} $ , where $ \pi {'}_1 $ is the possibility that prisoner 1 is innocent and $ \pi {'}_2 $ the possibility that prisoner 1 is guilty.

Are you justified in believing that prisoner 1 is guilty based on the eyewitness evidence? Well, your credence in the guilt of prisoner 1 is high: $ {P}_{\Pi '}\left(\Pi '\backslash \left\{\pi {'}_1\right\}\right)=99/100 $ . And you expect it to remain high. There are only three possibilities. $ \left\{\pi {'}_1\right\} $ is inconsistent with $ \Pi '\backslash \left\{\pi {'}_1\right\} $ and so irrelevant; $ {P}_{\Pi '}\Big(\left\{\pi {'}_2\right\}|\left(\left\{\pi {'}_2\right\}\right)=1 $ ; and $ {P}_{\Pi '}\left(\left\{\pi {'}_2\right\}|\Pi '\right)=99/100 $ . By choosing $ {B}_{\theta }=\Pi '\backslash \left\{\pi {'}_1\right\}, $ you are justified to believe that prisoner 1 is guilty.

We have seen that the different pieces of evidence in the prisoners example and the director example, respectively, determine the same credence in the guilt of prisoner 1. And yet my threshold view says that there is justified belief in his guilt in the former but not in the latter example. The reason is that the different pieces of evidence give rise to different partitions of the underlying possibilities. The 99:1 statistic induces a uniform credence function expressing a symmetry between the prisoners: each prisoner is just as likely as any other to be innocent. I suggest this symmetry is why it feels so random to convict one of the prisoners based on statistical evidence alone: looking at the probability values, it could likewise have been any other prisoner.Footnote 8

The director’s eyewitness testimony, by contrast, biases the fact-finder’s credences towards prisoner 1 being guilty. It induces an uneven credence function expressing that the eyewitness evidence supports the guilt possibility much more than the innocence possibility. The uneven credence over the two-cell partition—prisoner 1 killed the guard, or else he did not—gives a rather strong indication of what to believe about prisoner 1. The eyewitness evidence induces no air of randomness: the two possibilities are far from being equally likely. From the vantage point of my notion of justified belief, the distinction between the 99:1 statistic and the eyewitness testimony hints at a general notion of statistical evidence.

IV. Statistical Evidence

I have said that statistical evidence supports a high credence but no justified belief.Footnote 9 This common characterization is directly derived from the prisoners example, where the 99:1 statistic supports a high credence but no justified belief. Indeed, the term “statistical evidence” is usually characterized only by pointing to examples.Footnote 10 Enoch and Spectre make this explicit:

When we—following the literature—speak of statistical evidence, we think of examples such as Blue Bus [or the prisoners example], and the phenomenon it is an example of. This is the phenomenon sometimes called base-rate evidence, sometimes market-share evidence, or sometimes naked statistical evidence … How do we, then, define statistical evidence? We don’t.Footnote 11

I believe lacking a definition of statistical evidence is a problem. As long as we don’t know what pieces of evidence are statistical, we simply cannot answer the question of whether or not statistical evidence may give rise to justified belief—on my notion or another. We need a general definition of “statistical evidence” in order to know whether my notion of justified belief solved the problem posed by it.

My notion of justified belief suggests the following definition of statistical evidence. A piece of evidence is purely statistical iff it would assign a uniform probability distribution over the partition it induces if it were the only piece of evidence received. So defined, a piece of purely statistical evidence alone may support a high credence but never gives rise to justified belief. The problem posed by statistical evidence for the simple threshold view is solved by my notion of justified belief on the suggested definition. Furthermore, we may say that your total evidence is purely statistical iff it assigns uniform credences over the partition it induces. Non-statistical total evidence assigns non-uniform credences over the induced partition, and so may give rise to justified belief. The degree to which a piece of evidence (or the total evidence) is statistical may be measured by how much it deviates from the uniform distribution. The exact measure is left for future work.

In the literature, statistical evidence is usually contrasted with “individual evidence.”Footnote 12 A paradigm example of individual evidence is eyewitness testimony. Indeed, the prison director’s testimony is non-statistical (to a high degree) and induces justified belief. Based on the testimony alone, you expect the prisoner’s guilt to remain more likely than not. My statistical/non-statistical distinction (or continuum) accounts for the intuitive dichotomy between “statistical” and “individual” evidence in our two examples.

Many statistics are not statistical evidence on my definition. This sounds paradoxical but it is not. All statistics which, if they were the sole piece of evidence, would assign a non-uniform probability distribution over the induced partition are non-statistical (to some degree). And any sufficiently uneven distribution can give rise to justified belief depending on the induced partition and the specific probability values. An uneven distribution based on a statistic may well give rise to justified belief.

Base rates, by contrast, are statistical evidence. A base rate is a relative frequency—a proportion of individuals in a population who have a certain feature. A base rate without any further evidence induces a uniform distribution over a fixed number of possibilities. My definition, therefore, can explain why “a base rate unaccompanied by other evidence” is purely statistical evidence.Footnote 13 But note that my definition counts any piece of evidence inducing a uniform distribution “purely statistical”—not only base rates.

In my framework, all evidence is probabilistic. Each piece of evidence—be it statistical or not—leads to some credence distribution. Pieces of statistical evidence may still help give rise to justified belief when combined with other pieces of evidence. So “the” law should have no aversion to statistics in general, let alone probabilistic evidence.Footnote 14 The point is merely that a piece of purely statistical evidence alone cannot give rise to justified belief. And neither does purely statistical total evidence.

V. Rational Belief States

One might wonder, “why am I not justified in believing that prisoner 1 is guilty in the prisoners example? After all, my credence in his guilt is very high. Why is this not sufficient for justified belief of guilt?” This objection sides with the intuition expressed in the simple threshold view. My answer is that you have no justified belief in his guilt because your belief state would be irrational. Let me explain.

We have assumed that your beliefs are rational: consistent and deductively closed. To be more precise, we say your state of belief is consistent iff the strongest proposition $ {B}_{\theta } $ you believe—the conjunction of all the propositions you believe—is non-empty. We say your state of full belief is deductively closed iff (1) you believe the proposition $ B $ if you believe $ A $ and $ A $ entails $ B $ , and (2) you believe $ A\hskip0.3em \wedge \hskip0.3em B $ if you believe $ A $ and you believe B. Hence, you believe a proposition $ A $ iff your strongest belief $ {B}_{\theta } $ is consistent and entails $ {A} $ .

We show now that your beliefs in the prisoners example cannot be rational if you adhere to the simple threshold view. If so, you are justified in believing that one prisoner is innocent because your credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\Pi \right)=1 $ is maximal. At the same time, you are justified in believing of each prisoner that he is guilty because your credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\Pi \backslash \left\{{\pi}_i\right\}\right)=99/100 $ is high enough ( $ 1\le i\le 100 $ ). If your justified beliefs were closed under conjunction, you would also be justified in believing that all prisoners are guilty:

$$ \left(\Pi \backslash {\pi}_1\right)\hskip0.3em \cap \hskip0.3em \left(\Pi \backslash {\pi}_2\right)\hskip0.3em \cap \dots \cap \hskip0.3em \left(\Pi \backslash {\pi}_{100}\right)=\varnothing . $$

But you should never be justified in believing the contradiction that all prisoners are guilty and one is innocent. Indeed, the “simple threshold you” is not justified in believing that all prisoners are guilty because your credence $ P\left(\varnothing \right) $ in that proposition is minimal. Your “justified” beliefs are rather not closed under conjunction and so they are not deductively closed. The simple threshold view cannot satisfy the two standard rationality norms on justified belief.

Consequently, a simple threshold believer with non-maximal threshold is not guaranteed to have a rational state of belief: there is no strongest but consistent belief that entails all her other beliefs. This is a cost. To see that, imagine you are found guilty but the fact-finder’s “justified” beliefs are inconsistent. Surely you have a reason to contest the verdict. For one, the fact-finder believes everything, in particular that you are innocent. Moreover, imagine there are only three elements to be proven in court for a finding of guilt. The fact-finder is well justified in believing each element $ A $ , $ B $ , and $ C $ in isolation. However, the fact-finder’s beliefs are not closed under conjunction. So it could be that they are not justified in believing all elements $ A\wedge B\wedge C $ . This is indeed a possibility on the simple threshold view. Should the defendant then be found guilty? If so, the simple threshold view of legal proof is false. If not, what else is required for a justified finding of guilt besides the justified beliefs in each element? And how should the verdict of not guilty be explained considering the justified beliefs in $ A $ , $ B $ , and $ C $ ? To give up deductive closure seems to lead to more questions than answers.

Unlike the simple threshold view, my threshold view guarantees that you have a rational belief state. There is always a consistent and deductively closed belief state represented by the strongest non-empty proposition $ {B}_{\theta } $ you are justified in believing. Your credence $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right) $ is typically non-maximal. In the prisoners example, however, you are not justified in believing of a particular prisoner that he is guilty even though your credence in his guilt is very high. For then you would be justified in believing of each prisoner that he is guilty due to the symmetry of the example. But then, as your justified beliefs are deductively closed, you would believe that all prisoners are guilty and that one is innocent. Fortunately, you are rational enough not to believe such a contradiction. All you are justified in believing is that one prisoner is innocent and the other 99 are guilty—you just don’t know which one. Your rational belief state is $ {B}_{\theta }=\Pi $ , where $ \Pi $ is both the partition induced by your total evidence and the strongest proposition of which you are certain. Assuming your total evidence is non-empty, you are at the very least justified in believing your total evidence—and more generally any proposition to which you assign maximal credence.

We can assume that a notion of justified belief that guarantees rationality is better than one that doesn’t. This suggests that the rationality of our belief states explains the intuition that belief is not justified in the prisoners example—the unease to say yes that is felt by many when asked whether they believe the prisoner is guilty. There is no such unease in the director’s example. And no wonder. In this example, the consistency, deductive closure, and evidential support of your beliefs are not in any tension: you have a high enough credence in his guilt and expect it to remain more likely than not.

VI. Thresholds and Legal Proof

My notion of justified belief entails a threshold view. Your state of justified belief is represented by the “strongest” non-empty proposition $ {B}_{\theta } $ you are justified in believing. Hence, you are justified in believing a proposition $ A\subseteq \Pi $ iff $ {B}_{\theta}\subseteq A $ . $ {B}_{\theta}\subseteq \Pi $ is then the smallest set of possibilities of which you have a high enough credence and you expect it to remain more likely than not. As $ {B}_{\theta } $ is non-empty, it is consistent with the partition Π induced by your total evidence such that $ {P}_{\Pi}\left(\Pi \right)=1 $ . As your $ {P}_{\Pi}({B}_{\theta }|\Pi ) $ must exceed $ 1/2 $ , so does $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right) $ . And any superset of $ {B}_{\theta } $ has a credence that is at least as high. This means you are justified in believing a proposition $ A\subseteq \Pi $ iff $ {P}_{\Pi}(A)\ge {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right) $ .Footnote 15 Your (variable) threshold for justified belief is your (current) credence in the strongest proposition you are justified in believing.

I propose that a legal standard of proof should be tantamount to justified belief of guilt relative to a certain credence threshold. Murder is a matter of criminal law. A criminal conviction requires the prosecution to prove the defendant’s guilt “beyond a reasonable doubt.” This means the admissible evidence presented in court must be enough to “remove any reasonable doubt in the mind of the fact-finder that the accused is guilty of the crime with which they are charged.” What the phrase is supposed to mean, however, is less clear. It can be explained as follows: proof beyond a reasonable doubt should be tantamount to justified belief in a criminal trial. A defendant’s guilt should be proven beyond a reasonable doubt iff your justified beliefs $ {B}_{\theta } $ entail his guilt. You have a reasonable doubt if you consider a proposition to be relevant which would lower your credence in $ {B}_{\theta } $ to $ 1/2 $ or below. If you consider a set of possibilities consistent with your beliefs that would make the defendant’s innocence more likely than not, you have a reasonable doubt. If so, your belief in guilt is not justified.Footnote 16

Let us turn to the long-anticipated question: what credence is high enough for justified belief? The answer is that your credence should exceed a threshold that depends on your value assessments or “stakes.” You are fair in that you consider how valuable the possible outcomes of your verdict are. The argument rests on orthodox decision theory, where utility is a proxy for value. The theory says we should maximize expected utility. In this paradigm, a defendant should be found guilty iff finding him guilty has greater expected utility than finding him innocent.Footnote 17 The legal decision problem can be summed up as follows:

Your available options are finding him guilty or innocent. Let’s denote your credence that the prisoner is guilty by P(G), and so your credence that he is innocent by 1 − P(G). Each option—together with the prisoner’s actual guilt or innocence—determines an outcome: a true finding of guilt (TG), a false finding of guilt (FG), a false finding of innocence (FI), and a true finding of innocence (TI). Your utility function U assigns each outcome a value. According to the principle of maximizing expected utility, you should find the prisoner guilty iff

$$ U(TG)\cdotp P(G)+U(FG)\cdotp \left(1-P(G)\right)\ge U(FI)\cdotp P(G)+U(TI)\cdotp \left(1-P(G)\right). $$

The inequality is equivalent to

$$ P(G)\ge \frac{U(TI)-U(FG)\;}{U(TG)-U(FG)+U(TI)-U(FI)}=\theta . $$

Standard decision theory recommends finding guilty just in case your credence of guilt meets the threshold obtained from the utility values you assign to the outcomes. We borrow the threshold $ \theta $ to choose among the sets $ {B}_{\theta } $ you expect to remain more likely than not: pick the least probable $ {B}_{\theta } $ such that $ {P}_{\Pi}\left({B}_{\theta}\right)\ge \theta . $

Plausibly, you neither disvalue a true finding of guilt nor a true finding of innocence. Let’s say the cost of true findings is zero: $ U(TG)=U(TI)=0 $ . Under this assumption, we obtain

$$ P(G)\ge \frac{-U(FG)}{-U(FG)-U(FI)}. $$

Furthermore, let’s say you disvalue falsely finding the prisoner guilty much more than falsely finding him innocent. Blackstone thought “the law holds that it is better that ten guilty persons escape than that one innocent suffer.”Footnote 18 Assuming you deem a decision-theoretic version of the Blackstone ratio to be true of the prisoners example, you think a false finding of guilt is ten times worse than a false finding of innocence:

$$ U(FG)=-10\hskip4.00pt \mathrm{a}\mathrm{n}\mathrm{d}\hskip2pt U(FI)=-1. $$

Your credence threshold for justified belief is then $ 10/11 $ , or approximately 0.91. You deem a credence above this threshold to be high enough for justified belief in the prisoner’s example. This is how we use orthodox decision theory to obtain a threshold for your “high enough” credence.

To be clear, we propose a justified belief account of legal proof, not one that maximizes expected utility. And we do not aim to reconcile the two approaches. Indeed, you think finding prisoner 1 guilty has greater expected utility than finding him innocent in the prisoners example. Yet you are not justified in believing that prisoner 1 is guilty—at least on my notion of justified belief. Rational truth-seekers and expected utility maximizers may come apart.Footnote 19 The maximizers achieve a much higher accuracy than our truth-seeker in the prisoners example: 99 correct verdicts and only one incorrect one. But they cannot justify their verdicts in terms of full belief without further ado. Perhaps they could do so by adopting the simple threshold view. But there is some tension. Their value assessments in certain cases may be as follows: finding guilty has greatest expected utility but the credence threshold for finding guilty, and so for justified belief in guilt, is below $ 1/2 $ . As I explained above, such a simple credence threshold leads to “justified” beliefs in contradictions. Our rational truth-seeker does not maximize expected utility and is not prepared to sacrifice the rationality of belief for a gain in accuracy.

I leave a thorough comparison of my justified belief account of legal proof to one of maximizing expected utility for future work. There, I will discuss an avenue for reconciling the two approaches to a large extent, namely by investigating what value assessments are appropriate in what legal cases. For now, I merely use decision theory to borrow a credence threshold for justified belief. And I can do this without further problem: if the threshold imported from decision theory happens to be exactly $ 1/2 $ or below, your threshold is just above $ 1/2 $ —you must still expect your justified beliefs $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not.

My account of legal proof is unifying. Evidential standards other than beyond a reasonable doubt just require a less-high credence of guilt. The reason seems to be this: the difference between disvaluing a false finding of guilt and a false finding of innocence diminishes in these cases, compared with the “high stakes” cases like murder.

The evidential standard of civil law is known as “preponderance of the evidence” and is typically interpreted thus: a plaintiff’s claim counts as proven in court just in case the claim is established to be more likely than not. In a civil trial, you should have no preference for either a finding for the plaintiff or a finding for the defendant. This means in our framework that a false finding of liability and a false finding of innocence should be equally costly. Together with the above assumption that the cost of true findings is zero, the borrowed threshold for finding liable should then be exactly $ 1/2 $ . A defendant’s liability should be established by preponderance of the evidence iff the fact-finder is justified in believing that the defendant is liable. And this is the case whenever $ {B}_{\theta } $ entails the defendant’s liability and they expect $ {B}_{\theta } $ to remain more likely than not. This solves the “blue bus” case—a case of civil law that is structurally similar to the prisoners exampleFootnote 20—and other structurally similar cases such as the “paradox of the gatecrasher.”Footnote 21 In sum, my account of legal proof solves the “proof paradoxes.”Footnote 22

VII. Conclusion

I have argued that legal proof should be tantamount to justified belief of guilt. A fact-finder should find a defendant guilty just in case they are justified in believing that the defendant is guilty. Pace Buchak, my notion of justified belief implies a probabilistic threshold view that solves the problem posed by statistical evidence. And unlike other accounts, mine need not impose any further condition on legal proof but justified belief.Footnote 23 On my view, proof beyond a reasonable doubt should be justified belief in a criminal trial. And proof by preponderance of the evidence should be justified belief in a civil trial.

My threshold view improves upon the simple threshold view. The latter says you are justified in believing that a defendant is guilty just in case your credence in his guilt is high enough based on the available and admissible evidence. My threshold view adds that your strongest justified belief should entail guilt and you should expect your strongest justified belief to remain more likely than not. Both views admit the fact that you—our truth-seeking fact-finder—find yourself in a position where both your beliefs and credences should be rational. You must make a binary decision—to find guilty or not—based on your available and admissible evidence, which induces almost always non-extreme credences of guilt. You should therefore have a rational procedure to translate your evidence-based credences into a final verdict. The two threshold views can both serve as such a procedure: find guilty just in case you are justified in believing that the defendant is guilty. But only ours guarantees that your justified beliefs are rational. And only ours discerns statistical from non-statistical evidence.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Hannes Leitgeb, Armin Engländer, Michael Blome-Tillmann, Jennifer Lackey, Richard Bradley, Katie Steele, Alan Hájek, Anna Mahtani, Anjan Chrakavartty, Jan Sprenger, Caterina Sisti, Atoosa Kasirzadeh, Lewis Ross, Somayeh Tohidi, Nathan Lauffer, Martin Smith, Philip Ebert, Rafal Urbaniak, Antony Duff, Sandra Marshall, Marcello Di Bello, Kevin Dorst, Minkyung Wang, Ronald Allen, Anne Ruth Mackor, and two anonymous referees for very helpful comments. I am grateful for the opportunity to have presented parts of this work at the Workshop on Theories of Legal Proof at the Catholic Academy in Bavaria, the Center for Advanced Studies and the Research Seminar of Action and Decision Theory both of LMU Munich, the Cologne Center for Contemporary Epistemology and the Kantian Tradition of the University of Cologne, the Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association in 2023, the 11th International Congress of the Society of Analytic Philosophy at the Humboldt University Berlin, the 96th Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association at the University of St. Andrews, the Philosophy of Science Conference at the Inter-University Center Dubrovnik, and the Center for Logic, Language, and Cognition of the University of Turin. The publication was supported by a Junior Residency in the Center for Advanced Studies and LMUexcellent, funded by the Federal Ministry of Education and Research (BMBF) and the Free State of Bavaria under the Excellence Strategy of the Federal Government and the Länder.

References

1 In the law, guilt is usually understood to imply an actus reus—or objective element of a crime—and a mens rea—or criminal intent of a crime. For this article, I put the intricate issue of what constitutes a mens rea aside and focus on beliefs about actus reus.

2 This article builds on Mario Günther, Probability of Guilt (unpublished manuscript on file with author), where legal proof is analyzed in terms of rational belief.

3 See Richard Foley, Working Without a Net: A Study of Egocentric Epistemology (1993).

4 The prisoner example originates in Charles R. Nesson, Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences: The Value of Complexity, 92 Harv. L. Rev. 1187 (1979).

5 See, among others, Gary L. Wells, Naked Statistical Evidence of Liability: Is Subjective Probability Enough?, 62 Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 739 (1992), Keith E. Niedermeier, Norbert L. Kerr, and Lawrence A. Messé, Jurors’ Use of Naked Statistical Evidence: Exploring Bases and Implications of the Wells Effect, 76 Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 533 (1999), Mike Redmayne, Exploring the Proof Paradoxes, 14 Legal Theory 281 (2008), Hal R. Arkes, Brittany Shoots-Reinhard, and Ryan S. Mayes, Disjunction Between Probability and Verdict in Juror Decision Making, 25 Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 276 (2012), and Michael Blome-Tillmann, Sensitivity, Causality, and Statistical Evidence in Courts of Law, 4 Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 102 (2015).

6 Lara Buchak, Belief, Credence, and Norms, 169 Philosophical Studies 303, 291 (2014).

7 The expectation that a proposition remains more likely than not is inspired by the notion of P-stability put forth by Hannes Leitgeb, The Stability Theory of Belief, 123 Phil. Rev. 131 (2014).

8 Duncan Pritchard explains in Legal Risk, Legal Evidence and the Arithmetic of Criminal Justice, 9 Jurisprudence 108 (2018) the feeling of randomness thus: it is an easy possibility that the prisoner standing trial is innocent. He does not define what possibilities are easy in terms of probabilities. By contrast, we may stipulate that a possibility is easy if it is at least as likely as any other possibility. On this stipulation, it is an easy possibility that the prisoner standing trial is innocent given only the 99:1 statistic. Given only the director’s eyewitness testimony, however, the prisoner being innocent is not an easy possibility.

9 This is a characterization of statistical evidence also given by Dana K. Nelkin, The Lottery Paradox, Knowledge, and Rationality, 109 Phil. Rev. 373 (2000) and Buchak, supra note 6, among others.

10 See Georgi Gardiner, Legal Burdens of Proof and Statistical Evidence, in The Routledge Handbook of Applied Epistemology (J. Chase and D. Coady eds, 2018).

11 David Enoch and Levi Spectre, Sensitivity, Safety, and the Law: A Reply to Pardo, 25 Legal Theory 183–184 (2019).

12 See, for example, Judith J. Thomson, Liability and Individualized Evidence, 49 Law and Contemporary Problems 199 (1986) and Blome-Tillmann, supra note 5.

13 Jonathan J. Koehler and Daniel N. Shaviro, Veridical Verdicts: Increasing Verdict Accuracy Through the Use of Overtly Probabilistic Evidence and Methods, 75 Cornell Law Review 264 (1990).

14 Ronald J. Allen and Christopher K. Smiciklas observe in The Law’s Aversion to Naked Statistics and Other Mistakes, 28 Legal Theory 179 (2022) that there is no general aversion to probabilities in common law decision-making. Our account of legal proof provides a normative foundation for this legal practice.

15 This consequence has been proven in detail by Hannes Leitgeb, Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief, 164 Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 1338 (2013), and Leitgeb, supra note 7.

16 Our account of legal proof can be understood as a probabilification of Lackey’s in Norms of Criminal Conviction, 31 Philosophical Issues 188 (2021). She proposes: “Convict a defendant if and only if you (i) justifiably judge that the defendant is guilty on the basis of the admissible evidence and (ii) justifiably judge that there is no plausible account of innocence consistent with the admissible evidence” (p. 198). We may interpret condition (i) as requiring that you have a high enough credence in the defendant’s guilt based on the available and admissible evidence and condition (ii) as requiring that you consider no “plausible account” $ B $ such that your credence P(I | $ B $ ) in his innocence is more likely than not. Let us stipulate: an account is plausible iff you assign it non-zero credence and it is consistent with your strongest justified belief induced by your available and admissible evidence. A plausible account of the defendant’s innocence is then a reasonable doubt of his guilt. (i) and (ii) taken together simply mean: you should convict a defendant iff you are justified in believing that the defendant is guilty.

17 John Kaplan, Decision Theory and the Factfinding Process, 20 Stan. L. Rev. 1065 (1968).

18 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England: In Four Books, (J. B. Lippincott ed.) 358 (1753).

19 I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for this point.

20 The blue bus case originates in Laurence H. Tribe, Trial by Mathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process, 84 Harv. L. Rev. 1340–1350 (1971).

21 The gatecrasher case originates in L. Jonathan Cohen, The Probable and the Provable (1977).

22 See Redmayne, supra note 5.

23 Our account has no need to impose any modal notion of sensitivity (unlike David Enoch, Levi Spectre, and Talia Fisher, Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge, 40 Philosophy & Public Affairs, 197 (2012), David Enoch and Talia Fisher, Sense and ‘Sensitivity’: Epistemic and Instrumental Approaches to Statistical Evidence, 67 Stan. L. Rev. 557 (2015), and Mario Günther, Epistemic Sensitivity and Evidence, 67 Inquiry 1348 (2024)), of safety (unlike Duncan Pritchard, Risk, 46 Metaphilosophy 436 (2015), Pritchard, supra note 5, and Michael S. Pardo, Safety vs. Sensitivity: Possible Worlds and the Law of Evidence, 24 Legal Theory 50 (2018)), and of normic support (unlike Martin Smith, What Else Justification Could Be, 44 Noûs 10 (2010) and When Does Evidence Suffice for Conviction?, 127 Mind 1193 (2018)). Our account has also no need for knowledge; it neither imposes (probabilistic) knowledge (unlike Sarah Moss, Knowledge and Legal Proof, in Oxford Studies in Epistemology (2021)) nor sufficiently high evidential probability of knowledge (unlike Blome-Tillmann, ‘More Likely Than Not’ Knowledge First and the Role of Bare Statistical Evidence in Courts of Law, in Knowledge First: Approaches in Epistemology and Mind (E. C. G. J. Adam Carter and B. Jarvis eds., 2017)). Finally, our account has no need for a notion of second-order probability or meta-uncertainty (unlike Katie Steele and Mark Colyvan, Meta-Uncertainty and the Proof Paradoxes, 180 Philosophical Studies 1927 (2023)).