I Recent work on Cassius Dio
Older scholarship mostly took a dim view of Cassius Dio, dismissing him as an indifferent historian and banal thinker, corrupted by rhetoric and imitation of Thucydides — a judgement given classic expression in the scathing pages with which Schwartz opened his RE article before turning to his main business, Quellenforschung.Footnote 1In 1964 the subject was transformed by Fergus Millar’s A Study of Cassius Dio, the first monograph wholly devoted to him. Bypassing traditional source-criticism, Millar brilliantly set Dio in his political, social and cultural milieu and lucidly examined his methods of work and much of his narrative. But Millar still took a modest view of Dio’s worth, concluding that ‘most of his judgements are no more than commonplace’, and ‘the sheer effort of note-taking and composition … left no time for analysis and interpretation’.Footnote 2
From around 1980 things began to look up for Dio. Several monographs were devoted to him either on his own or with other historical writers of the imperial period.Footnote 3Commentaries also began to appear. A group of North American scholars embarked on the Dio Project, aiming to produce commentaries on the whole of Dio’s Roman History, of which three were published.Footnote 4French editions in the Budé series also got under way, providing a new text (the first since Boissevain’s still fundamental edition),Footnote 5translation, substantial introduction, and notes.Footnote 6
Recent years have seen a revolution in Dio studies, with an extraordinary outpouring of scholarship which, it has been claimed, ‘equals or exceeds the entire modern scholarly output on Dio down to 2010’.Footnote 7Much of this publication has continued earlier formats, including six excellent Budé volumes,Footnote 8and fine commentaries by Mallan on the Tiberian books and by Scott on Dio’s final books, the latter inaugurating the revival of the Dio Project.Footnote 9A number of dissertations and monographs wholly or partly relating to Dio have been produced, including the comprehensive study of the speeches by Burden-Strevens and of the contemporary history by Scott. Madsen has brought out a short overview of Dio, succinctly summarizing his own interpretations.Footnote 10
Translations also mark an advance. The series of concisely annotated Italian translations, published by Rizzoli, has now reached its tenth volume,Footnote 11with only one remaining for completion. For English readers, for whom the replacement of Cary’s elderly Loeb version is a longstanding need, Scott-Kilvert’s translation of the Augustan books (51–56) has now been joined by Waterfield’s of those on the Late Republic (36–40).Footnote 12
The most important development, however, has been the publication of no less than nine collections of essays dedicated to Dio, arising from conferences. First into the field was a major French project, Dioneia, organised by scholars associated with the Budé series and conducted over 2012–16, with the declared aim of taking stock of progress over the fifty years since the appearance of Millar’s seminal work and opening new lines of enquiry. This led to the publication of Cassius Dion: nouvelles lectures, two massive volumes comprising 46 contributions.Footnote 13The first volume focuses on Dio’s text and its Byzantine transmission, his historical sources and models, and the literary form and structure of the history, while the topics covered in the second, devoted to the ‘historian of power’, include Dio’s career, his political terminology and thought and his handling of institutional (dys)function and of Roman imperialism.Footnote 14
The year 2016 also saw the publication of Cassius Dio: Greek Intellectual and Roman Politician, the first of six volumes produced under the auspices of the Cassius Dio Network. This venture, co–founded by this volume’s editors, the Danish scholars Carsten Lange and Jesper Madsen, in collaboration with the North Americans Adam Kemezis and Josiah Osgood, arose out of an initial conference in 2014, and stated its principal aim as ‘to change how Cassius Dio … is perceived: from a historian sometimes judged mediocre to a politician and intellectual steeped in Roman history and historiography’.Footnote 15All but one of the volumes were published in the Brill series Historiography of Rome and its Empire, founded by Lange and Madsen. The next three Network volumes focus on specific topics, Dio’s treatment of respectively the Late Roman Republic, violence and war, especially civil war, and the Principate (a smaller volume, so published in a different series).Footnote 16The last two volumes deal with broad themes extending across the whole work, Dio’s methods and approaches and his intellectual background.Footnote 17
Besides these major enterprises, two further volumes arising from conferences have appeared, a second on Dio’s handling of the Principate and another examining his fragmentary and understudied account of Roman history down to 146 b.c.e.Footnote 18
Now such a hot topic, Dio was clearly due a Companion, and this need too has been met. The volume opens with four chapters on Dio’s multiple identities, followed by three on reception. Next comes the work’s core, six chapters on Dio’s treatment of successive periods, and it then closes with five chapters on ‘key themes’, three relating to speeches.Footnote 19
This remarkable revival of Dio research has produced a new consensus that Dio is much more deserving of study than used to be thought, as a literary artist and political thinker, and as an original historian who managed his vast enterprise with considerable success. Millar himself later came to form a more favourable judgement.Footnote 20Pelling deems Dio ‘very, very smart’.Footnote 21
The scale of the recent Dionian outpouring is daunting. Roadmaps are needed, and several have been provided. Pelling provides not just an ‘epilogue’ to the volume in which it appears, but stimulating remarks on recent publications and future directions. Fromentin sets consideration of recent work in the context of a fine overview of Dio scholarship since the nineteenth century. Kemezis provides an admirably comprehensive and insightful survey of publications from 2010 to 2021. Markov and Makhlayuk provide a thorough survey of work published from Millar on, with detailed discussion of a number of topics.Footnote 22
In what follows I seek to assess what progress has been made on a range of key issues relating to Dio and his history, focusing particularly on the collective volumes, but also taking due account of other recent work.
II Greek and Roman, senator and historian
Like his history, Dio was a hybrid. His work revived the old Roman model of a history of the Roman people from the foundation of the city, arranged by the consular year, but was presented in scrupulously Attic Greek and aspired to the highest Greek literary standards. Dio himself came from an elite Greek family long established in Bithynian Nicaea, and was a pepaideumenos, proud of his high culture; but he was also the son of a consul and provincial governor, and his senatorial career surpassed his father’s, culminating in a second consulship in 229, when he started the year with the emperor Severus Alexander as his colleague. Recent studies confirm that, as has long been recognised, Dio’s multiple identities posed no conflict, and illuminatingly explore aspects like his Bithynian background and bilingualism.Footnote 23Dio uses the first person plural sometimes of Romans or Bithynians, but more often of senators.Footnote 24He shows no special care for the interests of provincial cities, making Maecenas propose new restrictions on their expenses (52.30.3–4, 9–10), and, unlike earlier Greek writers, he gives Nero no credit for philhellenism.Footnote 25
Legal and epigraphic sources frequently cite Dio’s second consulship for dating, confirming the order of his names as Cassius Dio.Footnote 26A diploma (AE 1985, 821) adds his praenomen L(ucius). A Beroea inscription (AE 1971, 430) prefaces his name with the letters KL: this has been taken as showing that he also bore the name Claudius, but is more probably an error.Footnote 27
For his career we depend wholly on Dio’s own evidence. Fortunately, ‘Dio exceeds any previous historian in number and scale of preserved autobiographical participatory remarks’,Footnote 28many of them vividly anecdotal and displaying his eyewitness status or other sources of special knowledge.Footnote 29Molin provides the best recent reconstruction of his career, but differs only in a few details from the classic account given by Millar, for example that Dio did not hold the praetorship which Pertinax had granted him until 195, and the city commissionership to which Macrinus appointed him in 218 may have been not just as curator of Pergamum and Smyrna, but as corrector of the province of Asia.Footnote 30On the disputed questions of the date of Dio’s first (suffect) consulship and the nature of ‘the command in Africa’ (τὴν ἐν τῇ Ἀφρικῇ ἡγεμονίαν: 49.36.4, 80.1.2) to which he was appointed soon after Severus Alexander’s accession in 222, most scholars now, surely rightly, follow Millar that he received the consulship from Septimius Severus c. 206, rather than being denied it until early in Severus Alexander’s reign, and that the command was the prestigious proconsulship of Africa.Footnote 31
Dio survived a succession of autocratic regimes, but most of his career was, in Millar’s words, ‘respectable but not distinguished’: he was not close to any emperor and held no major appointment.Footnote 32All this changed, for reasons which remain obscure, with Severus Alexander’s accession, bringing Dio the consular governorships of successively Africa, Dalmatia and Pannonia, followed by the second consulship.Footnote 33That final advancement, however, was marred by the soldiers’ hostility and immediately followed by the retirement to Bithynia, his ‘fatherland’ (patris), with which he closes the history (80.4.2–5.3). Dio presents it as a welcome withdrawal from the fray, but he may perhaps have resented it as exile.Footnote 34
Controversy has continued over the chronology of the history’s composition.Footnote 35Dio, mediated by Xiphilinus, tells us (73[72].23) that he embarked on it after writing first a little book about the dreams and portents of Severus’ rule and then an account of the ‘very great wars and civil conflicts’ (πόλεμοι … καὶ στάσεις μέγισται) which followed Commodus’ death, and that he ‘spent ten years in collecting all the achievements of the Romans up to the death of Severus and another twelve in writing them up’.Footnote 36This statement has usually been taken to mean that he spent 22 years researching and writing the history up to Severus’ death.Footnote 37Unfortunately, Dio gives no explicit indication of their date.
Some scholars hold that the work on ‘wars and civil conflicts’ may have covered all the internal upheavals from Commodus’ death in 193 to the defeat of Clodius Albinus in 197 and also Severus’ Parthian campaigns in 195 and 197–8, others that it covered a shorter period.Footnote 38
Among older scholars, some dated the start of Dio’s work on the comprehensive history in the mid-190s, while others put it in or soon after 201. More recently, Letta and Barnes argued that he only began research for the history after Severus’ death in 211.Footnote 39All three datings have found recent supporters. Millar switched camps.Footnote 40The early dating has been argued for by Schmidt, Sordi, Kemezis and Lindholmer; the late dating has been reasserted by Letta and is also favoured by Molin and by Scott; the middle dating has been supported by Swan, Murison, Schettino, Mallan and Markov.
No doubt the debate will continue. However, I continue to hold that only the middle dating (in or not long after 201) for the start of his work is compatible with the natural interpretation of Dio’s words.Footnote 41Dio’s statement that he spent ten years collecting materials on events up to Severus’ death implies that he did not start this research until 201, ten years before that death, or later.Footnote 42His account also carries the implication that he passed directly from the publication of the second work to embarking on the main history: this is surely incompatible with the late chronology, on which he did not start research for the main history until 211 or later. A plausible hypothesis is that Dio presented the work on recent wars and civil conflicts to Severus on his return to Rome in 202 and started research for the comprehensive history later that year, and that he completed his account of events up to Severus’ death by or before 224.
Since, as he tells us, Dio’s two early works won Severus’ approval, they must have been favourable to him and so differed significantly from the critical account of his reign given in what survives of his history. Some scholars who date the work on wars and civil conflicts no later than 195 suppose that it reflected Dio’s initial enthusiasm for Severus, later turned to disillusionment by his rehabilitation of Commodus’ memory and harsh conduct after Albinus’ defeat (strongly criticised at 76(75).7–8). More probably, however, the work included the war with Albinus and reflected Dio’s keenness to commend himself to the victor, whatever his true feelings. Thus Dio ‘began his literary career as a propagandist for the Severan regime’.Footnote 43
Dio’s account of the period up to 211 includes some references to events in the later 220s like his Pannonian command.Footnote 44If the late chronology for composition is rejected, it follows that Dio made some revisions to his account of events up to Severus’ death after its completion, but such revisions need not have been extensive.
Dio had planned to continue his history after Severus’ death as long as he was able, but in the event concluded it with his retirement to Bithynia in 229.Footnote 45It has been doubted whether Dio would have risked publishing the completed history in his own lifetime.Footnote 46However, this probably exaggerates the danger,Footnote 47and Dio would surely have sought to make the work on which he had laboured for so long publicly available, unless death overtook him. A possible indication that Dio himself prepared the history for publication is provided by the important discussion by Mallan of the indices which head each book in our surviving manuscripts and both summarise its contents and list the consuls whose years of office it covered.Footnote 48Mallan shows that, far from being a later compilation as has generally been supposed, these indices were probably composed in the third century and may well have been produced by Dio himself or under his supervision.
III Transmission
It is chiefly to the Middle Byzantine period (tenth to twelfth centuries) that we owe the survival of Dio’s history, giving us both the two manuscripts which preserve the greater part of Books 36–60 (69 b.c.e. to 46 c.e.)Footnote 49and our chief sources for the rest of the history, namely the Constantinian Excerpts (extracts from Dio and other historians made on the order of Constantine VII Porphyrogenitus), Xiphilinus’ epitome of Dio’s account from 69 b.c.e. on, and the world history of John Zonaras, who used Dio as his chief source for Roman history down to 146 b.c.e. and from the advent of Octavian to the death of Domitian.Footnote 50Extensive recent study of the Constantinian Excerpts, Xiphilinus and Zonaras has made us much better informed about their contexts, methods and aims. Németh and Kampianaki have published monographs on respectively the Constantinian Excerpts and Zonaras, and numerous papers have been devoted to them and to Xiphilinus.Footnote 51
While Zonaras mainly paraphrases Dio, Xiphilinus, who provides our primary source for Dio’s imperial narrative where Dio’s own account is not extant, often follows him more or less verbatim, sometimes for long passages, and regularly reproduces even his first–person statements. However, he often compresses heavily and makes extensive omissions. His account has been estimated to be about a quarter of Dio’s in length for the emperors (much less on the late Republic), with the scale of treatment varying widely between reigns. His preference is mainly for colourful personal material, much less for institutional or military matters, and account must always be taken of how much may have been lost or distorted.Footnote 52
A good instance is provided by the question of how far Dio maintained annalistic narrative in his imperial books. Dio’s surviving text includes an annual narrative by consular years for reigns up to Claudius, when our manuscripts fail. Xiphilinus has no interest in such dating, but occasionally reproduces consular dates up to Domitian’s death in 96 (67.14.5). Millar supposed that Dio himself stopped giving an annual account by the consular year around the end of the first century.Footnote 53However, a reference to an event happening ‘in that year’ shows that Dio was still using such dating early in the reign of Hadrian (69.8.3), and in his account of Macrinus’ short reign, for which we have Dio’s text, he marks the consular year 218 (79[78].26.8, omitted by Xiphilinus).Footnote 54Scott thinks this may be an ‘aberration’, but acknowledges the alternative possibility (to my mind, more likely) that Dio continued to use consular dating throughout the imperial books.Footnote 55
Editors since Leunclavius (1592) have drawn on the Constantinian Excerpts, Xiphilinus and Zonaras to produce a composite text for Dio’s missing imperial books. Mallan has warned against the dangers of this practice, and provides a more deconstructed version in his translation of Books 57–58.Footnote 56It is important always to take account of the sources of individual passages (not always fully clear in the Loeb edition). Future editors may wish to use typographical devices like underlining to highlight source divergences.
IV Sources and models
For the events of his own time or the recent past Dio drew on his own experience and oral testimony, but for the rest of his work he will have been almost entirely dependent on earlier authors, chiefly historians. Recent writers have generally recognised that Dio often drew on a wide range of sources and made his own choices in the versions he adopted, and are much less inclined than their predecessors to attribute his views and interpretations to his sources. In the writing–up phase Dio may have worked mainly from his notes rather than going back to the originals.Footnote 57Such methods would account well for his treatment of early Roman history, where, as Briquel and Urso show, although in some respects closer to Dionysius than Livy, Dio often diverges from them both, and on the Julio-Claudians, where, as Devillers and Mallan demonstrate, he drew mainly from the early historians of the period who also served as Tacitus’ sources.Footnote 58
In just a few cases individual sources can be identified with reasonable confidence. There are, for example, enough points of contact between Dio and the fragments of Sallust’s Histories to confirm that he made substantial use of that major work.Footnote 59The closeness of Dio’s narrative of Caesar’s Gallic campaigns to Caesar’s own account shows that it served as Dio’s chief source. Some of the numerous divergences must have been drawn from other sources, as on the defeat of Cotta and Sabinus (40.5–6), but for many Dio himself will have been responsible. Many of the variations are to Caesar’s disadvantage, notably in the stress on his personal ambition.Footnote 60
Scholars have usually held that Dio made little use of documentary sources, but the opposite view has been maintained in a series of articles by Letta.Footnote 61Dio certainly makes frequent use of documents, especially emperors’ letters to the senate, in his contemporary history, and he may have drawn some of these from the archives, consulted either in person or by others on his behalf.Footnote 62For earlier periods too, much of his information must derive ultimately from archival sources such as senate records, but, as with Livy, it seems improbable that Dio would have had the time or inclination to undertake extensive archival research himself, and more likely that he drew the material from earlier writers. Letta is on strongest ground with cases where Dio has failed to realise that senate decrees he reports were not in fact implemented, but even there he may be following a literary source.Footnote 63
As has long been recognised, Dio was heavily influenced by Thucydides in style and thought and frequently echoed him (especially in speeches, but also often elsewhere). Recent writers have duly acknowledged both this debt and other Greek literary influences, for example from Herodotus.Footnote 64However, Dio’s intertextuality has played a much less prominent part in recent work than for many other ancient authors. Remarkably, there have been no detailed studies of his Thucydidean intertexts since the 1890s.Footnote 65Internal echoes are also frequent across the Roman History, but little studied. Dio’s intertexts and intratexts would surely repay further research, assisted by digital resources.
V Structure
The Suda’s entry on Dio (Δ1239) tells us that he organised the eighty works of his history by decads, units of ten books, and this structure is apparent in what survives. Division by decads was common for large historical works, probably because convenient for stacking the papyrus scrolls forming the individual books.Footnote 66Dio’s books are shorter than most, but like others vary considerably in size: the fully extant books average around 10,000 words, but range from around 8,000 to over 12,000 words.
The Roman History centres on the change from republican government, which, like other imperial Greek writers, Dio called dēmokratia, to the monarchy of the emperors.Footnote 67The first forty books take the story down to the outbreak of the civil war between Caesar and Pompey; Books 41–50 deal with this and the ensuing civil wars up to Octavian’s decisive victory at Actium, and the last thirty books with the emperors. This transition is also given the greatest density of treatment: thus Books 41–50 cover a mere nineteen years.
Outside the still extant books, we have only limited indications of Dio’s book distribution, mainly the fragment citations by (often inaccurate) book numbers in the so–called Lexicon on Syntax. The division of individual books for Books 1–35 in Boissevain’s and subsequent editions is highly conjectural and should not be relied upon. However, a fair idea of the overall structure of this part of the history can be obtained, with each decad opening with a major event: Book 11 opened with the outbreak of the First Punic War in 264 b.c.e., Book 21 with the outbreak of the Third Punic War in 149, and Book 31 probably with the year 88, which saw the outbreak of both the first war with Mithridates and the first civil war.Footnote 68Thus the destabilising of the Republic to the point of collapse was, along with continuing external war, the main theme of Books 21–40. Sadly, due to the lack of an epitome, we know much less about Dio’s treatment of the crucial years 146–70 in Books 22–35 than almost any other part of his history.Footnote 69
Dio showed considerable flexibility in his use of annalistic dating. Although sections of the first two decads provided relatively dense treatment, for example on the Second Punic War (Books 13–17), their coverage must elsewhere have been much more rapid, and it appears that Dio passed over quite a number of consular years on the ground that nothing worth recording had occurred.Footnote 70As we have seen, he may have been himself responsible for the lists of chief magistrates which preceded each book in the published edition of his history, and, if so, this will have compensated for his leaving some unnamed in the narrative.
Dio not infrequently departed from strict annalistic ordering, sometimes with some loss of clarity, and this has led some to criticise him for chronological incompetence.Footnote 71Recent writers, however, have rightly stressed the way in such departures served his artistic purposes.Footnote 72Book 40 is an extreme case, with the greater part of the book devoted to warfare in Gaul and Parthia over 54–50 (40.1–43), and Dio only then turning to events at Rome during 53–50 (40.44–66): switching to completely regional organisation at this point enabled him to give extended treatment to Crassus’ catastrophe and Caesar’s crushing of rebellion and then focus exclusively on the political developments leading to civil war. In the fifth decad Dio’s civil war narrative is focused first on Caesar (Books 41–44) and then on Octavian, with catching–up excursuses inserted on the activities of other actors like Brutus and Cassius in 44–42 (47.20–34) and Antony in 38–35 (49.19–33).
Such ‘biostructuring’ (Pelling’s term) becomes still more marked when Dio reaches the emperors.Footnote 73Dio now organised his account (like Tacitus) primarily by emperors’ reigns, with most reigns being accorded one or more books each, and the emperor’s doings provide the main subject-matter.Footnote 74For each emperor he bookends the narrative of events with sections on his accession and on his death, each with standard features. In particular, at the start of each reign Dio includes an assessment of the emperor’s character and/or government, which then leads into the year–by–year narrative, a pattern which Dio continued at least up to the reign of Hadrian (69.3.1–8.1).Footnote 75Further non–annalistic material on emperors’ conduct is also worked into the annual record.
One of the most important recent contributions on Dio is Kemezis’ brilliant chapter in his monograph setting Dio, along with Philostratus and Herodian, against the official self–presentation of the Severan regime.Footnote 76Kemezis offers a penetrating reading of the entire Roman History as an implicit response to Dio’s Severan context, centred on his identification of four successive ‘narrative modes’ — respectively, the Republic, dynasteiai, Principate, and contemporary or eyewitness modes. This interpretation in terms of ‘narrative modes’ has won wide acceptance,Footnote 77but has also prompted some criticism.Footnote 78
Kemezis’ last two modes, Principate and eyewitness, are relatively unproblematic. As we have seen, Dio makes clear changes to the structure of his account at the establishment of the monarchy, and in authorial statements he both notes it as a watershed (52.1.1) and comments on the informational issues which it presented (53.19, 54.15.1–3). From the reign of Commodus on, Dio repeatedly indicates that he is reporting as an eyewitness, and he proclaims the practice at 73(72).4.2, 18.3–4.
Kemezis’ first two modes, the Republic and the dynasteiai, do, however, present some issues. He summarises his view of these modes as follows:
The first [mode] …, the Republican, can only be examined briefly due to the fragmentary state of our evidence; nonetheless some key features emerge. These include notably a characterization of Roman successes as collective actions. The successes are furthered by extraordinary displays of virtue from individual leaders, but such displays are only possible because the overall political climate promotes heroic action in the public interest. At a point in the late second century that cannot be precisely determined from the surviving text, this mode gives way to the political dysfunction that Dio calls dynasteiai, a condition that will last until Actium. In this mode collective action in the public interest ceases to be possible, and instead events are driven by conflicts between a very few key political figures. The political system is in effect paralyzed by a cycle of the dynasts’ ambition and their enemies’ resentment.Footnote 79
A different view of Dio’s fragmentary treatment of the early and middle Republic has been taken by several contributors to Burden-Strevens and Lindholmer 2019, stressing its continuities with his account of the last years of the Republic in Books 36–40. Competition, ambition and jealousy already feature prominently in the early books,Footnote 80and for several episodes Dio adopts more violent versions than our other sources.Footnote 81The sharp contrast which Kemezis draws between the speeches in his first two modes has also been challenged.Footnote 82
Kemezis’ claim that Dio regarded the period from the late second century down to Actium as a time of dynasteiai is based on his statement at 52.1.1 on the establishment of monarchical government.Footnote 83The passage opens with the following summary of the content of the history up to that point: ‘these were the Romans’ deeds and sufferings under the kingship, under the dēmokratia and the dynasteiai’ (ταῦτα μὲν ἔν τε τῇ βασιλείᾳ καὶ ἐν τῇ δημοκρατίᾳ ταῖς τε δυναστείαις … καὶ ἔπραξαν οἱ Ῥωμαῖοι καὶ ἔπαθον). It is generally accepted that ‘the dynasteiai’ here must denote a period distinct from the period of republican government (the dēmokratia),Footnote 84but there has been no agreement as to what that period was. Dio’s use of the term dynasteia, frequent in his account of the Late Republic and ensuing civil wars, has also been much discussed.Footnote 85He uses the term for various forms of informal personal power, but in the civil war narratives of the fifth decad he uses it in particular for supreme power as held by one or more autocratic rulers. Caesar, he tells us, had long desired ‘the dynasteia’,Footnote 86and after the outbreak of war both he and his opponent Pompey were driven by ‘an insatiable lust for the dynasteia’.Footnote 87The position of autocratic power which Caesar achieved by his victories is repeatedly termed dynasteia.Footnote 88Summing up the situation during and after the Mutina war in 43, Dio says that each leader’s goal was to overthrow ‘democratic’ government and establish a dynasteia (46.34.4), and, at the later meeting at which Antony, Lepidus and Octavian agreed to get themselves appointed as triumvirs with effectively autocratic power, he describes them as swearing a compact for the dynasteia (46.55.2).Footnote 89In the decisive battle at Philippi, Dio tells us, Brutus and Cassius were fighting for ‘freedom and dēmokratia’, and Antony and Octavian for dynasteia.Footnote 90Given this context, it seems to me most likely that by ‘the dynasteiai’ at 52.1.1 Dio meant not, as Kemezis supposes, a continuous political condition in operation from the later second century down to Actium, but the much shorter periods when republican government had been superseded by autocracy. He will have had chiefly in mind the autocratic power achieved by Caesar through his civil war victories and the comparable autocracy established collectively by Antony, Octavian and Lepidus through their appointment as triumvirs and confirmed by their victory at Philippi, but he probably included also the briefer dominations of Marius, Cinna and Sulla in the 80s.
VI Speeches
Much of Dio’s history is taken up by extended direct-discourse speech episodes (single speeches, debates, dialogues). The largely extant books 36–56 include fourteen such episodes, occupying about a quarter of the total text.Footnote 91Zonaras and the fragments enable us to identify at least sixteen such episodes in Books 1–21, explored in several recent contributions,Footnote 92and the same pattern was no doubt in operation in the little-known Books 22–35. From Book 57 on, however, passages of extended speech seem to have been much less frequent and also shorter, while short dicta become much more numerous. This shift may possibly be linked to Dio’s view of the changed evidence available for the monarchy (53.19), but he retained the earlier pattern for Augustus’ reign.Footnote 93
One purpose which these speech episodes served for Dio was the display of his literary and rhetorical skills. They make extensive use of moral maxims, and several conform to patterns which served as exercises in the rhetorical schools, like Philiscus’ consolation for the exiled Cicero (38.18–29) or the funeral speeches delivered by Antony for Caesar and by Tiberius for Augustus (44.36–49, 56.35–41). These rhetorical aspects, discussed in a number of recent studies,Footnote 94have sometimes led scholars to treat Dio’s speeches as mere showpieces, detachable from their context.Footnote 95However, most scholars now rightly regard them as embedded in their narrative context and as serving both Dio’s dramatic purposes and to explore historical issues he regarded as important. A primary aim of Burden-Strevens’ 2020 monograph is to make a case for Dio’s speeches on these lines, and several other surveys take the same view.Footnote 96
For almost all of these episodes Dio seems to have had some evidence that speeches were made (perhaps only the Cicero/Philiscus dialogue is a complete invention), and we can often trace him drawing some material from earlier historical accounts.Footnote 97However, he also modified and expanded freely for his own purposes, as notably in Caesar’s speech to the mutineers at Vesontio (38.36–46), despite using Caesar’s own account (BGall. 1.40) as his main source.Footnote 98Occasionally, Dio also drew on other Roman sources: thus Cicero’s speech against Antony is a pastiche culled from the Philippics (45.18–47), while Calenus’ response draws on the anti-Caesarian tradition (46.1–28), and Cicero’s speech on the lex Manilia is exploited in the speeches on Gabinius’ earlier law conferring Pompey’s pirate command (36.25–36).Footnote 99
A key part in many of Dio’s extant speeches is played by dramatic irony, bringing out his favourite contrast between appearance and reality, men’s claims and their true intentions.Footnote 100Preceding authorial statements sometimes highlight the disingenuousness of speakers’ assertions: thus both Pompey and Octavian profess to decline powers which they are eager to hold (36.24.5–6, 53.2.6), and Caesar at Vesontio justifies as in the public interest the war with Ariovistus to which he is in fact impelled by personal ambition (38.31.1, 34.1–3). In these and other speeches, such as Caesar’s later addresses and the two funeral orations, piquant contrasts, which Dio evidently expected alert readers to savour, abound between the speakers’ claims and his narrative accounts of events.
For Kemezis and Burden-Strevens, this feature played an important part in Dio’s overall design. Kemezis holds that the speeches in what, as we have seen, he regards as Dio’s ‘dynasteia mode’ consist either of dynasts presenting transparent lies or figures such as Catulus and Cicero making arguments which have no influence on events, and Dio’s purpose here is ‘to portray rhetoric itself, and how it functioned, what sorts of propaganda were effective’.Footnote 101Burden-Strevens accepts and develops this interpretation, arguing that Dio represented deception and dynasteia as the norm in the Late Republic, and oratory itself as one of the main vehicles of the change, and that ‘dramatic irony represents one of Dio’s most important techniques for illuminating this degradation of oratory’.Footnote 102These are powerful readings, but perhaps do not take sufficient account of the extent to which such ironic contrasts between speakers’ claims and Dio’s narrative continue into his Principate speeches, at least up to Tiberius’ funeral speech for Augustus, or the complex functions which some of his speeches perform. Caesar’s victorious address to the senate in 46 (43.15–18) and the two funeral speeches all combine patently disingenuous claims about how Caesar or Augustus came to power with praise for their clemency and the excellence of their rule with which Dio elsewhere signals his warm agreement.Footnote 103
VII From ‘democracy’ to monarchy
The change from republican government to the monarchy of the emperors plays a central part in the architecture of Dio’s history, as we have seen, and this has been reflected in its prominence in recent research. Kemezis and Madsen have provided treatments of the process in all its phases, each of which has also prompted numerous other discussions.Footnote 104
In what survives of his history, Dio makes his preference for monarchy explicit for the first time at the start of his treatment of Caesar’s murder, insisting that dēmokratia has only ever flourished in states small enough not to generate ‘excesses from prosperity or jealousies from ambition’, and that for Rome, ruling the largest and finest part of the world, moderation and concord would be unattainable under dēmokratia (44.2.1–4). The same view is repeated in several further authorial statements (47.39.4–5; 53.19.1; 54.6.1). Such statements may have been lost from earlier in his work, but Dio may have chosen to leave his view unexpressed until the death of Caesar, who, despite his earlier portrayal of his ruthless rise to power, he now insists had become the city’s ‘leader and protector’ (44.2.5 τὸν τε προστάτην καὶ τὸν κηδεμόνα αὐτῆς), so confirming the claim he had earlier attributed to Caesar himself (43.17.1).
As Coudry has admirably shown, Dio in Books 36–40 highlights various ways in which the republican system was malfunctioning.Footnote 105The lavish space devoted to the Lex Gabinia (36.23–36) reflected both the senate’s inability to provide solutions for issues like the pirate crisis and the dangerous implications of the special commands which the law pioneered. Electoral and other corruption receives special attention, for example in the urban record for 67 and in the lavish treatment of the disputes over Ptolemy Auletes (36.38–41; 39.12–16, 55–63), and so too does the endemic political violence.
Dio, however, identified the primary cause of the fall of the dēmokratia not in such institutional factors,Footnote 106but rather in moral failings: philotimia (ambition, rivalry), epithymia (desire), pleonexia (greed for more), and their invariable consequence, phthonos (jealousy).Footnote 107Dio saw these as constants of human nature, and, as we have seen, regarded them as in operation already in the early and middle Republic. However, he viewed some of the great Romans of that time as motivated by the public good, and held that at the start of the Second Punic War the Romans had enjoyed moderation and concord (frg. 52). In the late Republic, however, Dio, like Sallust (Cat. 38.3), thought that hardly any politicians acted ‘from pure motives and without any consideration of personal gain’ (37.57.3), naming only Catulus, Cato, Brutus and Cassius as exceptions (37.22.3, 46.3, 57.3; 47.38.3). It is in these terms that he interprets the relations between Pompey and Caesar. In the hope of avoiding jealousy, Pompey pretends reluctance for the commands against the pirates and Mithridates, and on his return dismisses his army and (so Dio claims) declines further honours.Footnote 108His resulting weakness leads him to ally with Caesar and Crassus in 60, although Caesar had been scheming to win the people over from him and expose him to jealousy.Footnote 109Resentment of Caesar’s subsequent success in Gaul leads Pompey to work against Caesar from 56 in Dio’s interpretation (39.25–6), disregarding the tradition of their rapprochement at Luca, of which he must have been aware. After his final victory, Caesar allows himself to be decreed extravagant honours (44.3ff), so provoking the jealousy which leads to his murder.Footnote 110
One element which Dio identifies as an essential component of dēmokratia is free speech (parrhēsia), illuminatingly discussed by Mallan.Footnote 111As he shows, Dio held that parrhēsia could continue under the emperors, since good rulers would welcome candour from their subjects, but under both regimes excessive parrhēsia was a fault. This was in Dio’s view one of the fatal flaws of Cicero, the only other late Republican figure to be given the same prominence as Caesar and Pompey, in what is notoriously a predominantly hostile treatment.Footnote 112Dio implies that the enmities Cicero made by his excessive frankness contributed to his exile, and Philiscus is made to prophesy that it will lead to his death (38.12.6–7, 29.1–2). The same flaw is later shown in action in the huge debate between Cicero and Calenus, in which Cicero destroys the concord for which he had previously argued with a bitter attack on Antony, only for Calenus to respond with an equally bitter attack on Cicero himself, after which Dio comments that Cicero could not endure the immoderate parrhēsia he meted out to others (46.29.1).
Dio portrays Octavian/Augustus’s final establishment of monarchy as a phased process extending over the years 31–27, including in 29 a consultation with Agrippa and Maecenas (in its substance certainly unhistorical) as to whether he should retain the monarchy (52.1–41). Older scholars often treated Dio’s huge Agrippa-Maecenas debate as virtually a free–standing pamphlet incorporating reform proposals for his own time. Recent writers, however, rightly insist that the debate is embedded in its context and serves to develop Dio’s own interpretation of the successful transition to monarchy, as has now been eloquently demonstrated by Burden-Strevens.Footnote 113As he shows, the case for democracy put into Agrippa’s mouth is undermined by Dio’s narrative and authorial statements, enabling Maecenas in the opening part of his speech (52.14–18) to reassert and develop the case for monarchy which Dio had presented in his own voice, before proceeding to lengthier recommendations for the conduct of monarchy which would protect it against the risks Agrippa had identified. Maecenas’ specific administrative proposals (52.19–30) include many measures which Augustus was himself to introduce (for example, on the senatorial cursus or the establishment of a standing army), and the speech then closes with general recommendations for the monarch’s conduct which are in close agreement with Dio’s indications elsewhere of how a good emperor should behave (52.31–40). However, although the debate’s primary purpose is to reaffirm Dio’s approval for Augustus’ establishment of monarchy and present his ideal of how monarchy should be conducted, its function remains multiple. Among the administrative proposals, Dio includes one which had only been introduced in his own day, namely Caracalla’s grant of universal citizenship,Footnote 114and many which had never been introduced and should thus probably be regarded as Dio’s own reform proposals.Footnote 115
How emperors should — and should not — conduct themselves is a central theme of Dio’s imperial narratives, brought out especially, but by no means only, in the non–annalistic surveys of individual emperors’ rule. His characterisation, as has often been remarked, can seem colourless, but Dio’s interest is less in individuating emperors than in assessing their qualities for rule, often highlighting features which recur across reigns.Footnote 116As Kemezis has stressed, his evaluations are polyphonal, sometimes presented as authorial, but often as reports of contemporary judgements.Footnote 117
What Dio valued in emperors reflects above all his identification with the senate’s interests and values. Emperors should show clemency, and put senators to death, if at all, only following trial in the senate, and they should welcome advice and so govern in collaboration with the senate.Footnote 118Emperors who conducted themselves in this way or in other respects behaved modestly are sometimes commended as δημοτικός or δημοκρατικός, a concept corresponding to the Latin civilis and whose application by Dio has now been exhaustively studied by Bono.Footnote 119Dio the realist had presented Octavian/Augustus’ rise to power as the ruthless pursuit of supremacy, but he regarded his conduct as monarch as exemplary, praising him at his death (in a striking twist on the old doctrine of the mixed constitution) as having achieved a mixture of monarchy and dēmokratia (56.43.4).Footnote 120
Dio’s presentation of tyrannical emperors has been analysed in detail by Schulz, with special reference to Nero and Domitian.Footnote 121She focuses especially on his deconstruction of their regimes’ pretensions, but the hostile earlier tradition will generally have had greater influence on his portrayals.
VIII Dio’s contemporary history
The eyewitness quality of Dio’s contemporary history gives it a vividness which has made it one of the most valued parts of his work.Footnote 122However, the picture it draws is bleak. From Nerva to Marcus Aurelius the Roman state had enjoyed stability and senators almost complete security, and Marcus Aurelius, in Dio’s judgement, ‘ruled the best of all those who had held supreme power’ (72(71).34.2). By contrast, in the following period, the time of his adult participation, he regarded three emperors — Commodus, Caracalla and Elagabalus — as tyrannical monsters, and the remainder as at best flawed;Footnote 123there were repeated usurpations and civil wars; and the position of senators was almost constantly insecure. Gleason brilliantly explores Dio’s rich anecdotal record of masquerades and impersonation as a reflection of the uncertainties of the time.Footnote 124
In his 2023 monograph and in other contributions Scott provides a fine survey and assessment of Dio’s contemporary history,Footnote 125and he and others have produced important discussions of individual emperors and episodes of the period.Footnote 126Like others, Scott rightly stresses Dio’s portrayal of the senators — and himself among them — as obliged to behave with (often humiliating) passivity. Both he and Kemezis set this against Dio’s stance as a historian both of his own times and of the Roman past. Kemezis views Dio as offering an oppositional history, a counter-narrative not only to the dynasty’s self-presentation but also to its conception of its relation to Roman history from Augustus on, while Scott holds that Dio saw his history as a corrective to emperors’ historical misconceptions, from which he hoped that their successors and subjects might profit.Footnote 127
Two of Scott’s conclusions seem to me questionable. The first relates to Dio’s striking Hesiodic metaphor about the transition from Marcus Aurelius to Commodus: ‘The affairs of the Romans then fell from a golden kingship to one of iron and rust, as has now our history’ (72(71).36.4 [Xiph.] ἀπὸ χρυσῆς τε βασιλείας ἐς σιδηρᾶν καὶ κατιωμένην τῶν τε πραγμάτων τοῖς τότε Ῥωμαίοις καὶ ἡμῖν νῦν καταπεσούσης τῆς ἱστορίας). Like many others, Scott takes Dio to imply that not just Commodus’ reign but the whole ensuing period covered by the remainder of his history was a time of ‘iron and rust’, and he has adopted An Age of Iron and Rust as the title of his monograph.Footnote 128Dio is, however, perhaps more likely to have intended no more than the sharp contrast between Marcus and his son.Footnote 129As has often been noted, he had made a similar use of the metaphor earlier, when he remarked that the triumvirs’ conduct made Caesar’s monarchy appear golden (47.15.4), and may here be alluding ironically to the declaration in 192 of Commodus’ time as a Golden Age (73(72).15.6). Dio, who generally avoided using βασιλεύς and its cognates of the emperors,Footnote 130may have made an exception in recognition of Marcus’ excellence, and ‘kingship’ may be a better translation for βασιλεία here than the more ambivalent ‘kingdom’ or ‘realm’, let alone the paraphrase ‘age’. Although Dio will no doubt have regarded the reigns of Caracalla and Elagabalus too as times of iron and rust, it is unlikely that he would have passed so extreme a verdict on rulers like Septimius Severus, of whom he gave a more mixed account.
My other doubt relates to succession policy. Both Madsen and Scott regard Dio as a strong supporter of non–hereditary succession, with emperors adopting their successors from the best available senators, and as deploring the return to dynastic succession from Commodus on.Footnote 131Dio, however, makes no explicit statement on these lines. He does indeed acknowledge the successes of adoptive succession in the period from Nerva to Marcus Aurelius and the subsequent failures of hereditary succession: he praises Nerva’s adoption of Trajan (68.4.1–2), gives Hadrian a speech in favour of adoption (69.20.2–5), laments Marcus Aurelius’ disappointment in his son Commodus (72(71).36.4) and disapproves of Septimius Severus’ allowing his son Caracalla to succeed, ‘although he had often blamed Marcus for not putting Commodus out of the way, and had himself often threatened to do this to his son’.Footnote 132However, as Davenport and Mallan well show,Footnote 133Hadrian’s speech serves merely to problematise the issue, and Dio will have recognised that there was no realistic prospect of an emperor’s son being passed over for the succession in favour of non-relatives. The implication of Dio’s criticism is surely just that Severus should have carried out his threat against the treasonous Caracalla, so leaving the way clear for his other son, the (also unsatisfactory) Geta, to succeed.
IX Conclusion
This survey has been necessarily selective, and numerous valuable contributions have been unavoidably passed over. Other widely discussed topics include Dio’s handling of Roman expansion and external relations, examined by Bertrand and others,Footnote 134his accounts of civil war, on which Lange in particular has made notable contributions,Footnote 135and his treatment of women, both in the imperial court and elsewhere.Footnote 136Two fine Companion chapters, on his Renaissance editors and his use by Gibbon,Footnote 137illustrate the rich possibilities of Dio’s reception, and, as Osgood observes, there is more to be done on ‘assessing just how influential Dio has been on modern understandings of the whole shape of Roman history’.Footnote 138
The extraordinary recent explosion in Dio studies has resoundingly confirmed the more favourable judgement on which its contributors are agreed: an author who has inspired so much can no longer be dismissed as mediocre or insignificant. The magnitude of his achievement and the originality and quality of his historical shaping and interpretation have been amply demonstrated. Moreover, the research possibilities have been far from exhausted. We can be confident that there is much more Dio research to come, though collective volumes may henceforth play a less dominant part as a format. New editions and commentaries will continue to throw much light on sections of Dio’s history, particularly as both the Budé series and the Dio Project commentaries tackle more of the fragmentary books. Dio has now been rightly praised (perhaps sometimes over–praised) as political theorist and analyst, but, as others have observed, not enough has yet been written on Dio the literary artist.Footnote 139There is more to be said on how Dio structured his history, both in groupings of books and within individual books and episodes, and on his inter- and intratextuality, and his language and style remain under-studied. And, as Pelling has observed, there has been little literary theory in recent work on Dio, and ‘one could do with some more pieces of straightforward literary and stylistic analysis: we are too reluctant to take on the job of just showing how good a writer he can be.’Footnote 140