Published online by Cambridge University Press: 02 September 2013
The notion of power is often said to be central to the analysis of politics. But while that analysis is a very ancient activity, the conceptual clarification of the notion of power has been undertaken only in the past generation. The reason for this discrepancy I leave to the historians of political ideas. In this introduction I merely observe that the clarification has not proceeded as far as is needed, so that we are still not at all sure of what we are talking about when we use the term. Nevertheless there is light ahead, owing especially to some formal definitions that have been offered in recent years by Shapley and Shubik, March, Dahl, Cartwright, and Karlsson. By reason of the formality of these definitions the issues of meaning have been more sharply delineated than was previously possible. Hence we have reached the point, I believe, where we may confront definitions with each other and specify precisely how they differ. In so doing we may be able to resolve some of the ambiguities remaining in the concept of power. In that hope this essay is written.
1 Shapley, L. S. and Shubik, Martin, “A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System,” this Review, Vol. 48 (1954), pp. 787–92Google Scholar; Shapley, L. S., “A Value for N-Person Games,” Annals of Mathematics Study No. 28 (Princeton, 1953), pp. 307–17Google Scholar and “Simple Games,” Behavioral Science, Vol. 7 (1962), pp. 59–66Google Scholar.
2 March, James G., “Measurement Concepts in the Theory of Influence,” Journal of Politics, Vol. 19 (1957), pp. 202–226CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also his “An Introduction to the Theory and Measurement of Influence,” this Review, Vol. 49 (1955), pp. 431–51Google Scholar.
3 Dahl, Robert A., “The Concept of Power,” Behavioral Science, Vol. 2 (1957), pp. 201–15, at pp. 202–03CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Note that Harsanyi has modified Dahl's definition (and also Shapley's) by adding opportunity costs. Since these modifications do not affect the basic theory, I have not discussed them here. Harsanyi, John C., “Measurement of Social Power, Opportunity Costs, and the Theory of Two-Person Bargaining Games,” and “Measurement of Social Power in N-Person Reciprocal Power Situations,” Behavioral Science, Vol. 7 (1962), pp. 67–80, 81–92CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.
4 Cartwright, Dorwin, “A Field Theoretical Conception of Power,” pp. 183–220Google Scholar, in Cartwright, Dorwin, ed., Studies in Social Power (Ann Arbor, 1959)Google Scholar.
5 Karlsson, Georg, “Some Aspects of Power in Small Groups,” in Criswell, Joan H., Solomon, Herbert, and Suppes, Patrick (eds.), Mathematical Methods in Small Group Processes (Stanford, 1962), pp. 193–202Google Scholar.
6 If Cartwright's force to comply, f ab, and force to resist, , could be translated into conditional probabilities of compliance and resistance, then Cartwright's definition would be exactly the same as Dahl's formula, p1–p2.
7 Gasking, Douglas, “Causation and Recipes,” Mind, Vol. 64 (1955), pp. 479–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
8 Riker, William H., “Causes of Events,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 55 (1958), pp. 281–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar. This essay depends for its terminology on my “Events and Situations,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 54 (1957) pp. 57–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
9 Simon, Herbert, Models of Man (New York, 1957), chap, 1, 3Google Scholar.
10 Warnock, G. J., “‘Every Event Has a Cause’” in Flew, Anthony, ed., Logic and Language, Second Series (Oxford, 1953) p. 101 ffGoogle Scholar.
11 But see the addendum of this paper for evidence of a manipulative element in their definition.
12 Bachrach, Peter and Baratz, Morton, “Two Faces of Power,” this Review, Vol. 56 (1962), pp. 957–52Google Scholar.
13 Singer, J. David, “Internation Influence,” this Review, Vol. 57 (1963), pp. 420–30Google Scholar.
To send this article to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about sending to your Kindle. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.
Comments
No Comments have been published for this article.