To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
In Chapter 2, the classification of data processed by MDTs under the General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR) is examined. While the data processed by MDTs is typically linked to the category of biometric data, accurately classifying the data as special category biometric data is complex. As a result, substantial amounts of data lack the special protections afforded by the GDPR. Notably, data processed by text-based MDTs falls entirely outside the realm of special protection unless associated with another protected category. The book advocates for a shift away from focusing on the technological or biophysical parameters that render mental processes datafiable. Instead, it emphasises the need to prioritise the protection of the information itself. To address this, Chapter 2 proposes the inclusion of a new special category of ‘mind data’ within the GDPR. The analysis shows that classifying mind data as a sui generis special category aligns with the rationale and tradition of special category data in data protection law.
The chapter examines the public’s ideas and aspirations about the future constitution, through thousands of letters and memoranda that diverse publics sent to the Constituent Assembly. The public’s demands were informed by their everyday life experiences, generating constitutional ideas that would take years to find their ways into global constitutional governance. We focus on the new politics of caste that emerged with the promise of a transformative constitution, wherein caste groups invoked and disseminated the language and vocabulary of liberal constitutionalism for both regressive and progressive aims. We uncover a fuller range of public voices absent from the Constituent Assembly. The public demands were based on deliberative process of reasoning, and often grounded on universal principles that would apply to all groups. We thus uncover in this chapter a reservoir of public constitutional thinking, a body of constitutional theory that emerged from India’s streets.
The EU has been represented as a singular ‘Digital Empire’ speaking with one voice on matters of EU digital regulation. Closer examination of discrete areas of EU digital regulation reveals a more nuanced picture suggesting clear institutional divergence between the EU institutions regarding the substantive protection afforded by EU law. A detailed analysis of EU data protection adequacy decisions brings to the surface intra-EU tensions concerning the substance of core EU fundamental rights. This analysis reveals that the EU Commission has taken on a more prominent role in adequacy decision-making since the entry into force of the EU’s General Data Protection Regulation at the expense of other relevant stakeholders. Furthermore, the Commission’s decisional practice does not align fully with the stance of the Court of Justice on the right to data protection. New sites of intra-EU human rights tensions are therefore uncovered with consequences for the legitimacy of the EU as a digital regulator and the role of the Commission as a guardian of the treaties.
The concept of constitutional identity has recently been invoked to impose limits on fundamental rights. In this article, I explore the relation between constitutional identity and fundamental rights and argue that constitutional identity – when properly understood – does not stand in tension but rather presupposes respect for fundamental rights. In the first part of the article, I develop a conception of constitutional identity as a set of normative commitments of a community that reflects its shared experience of establishing, and being subject to, a constitutional form of authority. In the second part, I argue that, while different constitutional identities can be idiosyncratic, they must incorporate respect for fundamental rights if their claim to reflect such common experience is to be credible. The upshot of the argument is that fundamental rights should not be understood as external constraints that limit the scope of constitutional identity, but as internal requirements inherent to the concept of constitutional identity. Although this understanding does not eliminate the difficulties which arise from different interpretations of fundamental rights, it does allow for a more productive engagement with constitutional identity claims, and for analysing them in light of fundamental rights standards they must already accept.
This chapter examines the Supreme Court’s practice, over approximately a century and a half, in developing and applying the “substantive due process” doctrine. The animating premise of that doctrine is that the Due Process Clause confers judicially enforceable protections against substantively unfair infringements of certain “unenumerated” yet fundamental or important rights. After the Court’s embarrassed climb down during the 1930s from a line of decisions enforcing rights to freedom of contract, the Court reembraced the Due Process Clause as a source of “unenumerated” rights in Roe v. Wade (1973) and, later, in decisions protecting rights to engage in private acts of sexual intimacy and extending the unenumerated right to marry to same-sex couples. Although the current Court overturned Roe in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization (2022), the majority opinion avoided a strictly originalist approach by embracing precedents holding that the Due Process Clause protects some fundamental substantive rights that are grounded in “tradition.” The chapter explores the conservative justices’ reasons for adopting that position. It also considers whether substantive due process decisions invalidating prohibitions against sodomy and laws defining marriage as necessarily involving one man and one woman can survive under the rationale of Dobbs.
Chapter Six contends that courts should apply a system of weak judicial review to protect individual rights. Most of the rights protected under current constitutional doctrine are included in the Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. The United States is a party to that treaty. Congress has the power to authorize judicial enforcement of those treaty rights. If Congress enacts such legislation, and courts practice constitutional avoidance in cases where judicial enforcement of treaties provides a substitute for judicial enforcement of the Constitution, the net result would be a system of weak judicial review. The proposed system would enable judicial protection for rights that is substantially equivalent to, and in some cases better than, the current system of strong judicial review. Moreover, with weak review, Congress could override judicial decisions with which it disagrees. The option for legislative override is necessary to restore the power of We the People to exercise control over our government, a core structural feature of the Constitution.
This chapter examines the Supreme Court’s historically evolving interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause, including its recent embrace of the view – initially uttered by a solitary dissenter in an 1896 decision in the case of Plessy v. Ferguson – that “[o]ur Constitution is color-blind.” In equal protection cases, the Court has rarely claimed originalist support for its decisions, even when effecting sharp changes of course, as in its iconic decision in Brown v. Board of Education (1954). In a recurring pattern, the Court’s leading equal protection decisions have condemned forms of discrimination –– first on the basis of race, then sex, and then sexual orientation –– only when public opinion began to view them as unjustifiably bigoted. This chapter analyzes the Court’s recent decision to invalidate practices of affirmative action in higher education that prior decisions had permitted for more than forty years. It also surveys a branch of equal protection doctrine that strictly scrutinizes deprivations of rights that the Court deems “fundamental” under the Equal Protection Clause, centrally including voting rights. It explains continuities, but also revealing disparities, between the approaches to voting rights of the liberal Warren Court, on the one hand, and the conservative modern Court, on the other.
This chapter considers the role courts play in protecting fundamental rights. It addresses three questions. What role do domestic courts play in the protection of rights in different constitutional settings? In examining key elements of constitutional design, the chapter show how there are significant variations in how courts protect rights across the world. Secondly, what role should courts play in the adjudication of rights? Here it is argued that courts in their ordinary work, applying legislation and the common law, do and must protect rights. With regard to the more contested question whether courts should protect rights under a constitutional bill of rights, the chapter argues that the case for such a role for courts is at its strongest in certain circumstances but that it cannot be claimed that in all circumstances courts should be conferred with this power. Finally, the chapter considers the current debates in the United Kingdom concerning a possible repeal of the Human Rights Act, and withdrawal from the European Convention of Human Rights, and expresses dismay at the prospect of the repeal of the Human Rights Act, given how elegantly that Act combines protection for rights by UK courts with the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty.
The spread of disinformation, such as false and fabricated content, as amplified by the expansion of artificial intelligence systems, has captured the attention of policymakers on a global scale. However, addressing disinformation leads constitutional democracies towards questions about the scope of freedom of expression as the living core of a democratic society. If, on the one hand, this constitutional right has been considered a barrier to public authorities’ interferences to limit the circulation of disinformation, on the other hand, the spread of fabricated content and manipulative techniques, including deepfakes, has increasingly questioned liberal views. This constitutional challenge is further enriched by the role of online platforms which, by mediating speech in their online spaces, are essential tiles of a mosaic picturing the potential regulatory strategies and the limit of public enforcement to tackle disinformation. Within this framework, this work argues that the European constitutional approach to tackle disinformation has defined a unique model on a global scale. The European Union has developed a strategy that combines procedural safeguards, risk regulation, and co-regulation, as demonstrated by initiatives such as the Digital Services Act, the Strengthened Code of Practice on Disinformation, and the Artificial Intelligence Act. Positioned between liberal and illiberal models, the European approach proposes an alternative constitutional vision to address disinformation based on risk mitigation and the collaboration between public and private actors.
It is common ground that a bill of constitutional rights regulates the relationship between individual and the state. Fundamental rights create negative obligations for the state – duties not to interfere with life, liberty, conscience, speech, privacy etc. To what extent, if at all, though, do fundamental rights also have a bearing on relations between individuals? Can they also obligate the state to actively promote liberty in society? Are they focused merely on state abuse but silent on social inequality – or can they be mobilized as vehicles for social justice? Undeniably, constitutionally-sensitive conflicts routinely arise, e.g., between capital and labour; between financial service providers and vulnerable consumers; between vulnerable groups themselves, and so on. However, the “constitutionalisation” of private law relationships has not always been seen as an unmixed blessing. A first concern is that the expansion of substantive constitutional norms beyond the negative basic liberties eliminates the domain of private law and private autonomy that is an essential characteristic of liberal societies. A second concern is that constitutionalisation transfers substantial regulatory authority from democratic legislatures to constitutional courts. This chapter argues that that neither of these two concerns necessarily arises in connection with the doctrine of (indirect) horizontal effect.
Constitutions set out fundamental principles of political morality that bind institutional action and assign strong political rights to individuals. At surface level, the principle of proportionality is a methodological device. It operates as a doctrinal heading under which courts scrutinize state interference with individual liberty and assess the scope of their own authority. According to the orthodox understanding of proportionality, this scrutiny takes the form of balancing rights against public interest, which raises questions about the legitimacy of judicial review. This chapter argues that, contrary to the orthodox view, proportionality is primarily about the normative foundations of constitutional rights and the duty of courts to pursue, through principled legal reasoning, the moral truth about individual rights. On this rival account of proportionality, rights are equality-based moral norms constraining state action and no actual balancing takes place by courts. If we are to take seriously both the idea of fundamental rights and the principle of proportionality, we must abandon the misleading metaphor of balancing and the problems of incommensurability and judicial scepticism to which it leads.
The use of religious symbols has sparked heated debate and numerous judicial cases across Europe. Early case law from the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) has been criticised for allegedly employing biased discourses. However, it remains unclear whether such biased discourses are present in recent ECtHR rulings or in comparable decisions by the European Court of Justice (ECJ). This article applies Critical Discourse Analysis, a linguistic and social science approach, to examine the narratives used by the ECtHR and ECJ in cases involving religious symbols. It argues that religious and gender biases are pervasive in ECtHR judgements. While the ECJ generally employs neutral language, biased discourses occasionally emerge in the ‘subtext’ of its decisions. These biases are not incidental but serve as strategic tools within judicial narratives, reinforcing the argumentative legitimacy of rulings for audiences influenced by societal prejudices.
The right to freedom of thought occupies a dubious position in Brazil. It completely lacks explicit constitutional or legal protection, despite a strong implicit recognition through derivative freedoms like expression, press and privacy. This research addresses this paradox, examining constitutional and legal frameworks, scholarly jurisprudence, significant court cases, and international treaties to delineate Freedom of Thought’s status in Brazil. It also considers recent legislative initiatives and the challenges that regulating misinformation poses for the right. The findings indicate that the right to Freedom of Thought functions as a vital juris-philosophical criterion in Brazil, underpinning various fundamental rights and playing a key role in the Supreme Court’s legal hermeneutics. Nevertheless, the absence of explicit protection leads to several limitations in its safeguard. First, it lacks a clear definition of its content and a precise delimitation of what it entails. It is also not acknowledged as a standalone right, being often conflated with other rights. Finally, its legal interpretation fluctuates with Brazil’s unstable case law. Remarkably, the internal dimension of Freedom of Thought remains largely unprotected and overlooked. The research underscores the need for explicit constitutional amendments and clearer legislative definitions to safeguard the right comprehensively, ensuring consistent legal recognition and protection in Brazil.
This study investigates whether corruption among public officials undermines fundamental rights, analysing data from 142 countries using the Rule of Law Index, a widely recognised and respected tool for assessing the rule of law worldwide. The results show that corruption among judges and bureaucrats consistently erodes fundamental rights, including labour rights and freedom of association. In advanced democracies, police and military corruption significantly reduces freedom of association, while lawmakers’ corruption undermines labour rights. However, in the broader context, corruption among lawmakers, police, and military officers does not significantly affect these rights. This study emphasises the significant role of bureaucracy in protecting rights and the devastating consequences of bureaucratic corruption. The trend of executive power abuse further complicates this issue. To combat corruption and safeguard fundamental rights, this article recommends robust mechanisms to ensure accountability and transparency, emphasising the importance of democratic oversight.
In spring 2024, the European Union formally adopted the AI Act, aimed at creating a comprehensive legal regime to regulate AI systems. In so doing, the Union sought to maintain a harmonized and competitive single market for AI in Europe while demonstrating its commitment to protect core EU values against AI’s adverse effects. In this chapter, we question whether this new regulation will succeed in translating its noble aspirations into meaningful and effective protection for people whose lives are affected by AI systems. By critically examining the proposed conceptual vehicles and regulatory architecture upon which the AI Act relies, we argue there are good reasons for skepticism, as many of its key operative provisions delegate critical regulatory tasks to AI providers themselves, without adequate oversight or redress mechanisms. Despite its laudable intentions, the AI Act may deliver far less than it promises.
The swift proliferation of connected devices in the Internal Market brought attention to their weak cybersecurity standard, reflected by widespread and oftentimes unpatched vulnerabilities and successful cyberattacks. Attacks on cyber-physical systems have a critical impact not only on the Union’s economy but also on consumers’ health, safety, and fundamental rights. Against the background of the failure of the cybersecurity market of connected devices, the 10 December 2024 entered into force Regulation (EU) 2024/2847 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 23 October 2024 on horizontal cybersecurity requirements for products with digital elements (Cyber Resilience Act, CRA). After casting light on the three regulatory foundational choices underpinning this EU legal act in the field of cybersecurity (ie, horizontal approach, risk-based approach, product safety approach), the article investigates the extent to which the CRA enhances the protection of fundamental rights, as claimed in the Explanatory Memorandum of the Commission’s proposal.
Chapter 2. The removal of James II from the throne in 1688 and the settlement of the crown jointly on William and Mary gave rise to an extensive debate about the legitimacy of the new regime. Many wrote to celebrate the ending of arbitrary rule. Some commentators (notably James Tyrrell) focused on the final securing of the fundamental rights of the people in the manner promised by the ancient constitution of England. But others (notably John Locke) preferred to appeal to the natural rights of the people as the only sound basis for guaranteeing freedom under government. At the same time, however, many rejected the settlement of 1688. The Jacobites objected that William and Mary were merely usurpers, while in the course of the 1690s a group of ‘commonwealth’ writers began to argue that the crown and executive were failing to keep their promise to outlaw the use of arbitrary power. The chapter concludes by discussing the contributions of Molesworth, Trenchard and Toland to the development of ‘commonwealth’ claims about the policies that will need to be followed if the freedom of the people from subjection and dependence is to be secured.
In 2020, amid aggressive and inflammatory political discourse and an unprecedented wave of violent attacks against migration Non-Governmental Organizations and their staff, the Greek Government sought to establish a new legal framework for the registration of Non-Governmental Organizations active in the fields of international protection, migration and social inclusion, and their members. This Article aims at providing an overview of the EU-law based litigation brought by Greek Civil Society organizations to challenge the new framework for breaching fundamental rights, and at exploring its effects beyond the Court proceedings. This Article concludes that, counterintuitively, the existence of pending litigation against the Regulation establishing the NGO Registries hampered advocacy on this issue with the European Commission.
This paper traces the legislative process of the EU Artificial Intelligence Act (AI Act) to provide an empirical and critical account of the choices made in its formation. It specifically focuses on the dynamics that led to increasing or lowering fundamental rights protection in the final text and their implications for fundamental rights. Adopting process-tracing methods, the paper sheds light on the institutional differences and agreements behind this landmark legislation. It then analyses the implications of political compromise for fundamental rights protection. The core message it aims to convey is to read the AI Act with its institutional setting and political context in mind. As this paper shows, the different policy aims and mandates of the three EU institutions, compounded by the unprecedented level of redrafting and the short time needed to reach a political agreement, influenced the formulation of the AI Act. Looking forward, the paper points to the role of implementation, enforcement and judicial interpretation in enhancing the protection of fundamental rights in the age of AI.