Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-br6xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-09-26T02:32:57.739Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fighting to Be Friends: Third-Party Bargaining, Alliance Formation, and War

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 September 2025

Brandon K. Yoder*
Affiliation:
School of Politics & International Relations, Australian National University, Canberra, Australia
Michael D. Cohen
Affiliation:
National Security College, Crawford School of Public Policy, Australian National University, Canberra, Australia
*
*Corresponding author. Email: brandon.yoder@anu.edu.au

Abstract

Alliance formation typically entails some risk of abandonment, wherein an ally may not honor its obligations in the future. When potential security partners’ preferences are misaligned, this risk looms large, discouraging mutually beneficial investment in an alliance. How can a prospective ally credibly reassure an uncertain patron that their preferences align, to mitigate abandonment risks and elicit a security commitment? We show formally that pre-alliance bargaining with third parties is one way to do so. When the patron holds abandonment concerns, the prospective ally can reassure the patron by making greater concessions to the patron’s existing allies, but more hard-line demands of its rivals. This finding implies that the prospect of an alliance can alternately promote conflict with a prospective patron’s enemies and forestall conflict with its friends. Indeed, we show that incentives for pre-alliance reassurance can result in war, even with perfect asset divisibility, no commitment problems, and complete information among the belligerents. The results are illustrated by China’s intervention in the Korean War and Australia’s post-World War II rapprochement with Japan, which were motivated largely to foster security cooperation with the Soviet Union and the United States, respectively.

Information

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The IO Foundation

As the Chinese Civil War concluded in 1949, Mao Zedong wanted no part of a conflict with the United States, given the litany of foreign and domestic problems facing the nascent Chinese communist regime. Yet less than a year later, Mao had committed tens of thousands of Chinese troops to fight the US in Korea, with clear intent to escalate as needed. Around the same time, a similarly abrupt sea change occurred in Australia’s policy toward Japan. Until 1950, the Australians considered Japan their primary security threat and steadfastly opposed Japanese rehabilitation. Yet in 1951, Australia signed a multilateral peace agreement that made substantial economic concessions to Japan, which would underpin Tokyo’s revival as a leading regional power.

In this article we argue that such shifts in a state’s bargaining position can result from the conditional promise of an alliance from a third-party patron, and the resulting incentives the state faces to reassure its prospective patron that it will be a reliable ally. In the case of China the patron was the Soviet Union, whose leader, Josef Stalin, was skeptical of China’s resolve to fight in support of Soviet aims. He therefore presented the Korean conflict to Mao as an explicit test of Mao’s “revolutionary credentials,” promising a substantial alliance investment if China were to intervene with sufficient vigor. In the other case, the US had withheld an alliance with Australia out of concern that it was not sufficiently anti-communist to support US containment policies. Thus, conceding to Japan’s rehabilitation as a bulwark against communist expansion, despite the pronounced threat it was still believed to pose, constituted a costly signal of Australia’s commitment to US priorities. In short, the need to reassure a prospective ally incentivized China to go to war with a rival of the Soviet Union (the US), and Australia to back down in its dispute with an existing client of the US (Japan).

These cases illustrate how pre-alliance bargaining with third parties affects, and is affected by, the reassurance problems patrons face when considering whether to commit to an alliance.Footnote 1 One key risk of such a commitment is the potential for abandonment—that is, that the ally would shirk its obligations in the future.Footnote 2 The prospect of being abandoned ex post informs the patron’s decision about whether to grant an alliance ex ante, because it wants to avoid sinking resources into a security relationship that then does not provide a return. Thus, we focus on largely overlooked cases of potential alliance formation in which the costs of investing in an alliance make patrons hesitant to conclude one, out of fear that clients would abandon them in the future. Abandonment risks, in turn, stem from misaligned preferences—specifically, when one’s ally values shared objectives insufficiently. Thus, before a mutually beneficial alliance can be consummated, clients must reassure patrons that their preferences adequately align.

We present two models that show how a prospective ally can achieve such reassurance through its pre-alliance bargaining behavior toward third parties. By taking a hard line toward the patron’s rival or making concessions to the patron’s existing client, a prospective ally can signal its resolve to uphold alliance obligations and thereby reduce the patron’s abandonment concerns. These signals of compatible preferences can induce an initially skeptical patron to grant an alliance, even when doing so carries direct costs.

The role of third parties in pre-alliance reassurance has been largely neglected. Instead, the focus has been on how abandonment affects the likelihood of war between an allied coalition and a third-party adversary after an alliance has formed. Although some works have addressed intra-alliance reassurance, none examine the signaling effects of a prospective ally’s posture toward a third party in ameliorating abandonment concerns, or the effect that the prospect of an alliance can have on a state’s incentives for war with a third party.

Our models yield several key results. First, the prospect of an alliance makes a potential ally’s bargaining behavior with third parties more informative of its preferences. Second, the conditional promise of an alliance incentivizes a state to take a hard line toward its prospective patron’s adversaries and offer concessions to the patron’s current allies. Fighting can thus serve as a crucial signaling mechanism that underpins alliance formation. Indeed, a secondary result is that when an alliance is valuable enough, the incentive to reassure the patron can generate inefficient, costly conflict between the prospective ally and a shared rival, even with perfect asset divisibility, no commitment problems, and complete information between the belligerents in their bilateral interaction. Instead, this mechanism for war centers on incomplete information held by a nonbelligerent third party, which generates reputational incentives for a prospective ally to fight as a costly signal of its reliability. It is therefore only possible in a multilateral setting, one in which the net benefits of alliance outweigh the cost of war.

We first review the literature on alliances, reassurance, and war. We then present the models and their results, illustrating each with an historical case: China’s alleviation of Soviet abandonment concerns through intervention in the Korean War, and Australia’s alleviation of US abandonment concerns through post-World War II rapprochement with Japan.

Previous Models of Alliances

Few models have studied the interplay of intra-alliance reassurance and third-party bargaining.Footnote 3 Most work on alliances focuses on how they commit allies to defend each other’s interests and send credible deterrence signals to common adversaries.Footnote 4 This literature has sought to identify how the existence and design of alliances affect the likelihood of conflict.Footnote 5 Yet it does not address the dynamics of reassurance that allow the alliance to form in the first place.

Recent models have tackled alliance formation, but not its relationship to third-party bargaining beforehand.Footnote 6 Kim studies intra-alliance bargaining where allies are completely informed of each other’s preferences, which omits reassurance entirely.Footnote 7 Other work examines how various forms of reassurance can facilitate alliance formation,Footnote 8 or maintain alliance cohesion,Footnote 9 but these analyses are restricted to bilateral signals between allies, not bargaining behavior toward third parties. Studies of how the institutional design of alliances mitigates abandonment risks are likewise limited to the interactions of the alliance parties.Footnote 10

A few works capture parts of our argument, but ultimately address different questions. Several scholars show how states form reputations for alliance reliability through past behavior toward their own allies, but not toward a prospective patron’s existing client or rivals, nor how these signaling processes affect conflict incentives.Footnote 11 Blankenship shows how the US has used reassurance to dissuade its current allies from pursuing outside options.Footnote 12 However, he addresses neither alliance formation, nor the sources of credibility in reassurance signals, nor the role of third-party threats (as opposed to alternative allies).Footnote 13 Gannon and Kent corroborate an aspect of our argument empirically by showing a correlation between a state’s contribution to a joint intervention and its possession of a formal security relationship with the coalition leader.Footnote 14 Our argument is more general, however, showing how the prospect of an alliance affects a state’s bargaining interactions with third parties prior to coalition formation, and that it can promote peace as well as conflict. And although Benson and Smith address pre-alliance reassurance in a trilateral setting, they focus on reassuring the rival of moderate capabilities, rather than reassuring a prospective ally of compatible aims.Footnote 15

The models closest to ours are Scott Wolford’s, which examine how a patron balances the trade-off between coercing the adversary into greater concessions, on the one hand, and reassuring its ally that it will not make excessive demands that raise the likelihood of war, on the other.Footnote 16 Like our models, Wolford’s capture incentives for intra-alliance reassurance and examine how those incentives affect bargaining outcomes with a third-party adversary. Yet his argument remains quite distinct from ours. First, Wolford’s main outcome of interest is the probability of war between the patron and the adversary. We focus instead on whether alliances form in the first place, and whether the pre-alliance reassurance process can generate or forestall war between a prospective client and a third-party adversary. Accordingly, the key conditions we compare here are whether or not the patron’s alliance decision hinges on the prospective ally’s pre-alliance bargaining behavior, which in turn is a function of the patron’s beliefs. This is our main causal variable. Wolford’s, on the other hand, are the adversary’s military power and the patron’s resolve, which determine whether the presence of the ally increases or decreases the likelihood of war between the patron and the adversary.

Before proceeding, we offer some notes on our scope. First, our model captures the process of forming any security relationship, formalized or not, wherein one party (the “patron”) transfers net resources to another (the “ally”), and their joint capabilities are enhanced. This transfer can take the form of either money and matériel or military integration that asymmetrically benefits one side.Footnote 17 We use “alliance” as a shorthand for such security relationships, but our argument extends beyond formal alliances.

Second, one of our contributions is to highlight patrons’ abandonment concerns prior to alliance formation, in contrast to the prevailing theoretical focus on clients’ abandonment concerns following alliance formation.Footnote 18 Abandonment concerns straightforwardly affect patrons’ decisions about whether to grant alliances, which is our focus: they must avoid investing substantial resources in security relationships with clients that might not fulfill their obligations.Footnote 19 Even if the client suffers more from abandonment ex post, after the investment in the relationship has been sunk, the patron is more concerned about its prospective ally’s reliability ex ante, when deciding whether to make the investment in the first place. For example, our case studies will show that the US and the USSR were extremely wary of admitting unreliable allies even in the insecurity-fraught environment of the early Cold War.Footnote 20 Furthermore, even asymmetrically small allies (such as Vietnam or Cuba) carry significant value for a great power, as evidenced by the intense US–Soviet competition for clients and the oft-cited advantages the US reaps from the alignment of middle powers in Europe and Asia.Footnote 21 Thus, the potential for future abandonment by clients is a significant concern in great-power alliance decisions.

Finally, although our argument clearly captures asymmetric patron–client relationships, the mechanisms also potentially apply to roughly symmetrical security relationships in which one party transfers net resources to the other. This often occurs among great-power allies with complementary and heterogeneous strengths. For example, before World War I France used its comparative financial advantages to subsidize Russia’s modernization and thus take advantage of its ally’s location, size, and resource endowments, despite their comparable overall capabilities. Similar divisions of labor characterized great-power relations between the Western Allies and the Soviet Union in World War II, the Dual Alliance of Germany and Austria-Hungary, and the Sino–Soviet alliance in our case study in this article.

Baseline Model: Bargaining with a Third-Party Rival

Specification

The baseline model has three players: a patron (P), a prospective ally (A), and a common rival (R). There are two stages, each of which entails a bargaining interaction with R. In stage 1 A bargains with R on its own, while in stage 2 P and R bargain, with A potentially weighing in on P’s side. Here, we study how observing A’s bargaining interaction with R in stage 1 allows P to draw inferences about A’s preferences and future behavior in stage 2.

A and P share a preference over the distribution of the assets in dispute with R, but place different values on them. P (and R) value them at 1, while A values them at $\alpha \lt 1$ , which is private information to A. In other words, A holds a “bias” in favor of P’s bargaining position, capturing the intuition that A’s preferences over the issue(s) at stake are closer to P’s than to R’s, but not identical to P’s.Footnote 22 $\alpha $ can take on one of two values, $\underline \alpha $ or $\overline \alpha $ , where $\underline \alpha \lt \overline \alpha $ . When $\alpha = \underline \alpha $ , A is defined as an abandoner (denoted $\underline A $ ) that will not support P against R even with an alliance, whereas when $\alpha = \overline \alpha $ , A is a supporter (denoted $\overline A$ ) that will honor its alliance obligations to P. P is initially uncertain of A’s type, holding prior beliefs that $\alpha = \overline \alpha $ with probability $q$ and $\alpha = \underline \alpha $ with probability $1 - q$ . Similarly, R holds priors that $\alpha = \overline \alpha $ with probability $\rho $ and $\alpha = \underline \alpha $ with probability $1 - \rho $ .Footnote 23 Figure 1 illustrates the configuration of the actors’ goals.

Figure 1. Spatial graph of actors’ preferences and types

Figure 2 presents the game tree. Stage 1 begins with A choosing whether to accept or reject an offer, $x$ , from R. Acceptance results in peaceful settlement at $x$ . Rejection results in winner-take-all conflict that imposes costs ${k_{\rm{R}}}$ on R and ${k_{\rm{A}}}$ on A, and which A wins with probability $w$ , its share of the bilateral distribution of power with R. Payoffs from the first-stage settlement are weighted by a factor, $\phi $ , which can be greater than or less than 1. This captures the relative value of the different assets at stake across the two stages (including discount rate). Conflict thus yields expected payoffs of $\phi w\alpha - {k_{\rm{A}}}$ for A and $\phi \left( {1 - w} \right) - {k_{\rm{R}}}$ for R, while a peaceful settlement yields payoffs of $\phi \alpha x$ for A and $\phi \left( {1 - x} \right)$ for R.Footnote 24

Figure 2. Extensive form of the baseline model (R’s payoffs omitted for legibility)

Between stages, P chooses whether to ally with A. Alliance transfers utility $u$ from P to A, whereas nonalignment is payoff-neutral.Footnote 25 $u$ captures two benefits to A at P’s expense.Footnote 26 First is the investment P makes to enhance A’s military capabilities and coordinate them with P’s own. Second, by accepting some degree of dependence on A for operational effectiveness—such as basing, logistics, or local force deployments—P becomes obligated to defend A from third-party threats in general. In turn, P’s investment in and commitment to its allies reduce their defense spending needs,Footnote 27 amounting to a direct transfer captured by $u$ . Thus, we model P’s prospective abandonment concerns during the alliance-formation process as the risk that its costly investment in A will yield no strategic payoff.

The second-stage asset is again valued at 1 by P and $\alpha $ by A, with the actors holding identical ideal points.Footnote 28 How stage 2 proceeds depends on whether P has allied with A. Without an alliance, P reaches a peaceful settlement according to the bilateral distribution of power, $\pi $ . This yields second-stage payoffs of $\pi $ for P, $\alpha \pi $ for A, and $1 - \pi $ for R.

Conversely, if P has allied with A, stage 2 begins with A choosing whether to support P against R or to abandon its alliance commitment. Support carries cost $c$ , which represents the effort A must expend to actually bring its military power to bear on P’s side.Footnote 29 Whereas abandonment entails pocketing the security resources bestowed by P, support, even short of war, requires A to invest in and mobilize its military capacity to enhance P’s bargaining leverage against R.Footnote 30 Thus, support occurs when $\alpha $ is above a particular threshold, ${\alpha ^{\rm{*}}} \equiv {{c} \over {w}}$ , while abandonment occurs when $\alpha \lt {\alpha ^{\rm{*}}}$ . As mentioned, we assume that $\underline \alpha \lt {\alpha ^{\rm{*}}}$ and that $\overline \alpha \ge {\alpha ^{\rm{*}}}$ , such that A is an abandoner when $\alpha = \underline \alpha $ and a supporter when $\alpha = \overline \alpha $ .

If A abandons, the second-stage payoffs follow just as they did with no alliance. However, sustaining the alliance adds A’s capabilities to P’s in the bargaining interaction with R. With A’s support, the coalition of P and A holds capabilities of $\pi + w$ , raising the settlement to that point. P’s second-stage payoff is then $\pi + w$ , while A’s is $\alpha \left( {\pi + w} \right) - c$ and R’s is $1 - \pi - w$ .

Results

Equilibrium analysis

We solve the model using the perfect Bayesian equilibrium solution concept.Footnote 31 There are three “classes” of equilibria across all parameter spaces, depicted in Figure 3: (1) separating equilibria (SE) in which abandoners accept R’s offer and supporters reject it; (2) pooling equilibria (PE) in which both types accept; and (3) a PE where both types reject.Footnote 32 Our main results concern a comparison of the SE and the acceptance PE, so we begin by describing those equilibria before returning to the rejection PE.

Figure 3. A’s equilibrium response for the baseline model. Arrows indicate the effect of having alliance at stake

The acceptance PE occur when R is sufficiently confident A is a supporter that it issues the minimum offer, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ , that supporters (and thus both types) accept.Footnote 33 In response to acceptance, P retains its prior beliefs, allying if and only if it holds sufficiently confident priors that A is a supporter ( $q \gt {u} \over {w}$ ).Footnote 34

Conversely, the SE occur when R is sufficiently confident that A is an abandoner that it issues the minimum offer, $x_{\underline A }^*$ , that only abandoners would accept. Supporters, being the more resolved type, necessarily reject this offer. P therefore forms posterior beliefs that A is a supporter with certainty in response to rejection, and an abandoner with certainty in response to acceptance. In the latter case P never allies, while in the former case P allies if and only if $w \ge u$ .Footnote 35

Our key results rest on a comparison of A’s incentives to fight in the equilibria where alliance is at stake versus those where it is not. Alliance is defined to be at stake when P would ally if and only if A rejects R’s offer.Footnote 36 Thus, in terms of the exogenous game parameters, alliance is at stake in the SE if and only if $w \ge u$ , whereas in the PE it also depends on P’s prior and off-path beliefs.Footnote 37 Since these formal definitions are cumbersome and unintuitive, we use “alliance at stake” as a more substantively meaningful shorthand hereafter.

Comparative statics

Our most straightforward result is that with alliance at stake A rejects offers from R it otherwise would accept, allowing it to signal compatibility with P and thereby elicit an alliance commitment. Pooling offer $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ and separating offer $x_{\underline A }^*$ each take one of two values, depending on whether alliance with P is at stake. In the SE without alliance at stake, . But this threshold increases to in the SE with alliance at stake. Likewise, in the PE without alliance at stake, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}} = w - {{{k_{\rm{A}}}} \over {\phi \overline \alpha }}$ , but this increases to $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}} = w - {{{k_{\rm{A}}}} \over {\phi \overline \alpha }} + {{w\underline \alpha + u - c} \over {\phi \overline \alpha }}$ in the PE with alliance at stake.Footnote 38 Figure 3 illustrates how these thresholds shift with versus without alliance at stake, and the ranges of offers (including out-of-equilibrium offers) each type accepts and rejects under each condition.

Result 1. Having an alliance at stake increases A’s threshold for accepting R’s offer.

Result 1 implies that conflict becomes more likely when alliance is at stake. When that alliance is sufficiently valuable, the minimum offer the supporter will accept is greater than R is willing to make. Formally, this occurs when $w$ exceeds a particular threshold.Footnote 39 When $w$ falls below this threshold, R simply increases its offer with alliance at stake to meet A’s inflated demands. However, when $w$ is large enough, R is no longer willing to make the high pooling offer both types would accept, and instead makes the separating offer that the supporter rejects. The reason for this is as follows. Recall that the supporter gains more from alliance than the abandoner does, because the supporter will actually benefit from the increased bargaining leverage against R in stage 2, whereas the abandoner will not. Thus, the supporter’s minimum offer increases more than the abandoner’s does when alliance is at stake. This increases R’s incentive to make the separating offer that satisfies only the abandoner and yields conflict with the supporter, rather than the high pooling offer that will satisfy the supporter as well. At the extreme, when alliance is sufficiently valuable, the supporter rejects all offers with alliance at stake: A prefers to suffer the costs of conflict with R in order to reassure P that it will be a reliable ally. Thus, a patron’s abandonment concerns, and the resulting incentive to reassure this generates for its prospective ally, can drive the ally into costly conflict with the patron’s rival.

Result 2. When alliance is sufficiently valuable, A’s incentive to induce P to grant an alliance can completely eliminate the bargaining range between A and R, producing costly conflict. Footnote 40

A secondary implication is that when A rejects all offers, inefficient conflict can occur even when R and A enjoy complete information bilaterally. Without alliance at stake, R would always make an offer acceptable to the supporter. But when a sufficiently valuable alliance is at stake, there is no offer the completely informed supporter will accept, so even a completely informed R cannot avoid war. In this case, incomplete information is driving conflict, but not in the typical way: it is third party P’s uncertainty about A’s resolve, not R’s uncertainty, that underpins the bargaining failure. In contrast to the standard bilateral informational mechanism, war in this case occurs because fighting constitutes an informative signal that is necessary for P to grant an alliance, giving A a reputational incentive to reject R’s offer. When this positive byproduct of fighting—alliance formation—is taken into account, war becomes net-beneficial to A, even though it remains an inefficient mechanism for dividing the asset with R. Others have recognized that incentives to build reputations for toughness with potential third-party adversaries can make war net-beneficial in multilateral settings,Footnote 41 but our model extends this logic to reputations for compatibility with potential third-party allies. We build on these past arguments in demonstrating that in a multilateral context, the strategic behavior of third parties can make war rational even with perfect asset divisibility, no commitment problems, and complete information between the belligerents, conditions that have been axiomatically cited as sufficient for peace between rational actors.Footnote 42

A final result is that having an alliance at stake can facilitate credible signaling when that alliance is sufficiently meaningful. Because A’s signals are fully informative in the SE but uninformative in the PE, expansion of the SE represents an increase in signal credibility.Footnote 43 Proposition 4 in the appendix shows that the parameter space under which R issues the separating offer instead of the high pooling offer (thereby enabling credible signals) expands with alliance at stake whenever $w$ exceeds a certain threshold. In short, the prospect of an alliance not only gives prospective allies incentives to reassure the patron of their reliability, it also makes sending credible reassurance signals more feasible than it otherwise would be.

Result 3. Separating signals that reveal A’s type are more likely with alliance at stake, as long as the alliance is sufficiently valuable to the supporter (that is, as long as $w$ is sufficiently high). Footnote 44

Pooling equilibrium on reject

Interestingly, the model also reveals a second theoretical pathway to war whereby R issues a low offer that both types reject (the rejection PE).Footnote 45 It does so under very large values of $w$ that raise high pooling offer $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ to a level that is unacceptable to R: R would prefer to fight than to make such an offer. $w$ must also be high enough that R is unwilling to make separating offer $x_{\underline A }^*$ , because the effect of an alliance between P and A (if A turns out to be a supporter) would be too onerous for R.Footnote 46 Thus, R would rather fight with certainty than allow the possibility of P forming an alliance with the supporter. Under this set of conditions, R “jams” A’s signals by making a low pooling offer that both types would reject rather than letting the supporter separate and signal its compatibility with P (assuming P’s priors dictate no alliance). In principle, therefore, R might overtly precipitate war with A to conserve P’s priors and forestall alliance formation. However, although this pathway to war is theoretically interesting, we know of no examples and are not confident that it is a common empirical phenomenon.

Empirical Applications

To establish the generality of our argument before presenting a detailed empirical illustration, we first provide a brief, nonsystematic survey of historical cases that appear to exhibit our theoretical logic.Footnote 47 Naturally, the range of the examples that follow is constrained by the limits of our own knowledge, and there are likely many additional manifestations of the theory.

There are numerous instances of military confrontations that were motivated in part by reassurance of a prospective security partner. Many occur under US hegemony, with other states attempting to secure or maintain a beneficial security relationship with the US as patron. In a cross-national study that corroborates one aspect of our mechanism, Gannon and Kent find a correlation between a state’s need for a US alliance commitment and the costliness of its contribution to the 2001–2014 war in Afghanistan,Footnote 48 suggesting that our causal logic motivated US security partners in this period. The same was true of the Korean War. In Thailand, for example, the “mere prospect of military aid had sparked a revolution in postwar Thai foreign policy amenable to American interests.”Footnote 49 The Thais knew the US sought a “definite confirmation regarding the policy of the Thai government in defending against communist aggression,”Footnote 50 and acknowledged that by deploying troops with UN forces in Korea “we will get various things in return,” ultimately resulting in membership in the US-led SEATO alliance.Footnote 51

A more speculative example is China’s attempt to achieve rapprochement with the US in what would become a “tacit alliance” against the USSR. Margaret MacMillan suggests that Mao Zedong may have provoked the 1969 Sino–Soviet border war in part as a means of “sending a signal to the Americans that the rupture between the People’s Republic and the Soviet Union was permanent,” and marks this as “the moment when [Henry] Kissinger finally accepted that … the time was favorable for an American move toward China.”Footnote 52

Our argument is equally applicable in contexts where reassurance is needed to maintain existing alliance benefits or resuscitate a lapsed or fraying alliance. In recent years, Denmark’s “will to actively maintain its status as a contributing and constructive ally through participation in [US-led] military operations [was] driven by a perception of the United States as crucial to Denmark’s national security.”Footnote 53 Denmark has been “happy to fight … to secure the alliance commitments that not so long ago seemed unchallenged.”Footnote 54 Similarly, Austria made a deliberate decision in 1914 to provoke war with Serbia, in part to assure Germany of Austrian reliability and sustain its alliance commitment. Austrian diplomats fretted that “our decision should be influenced strongly by the fact that … by a weak and hesitating policy we might risk not being so certain of German support at some future time.”Footnote 55 Austria’s foreign minister wrote that “in Germany it would not be understood if we were to neglect this opportunity” to provoke war with Serbia. That is, “Germany would consider further negotiating with Serbia a confession of weakness on our part,” which would have serious “repercussions for our position in the Triple Alliance and Germany’s future policy” toward Austria.Footnote 56 Germany’s urging “had a great influence on the firm attitude of the [Austrian] Emperor” Franz Joseph, resulting in an ultimatum to Serbia “composed so that the possibility of its acceptance is practically excluded.”Footnote 57

This last illustration highlights the applicability of our argument to contexts without a hegemonic US patron, and to relatively symmetrical great-power security relationships. An example under the former condition is the intervention of the Kingdom of Piedmont-Sardinia (“Piedmont”) in the Crimean War. Piedmont joined the anti-Russia coalition in part to “insinuate [itself] into the West’s good graces ahead of Austria, and, if possible, to gain Western support for [Piedmont]’s ambitions in Italy.”Footnote 58 Thus, Piedmont fought to signal that it would be a more reliable partner to the British and French in securing the European status quo than the Austrians would be. Historians conclude that as a result of its involvement in the Crimean War, Piedmont “came to the [diplomatic] understanding which led ultimately to the independence of Italy,” with a Franco–Italian coalition defeating Austria at Solferino in 1859.Footnote 59

Another pre-1945 manifestation of our mechanism was the formation of the Anglo–Japanese Alliance. In 1894, “Russian penetration into northern China … culminated in the Sino-Japanese War,” wherein Japan sought to wrest Korea from a crumbling Qing Empire to prevent it from falling to the Russians. Thus, “Japan emerged as a rival with Russia”—which was also Britain’s chief rival—making clear that “Britain and Japan shared a common interest in opposing further Russian expansion.”Footnote 60 In light of Japan’s war to obstruct Russia, Britain’s foreign secretary considered “a Russo-Japanese clash over Korea … inevitable in the long run,” deeming Japan “our natural ally… [Japan] will be a counterpoise to the Russians & so far a distinct advantage to us. Our policy must be to make her our ally.”Footnote 61 Similar dynamics played out more intentionally in the Boxer Rebellion during 1901. Tokyo dispatched 10,000 soldiers to help defend joint Japanese–British interests and contest expansion of Russian influence in China, in hopes of making “Britain willing to allot Japan a role as its principal partner in Asia.”Footnote 62 The interventions were ultimately successful in this endeavor, as “Japan finally achieved its goal of concluding a new treaty with Britain” in 1902.Footnote 63 Ian Nish concludes that “Japan’s behavior helped in steering British opinion towards recognizing Japan as a useful ally against Russia in Asia.”Footnote 64

Furthermore, although our argument applies most clearly to asymmetric cases in which a powerful patron confers security rents on a relatively weak ally, it can also obtain among relatively equal powers when one transfers net resources to the other. Once such instance is the “diplomatic revolution” of 1756, during the Seven Years’ War, in which long-time rivals France and Austria aligned with each other against their previous allies, Prussia and Britain, respectively.Footnote 65 Key to the realignment was the burgeoning Austro–British commercial and colonial rivalry, as well as Britain’s overtures toward Austria’s main rival, Prussia.Footnote 66 As Britain moved increasingly toward Prussia, the Austrians looked to France, Britain’s adversary in the North American theater, as a potential alternative. Recognizing that they “held in prospect a substantial alliance with Austria,” the French launched maritime operations against Britain and a 15,000-troop landing at Minorca to attract Vienna further. Subsequently, the Austrians were “impressed by France’s performance in the war, and believed … Versailles would deal with her more honestly than had their counterparts in London.”Footnote 67 Thus, France’s demonstrated willingness to fight the British in Europe helped persuade the Austrians that France would also be a reliable ally against Prussia.Footnote 68

A final empirical implication is that if taking a hard line and demonstrating a willingness to fight a common adversary can promote alliance formation, then a prospective ally’s concessions and refusal to fight should forestall it. This is seen in the effect that British and French appeasement of Nazi Germany had on alliance negotiations with the Soviet Union. Although the British “saw Soviet policy as a ruse to get Britain and France into a war with Germany while the USSR sat aside … the Soviet side saw it the other way around, convinced by various Anglo-French attempts to come to terms with Hitler.”Footnote 69 Indeed, “after the Munich conference, Soviet confidence in Britain and France hit rock bottom.”Footnote 70

This brief historical survey demonstrates that our logic generalizes across several different contexts. Whereas smaller states have often fought to garner patronage from a hegemonic US since 1945, we can also identify several cases with a non-US patron, one with symmetrical alliance partners (the Seven Years’ War), and another (Allied appeasement of Germany) exhibiting the negative implication of our argument that failure to stand firm can subvert alliance formation that otherwise seemed likely.

Sino–Soviet Reassurance in the Korean War

We illustrate results 1 to 3 with China’s entry into the Korean War in 1950. This case captures the SE with alliance at stake, casting China as the prospective ally, the USSR as patron, and the United States as third-party rival. We argue that China’s involvement in the war helped Chinese leader Mao Zedong demonstrate to Soviet dictator Josef Stalin China’s reliability as an ally. This allowed Mao to garner a Soviet alliance commitment and corresponding economic aid vital to the survival of the fledgling PRC. Initially skeptical of China’s intentions, Stalin demanded that the Chinese demonstrate their resolve to fight in support of Soviet aims by intervening in Korea. This conditional promise of Soviet security cooperation played an important role in Mao’s authorization of North Korea’s initial invasion, his decision to enter the war, and the manner in which he conducted it, informing both the timing of the intervention and the costly and prolonged military strategy China employed. But our primary purpose is to show how Mao used his entry into the war and tough bargaining posture during its course to credibly reassure Stalin and secure alliance benefits, rather than showing that war would not have occurred counterfactually. We will discuss later how our argument complements Mao’s other main motivation for intervention, to counter the threat of US troops approaching the Chinese border.

In late 1949, the Chinese communists faced a litany of problems that made securing a Soviet alliance immensely valuable. The task of rebuilding and governing a backward, war-torn country stood before them, and US-backed threats still loomed from Taiwan and Japan. A Soviet alliance was China’s best hope of bolstering itself against these formidable security challenges, while also promising desperately needed economic assistance.Footnote 71 As Westad notes, “virtually all Chinese Communist leaders believed that the construction and survival of [a Chinese socialist] state would depend on Soviet support.”Footnote 72 Thus, through 1949 Mao bombarded Stalin with pleas for an alliance accompanied by aid. Yet Stalin repeatedly declined to hear Mao’s requests.Footnote 73

The fundamental barrier to an alliance was a daunting reassurance problem. Stalin was skeptical that the PRC was sufficiently reliable to warrant the massive investment in China’s reconstruction Mao hoped would accompany a formal alliance.Footnote 74 As the CCP emerged victorious in its civil war, “Stalin could not shake his doubts about Mao’s long-term intentions toward the Soviet Union and the West,”Footnote 75 concluding from Mao’s ambivalent diplomatic posture toward the US that if push came to shove the Chinese would not “want to quarrel with the Americans.”Footnote 76 Ideologically, “Stalin remained very concerned about Mao’s loyalty to Soviet leadership” and his commitment to Stalin’s vision for world communism.Footnote 77 As Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue emphasize, “Stalin did not consider Mao a true Marxist and always suspected that the Chinese revolution sooner or later would mutate into something else, meaning something anti-Marxist and anti-Soviet.”Footnote 78 Moreover, “Mao was aware of Moscow’s apprehensions about Chinese ‘Titoism’ and was determined to prove China’s loyalty to the world revolutionary movement.”Footnote 79 To overcome these concerns and achieve a mutually beneficial alliance, credible reassurance signals were needed.

Mao’s key reassurance signal was his willingness to confront the US over Korea once it became clear the Soviet alliance was at stake. North Korean leader Kim Il Sung badly needed Soviet and Chinese support in his pending civil war, but initially found both Stalin and Mao unenthusiastic.Footnote 80 Mao twice turned down Kim’s early requests for Chinese intervention in Korea, and Chinese leaders even agreed in October 1949 that a North Korean attack on the South should be avoided entirely.Footnote 81

Once Stalin agreed to discuss a potential alliance with Mao in January 1950, however, Mao’s position on Korea changed dramatically. In one exchange, Stalin (who himself had leverage to restrain Kim Il-Sung) “clearly placed the last chance at stopping [North Korea’s initiation of] the war on Mao’s shoulders by giving him veto power over Kim’s final decision.”Footnote 82 Stalin’s reason for doing so was “to test Mao’s dedication to ‘proletarian internationalism.”’Footnote 83 Christensen concurs that “the outbreak of the Korean War was the first ‘great test’ of the Sino-Soviet alliance, and the process leading up to it exemplified Stalin’s pre-war lack of trust in Mao.”Footnote 84 This clearly shows that Stalin saw China’s behavior in the looming Korean conflict as a critically informative signal of Mao’s commitment to Soviet aims. In terms of our model, an alliance was at stake.

Crucially, Mao fully recognized Stalin’s “great test” and responded as we hypothesize. Once he had been “put on the spot by Stalin, Mao Zedong had no alternative but to confirm his support for the North Korean plans” in order to maximize alliance benefits from the USSR.Footnote 85 Thereafter, as Westad notes, Mao was quite genuinely “fighting for friendship.”Footnote 86 Mao himself recalled that “Stalin did not fully trust him to be a real revolutionary until after China’s massive intervention in the Korean War.”Footnote 87 To demonstrate his revolutionary credentials, in January 1950 Mao sent 50,000 to 70,000 troops to North Korea, a move he had previously refused to make.Footnote 88 Thus, having ensured war was imminent by granting support for Kim’s invasion, Mao then committed to covert intervention by preemptively deploying Chinese troops.Footnote 89 These were key signals of Mao’s resolve that coincided precisely with the initiation of Sino–Soviet alliance discussions.

Furthermore, as US forces approached the Chinese border in October, Mao responded to Stalin’s request that he officially enter the war with five to six additional divisions by instead sending nine, despite his awareness that the initial lack of Soviet air support would leave his troops immensely vulnerable.Footnote 90 For Shen and Xia, “China’s dispatch of troops, therefore, was a key step in turning the Sino-Soviet alliance from a paper alliance to a real one.”Footnote 91

Consistent with result 3, the Soviets deemed China’s entry into the Korean War a credible signal of its reliability and responded accordingly. Chinese intervention served to “convince Stalin that Mao and his government would not compromise with the United States and would stand by the Communist cause even against staggering odds… The Korean conflict strengthened Stalin’s trust in Mao.”Footnote 92 Mao himself confirmed that until China’s intervention in Korea, the Soviets “doubted that ours was a real revolution.”Footnote 93 Thus, “only because of the outbreak of the Korean War and Mao’s decision to send troops to aid Korea under extremely difficult circumstances was the Sino-Soviet relationship strengthened… The political, military, diplomatic, and economic dimensions of the Sino-Soviet alliance were transformed by the war.”Footnote 94 As mentioned (see note 71), Soviet assistance to China dramatically increased thereafter.

The direct quotes and historical literature we have cited show that the actors were motivated at least in part by our hypothesized mechanism. However, this is not intended to refute the leading alternative hypothesis for why China entered the war—the threat from the US advance on the Korean Peninsula—which operated alongside ours. Christensen, among others, argues that “Mao’s decision to enter Korea in force was triggered by the American decision to send US forces north of the 38th parallel… Mao did not intend to allow American troops to remain permanently behind a buffer in North Korea, regardless of the buffer’s width.”Footnote 95 Yet many of these scholars have also acknowledged the salience of Mao’s desire to secure Soviet support. Christensen himself notes that the aggressive military strategy and “tough posturing” Mao adopted were at least partly “designed to influence the Soviets.”Footnote 96 Hao and Zhai similarly identify “several Chinese interests and goals, including the improvement in Sino-Soviet relations [that] were considered by the Chinese leaders in making their decision.”Footnote 97 Likewise, for Chen Jian, Rosemary Foot, and Allen Whiting, defending China against US forces and strengthening ties to the Soviets were both significant elements of Mao’s calculus.Footnote 98

Furthermore, while the arguments are not mutually exclusive, ours helps account for several aspects of China’s entry into and conduct in the war that are otherwise anomalous. The first is the timing of Mao’s authorization of, preparation for, and initial intervention in the conflict. As we have seen, Mao invited the US threat by signing off on Kim’s invasion in the first place, in order to impress Stalin. Likewise, the deployment of combat-ready troops to North Korea in January occurred immediately after Stalin revealed the conditional possibility of an alliance, but nine months before US forces entered North Korean territory and threatened China’s border. Second, as Christensen observes in his later work, once China intervened its military strategy “of course ran directly against the goal of deterring the United States from sending its forces across the 38th parallel in the first place and reduced the likelihood that Sino-American conflict would remain limited after escalation.”Footnote 99 Thus, while “Mao’s decision to enter Korea in force” may have been “triggered by the American decision to send US forces north of the 38th parallel,” as Christensen argues,Footnote 100 our mechanism helps explain the earlier Chinese diplomatic and military policies that helped precipitate this threatening US behavior.

Finally, our argument sheds light on the intransigent bargaining position Mao adopted even as the US sought a settlement that could eliminate the threat to China. As Oriana Mastro notes, after entering the war China “maintained a closed diplomatic posture for the next eight months, refusing all third-party proposals for direct talks and not making any offers itself.”Footnote 101 This bargaining posture is puzzling if Mao’s only goal was to eliminate the US threat on the Korean Peninsula. However, it fits very well with Mao’s goal of securing an alliance by reassuring the Soviets of his resolve to incur high costs in opposing the Americans. Our argument thus works in tandem with Mao’s defensive motivations to explain China’s entry into the Korean War, and adds value in explaining crucial aspects of Mao’s strategy.

In sum, China’s entry into the Korean War nicely illustrates the model’s first three results. A state might harden its bargaining position and even incur costs of war with a common rival to reassure a prospective patron and secure a valuable alliance. Although China’s costs of fighting the US were immense, once Stalin made clear that authorization of and intervention in the Korean War would be seen as credible signals of China’s reliability, Mao jumped in with both feet. He endorsed Kim’s invasion, committed thousands of his best troops to fighting well before the war began, and then adopted a military strategy and bargaining position that guaranteed much higher costs than were necessary to defend China’s border. The gamble was successful, helping to nail down the Soviet alliance commitment and economic aid China so desperately needed.

Extension: Bargaining with a Patron’s Existing Client

This section extends the baseline framework to capture pre-alliance bargaining with a third-party client that shares the patron’s preferences, rather than with the common rival. In contrast to the baseline model, here the patron views acceptance of the third party’s offer as a signal of compatibility, and rejection as a signal of incompatibility. Thus, instead of securing an alliance by fighting the third-party rival, in this extension reassurance and alliance formation are facilitated by concessions from the prospective ally to the patron’s existing client, which can avert conflict that otherwise might have occurred.Footnote 102

Specification

This extension adds a new actor, P’s existing client, C, who shares P’s ideal point and valuation of the asset.Footnote 103 Stage 1 parallels the baseline model, except that instead of bargaining with R, A bargains with C over an asset orthogonal to the one at stake with R in stage 2.Footnote 104 This first-stage asset carries a value of $\beta $ to A. As above, C makes an offer, $x$ , regarding the first-stage asset, which A accepts or rejects. In stage 2 P then bargains with R, either alone or in conjunction with A, depending on P’s and A’s previous choices.

Two departures from the baseline model more realistically capture bargaining with P’s existing client.Footnote 105 First, because C reliably supports P against R, first-stage conflict between A and C reduces P’s second-stage bargaining leverage against R by quantity $f$ , from $\pi $ to $\pi - f$ . Second, we no longer assume A’s power relative to C is the precise degree of power that it adds in coalition with P against R. Instead, we attach coefficient $z \ge 1$ to A’s first-stage share of power, giving A a $zw$ probability of winning a first-stage conflict with C. Thus, C receives a first-stage payoff of $\phi \left( {1 - x} \right)$ following acceptance and of $\phi \left( {1 - zw} \right) - {k_C}$ following rejection. C’s second-stage payoffs are identical to P’s.

Results

The equilibrium profile of this extension is identical to the baseline model, except that there is no pooling on rejection.Footnote 106 This leaves two equilibrium classes, separating and pooling on acceptance.Footnote 107 Section 2 of the appendix contains a full equilibrium analysis of the extension.

The PE occur when C is sufficiently confident A is an abandoner that it issues the minimum offer, $x_{\underline A }^*$ , that both types accept. In response to acceptance, P retains its prior beliefs, allying if and only if it holds sufficiently confident priors that A is a supporter ( $q \gt {u \over w}$ ). Alliance is at stake in the PE if and only if P’s priors dictate alliance in response to pooling ( $q \ge{u \over w}$ ) and P forms off-path beliefs $q' \le {{\rm{u}} \over {\rm{w}}}$ . These conditions imply that P would ally in response to pooling on acceptance, but not off path in response to rejection.Footnote 108

The SE occur when C is sufficiently confident A is a supporter that it issues the minimum offer, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ , that only supporters would accept. P therefore forms perfectly accurate posterior beliefs. P never allies in response to rejection, and allies in response to acceptance if and only if $w \ge u$ . Thus, alliance is at stake in the SE if and only if $w \ge u$ .Footnote 109

As before, we compare A’s incentives to fight in the equilibria where alliance is at stake to those where it is not. Figure 4 shows how the minimum offers each type will accept— $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ for the supporter and $x_{\underline A }^*$ for the abandoner—shift with and without alliance at stake, and the ranges of offers (including out-of-equilibrium offers) each type accepts and rejects under each condition. In the SE without alliance at stake, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}} = zw - {{{k_{\rm{A}}} + f\overline \alpha } \over {\phi \beta }}$ . But this threshold decreases to $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}} = zw - {{{k_{\rm{A}}} + f\overline \alpha } \over {\phi \beta }} - {{u - c + w\overline \alpha } \over {\phi \beta }}$ in the SE with alliance at stake. Likewise, in the PE without alliance at stake, $x_{\underline A }^* = zw - {{{k_{\rm{A}}} + f\underline \alpha } \over {\phi \beta }}$ , but this decreases to $x_{\underline A }^* = zw - {{{k_{\rm{A}}} + f\underline \alpha } \over {\phi \beta }} - {u \over {\phi \beta }}$ in the PE with alliance at stake.Footnote 110

Figure 4. A’s equilibrium response for the model extension. Arrows indicate the effect of having alliance at stake

These results are the mirror image of the baseline model’s. As before, the prospect of an alliance incentivizes both abandoners and supporters to reassure P. In contrast, however, reassurance entails accepting the offer from the patron’s existing client, rather than rejecting an offer from its rival. Thus, accepting C’s offer signals compatibility with P, whereas rejection signals incompatibility.

This implies that whereas the prospect of alliance can generate conflict between a prospective ally and the patron’s rival, it can avert conflict that counterfactually might have occurred between the ally and the patron’s existing client (due, for example, to exogenous incomplete information or commitment problems that are not included in our model). Proposition 6 (in the appendix) shows that when the alliance is sufficiently valuable, supporters accept all offers. In this case, even if C were overoptimistic about its likelihood of victory or underestimated A’s valuation of the first-stage asset, war with the supporter would still be avoided no matter how severe these information problems.Footnote 111 In short, a patron’s abandonment concerns can facilitate rapprochement between its prospective and existing clients, as a means for the former to reassure the skeptical patron of its reliability.

Result 4. When P’s alliance decision is conditional on A’s bargaining behavior toward an existing client that shares P’s preferences, both supporters and abandoners are more likely to accept the client’s offer. If alliance is sufficiently valuable, supporters accept all offers.Footnote 112

Empirical Applications

As we did for the baseline model, we preface our full-length case study of the formation of the ANZUS Alliance with several other real-world manifestations of result 4 to establish that it generalizes beyond a single example.

In 1972, Egypt sought substantial US military and economic aid, if not an alliance, yet “American economic aid was largely contingent upon [Egypt] pursuing a USA-sponsored peace with Israel.”Footnote 113 Consequently, reducing hostilities with Israel loomed large in Egyptian strategy: “The Egyptian-Israeli peace process … was intimately linked to … Egypt’s transition from a Soviet ally to a nation in the American orbit.”Footnote 114 Egyptian President Anwar Sadat’s unprecedented concessions to achieve peace with Israel “aimed at changing the attitudes of the US public, Congress and the USA’s Jewish community.”Footnote 115 Indeed, Sadat saw the “framework for the agreement he was seeking with the Israelis” as part of a wider plan to “restore diplomatic relations between Egypt and the United States.”Footnote 116

This mechanism also operates in the absence of a hegemonic US. When considering expansion of the Austro–German Dual Alliance to include Italy, Germany made its commitment conditional on Italian concessions to Vienna. The Germans required Italy’s “abandonment of irredentism”—that is, of “the enlargement of the Italian state by the conquest of Austria’s subject nationalities.” But although “acceptance of the status quo in Central Europe and the Balkans must have been a bitter pill,”Footnote 117 the Italians recognized it as a worthwhile trade-off on the grounds that “as soon as we have removed the causes of distrust existing towards us in Austria, the accomplishment of an alliance with Germany will meet with no obstacle.”Footnote 118 Bismarck himself acknowledged that for Italy “the key to the German door was to be found in Vienna.”Footnote 119

Finally, this causal logic again manifested between symmetrical allies during the “diplomatic revolution” early in the Seven Years’ War. With the Anglo–Austrian alliance breaking down in 1755, the British attempted to resurrect it by offering a massive subsidy to Russia, which had been allied with Austria since 1746. Although this gambit was unsuccessful for the reasons discussed earlier, Britain’s extension of aid to Russia was a direct response to an Austrian suggestion and implies that reassuring Austria was a key British motive.Footnote 120

Australia’s Bid for a US Alliance

We illustrate result 4 through Australia’s post-World War II bargaining position regarding its rival, Japan, which the US was nurturing as a bulwark against communist expansion. In terms of our model, this case again captures the SE with alliance at stake, with the US as P, Australia as A, Japan as C, and the USSR/China as R. Despite profound fear of renewed Japanese aggression, Australia made substantial concessions concerning Japan’s economic revival to demonstrate that it shared US anti-communist priorities—actions that were sufficiently credible to American decision makers that the US granted the ANZUS alliance by mid-1951. To be clear, we do not claim that war between Australia and Japan would have counterfactually occurred, only that Australia took a softer line toward Japan to signal compatibility with the US, which captures our core argument.

Although the US and Australia now seem like natural and inevitable allies, the overlap in their interests and regional visions was quite unclear following World War II. Australia initially seemed far less committed than the US to containing communism. Tensions between Canberra and Washington centered on, among other things, Australian efforts to develop a neutral camp between the US and USSR that would include London and Ottawa,Footnote 121 and the American perception that the Australians were simply “unrealistic as regards Communist designs and methods.”Footnote 122 US concerns about “initial efforts by Australia to lead a third force in the growing conflict between East and West” persisted into 1950, as reflected in a US embargo on sharing classified intelligence with Canberra.Footnote 123 Due to this US skepticism, Australia’s initial efforts to “extract some sort of post-war security guarantee … proved unsuccessful.”Footnote 124

Abandonment concerns underpinned US alliance hesitancy.Footnote 125 NSC 48/2 emphasized in 1949 that Asia-Pacific countries, including Australia, must show themselves willing to contain communism collectively before the US would become involved.Footnote 126 Prominent in the minds of American policymakers was the cost of sinking resources into Australia’s defense capabilities, represented in the model by the direct utility transfer, $u$ , from P to A. Assistant Secretary of State William Butterworth opposed allying with Australia, largely because US security provision would reduce Australia’s incentives to pay for its own defense.Footnote 127 Thus, as Australia’s Department of External Affairs noted, “Between the end of 1947 and mid-1950 the Americans showed little inclination [toward a multilateral] Japanese peace settlement or a Pacific Pact.”Footnote 128

Crucially, US anti-communist strategy in Asia centered on a rehabilitated Japan as the United States’ key ally. As Secretary of State Dean Acheson put it, the US needed to “push ahead with the reconstruction of those two great workshops,” Japan and Germany.Footnote 129 Thereafter, “the new [US] priority was to make provisions for Japan’s security from outside aggression. Punitive efforts were replaced by regenerative efforts.”Footnote 130

However, Australia still perceived Japan as a profound threat.Footnote 131 Indeed, “one legacy of the war shared by the overwhelming majority of Australians was this realised fear of Japan.”Footnote 132 In February 1951 Minister of External Affairs Percy Spender decried US plans to include Japan in a Pacific Pact that would transform it “from an enemy into an ally over-night… We would clearly find it most difficult to accept… We cannot, in common prudence, dismiss Japan as a threat to Australian security, remote as this may seem at the moment.”Footnote 133 In short, as Spender stated, “we did not trust Japan.”Footnote 134

Spender reiterated to Truman advisor John Foster Dulles many times Australia’s resistance to cooperating with Japan, and the Americans were well aware that they could not resolve these Australian insecurities.Footnote 135 Indeed, Dulles and Acheson were convinced that a multilateral alliance including Japan would be a nonstarter with Australia.Footnote 136 Acheson bemoaned that Australian behavior at the Far Eastern Commission overseeing the Japanese occupation threatened to “jeopardize [Japan’s] stabilization program” and “seriously weaken [authority] of occupation,” from which “only Sovs and their Jap Commie Party minions will reap any advantage.”Footnote 137 Furthermore, he expressed deep concern that “Australia has clung to the belief that the principal threat to its security comes from a revived Japan rather than from a Communist Asia backed by the Soviet Union.”Footnote 138 Thus, American leaders held pessimistic prior beliefs about Australia’s support for a US containment strategy centered on a powerful Japan.

However, as result 4 implies, Australia’s apprehensions about Japanese aggression also made its willingness to support Japanese rehabilitation an informative signal of whether it shared US anti-communist priorities. The US therefore made alliance with Australia conditional on Australia’s policies toward Japan. According to Dulles’ chief advisor, Marshall Green, the key question was whether, given that an alliance was at stake, “Australia could be expected to moderate its previous position demanding that Japan remain completely disarmed and demilitarized for decades hence.”Footnote 139 Truman was adamant that he would commit to a “mutual assistance arrangement among the Pacific island nations” only on the strict condition that potential alliance partners “accept the general basis on which the United States is prepared to conclude a peace settlement with Japan.”Footnote 140 Dulles likewise wrote in January 1951 that “in view of the inter-dependence of the Pact and the proposed Japanese peace, the United States should not become committed to the Pact unless it is assured that the other Parties will agree to the kind of a Japanese peace that the United States feels is necessary.”Footnote 141

By early 1951, the Australians came to realize that a US alliance commitment was conditional on Australia’s acquiescence to a revived and integrated Japan: “The American interest in guaranteeing Australia and New Zealand appears to be linked with their desire to ensure that Japan … is protected against Communist aggression.”Footnote 142 An External Affairs memo confirmed that to consummate a US alliance “we should be required to identify ourselves with the policy that … Australia is committed to support Japan.”Footnote 143 This was the first time the Australians had explicitly linked “some substantial guarantee of our security” from the US to “a form of peace treaty with Japan which we dislike.”Footnote 144

Having come to understand that a US alliance was at stake, Australian policy-makers deemed it sufficiently valuable that they tolerated much looser restrictions on Japan than they preferred, ultimately accepting Tokyo’s economic and military resurgence as a counterweight to Chinese and Soviet expansionism. As Spender noted in February 1951, he had “taken the utmost care during the past few months to maintain a common front with the United States.”Footnote 145 Consequently, the multilateral Japanese peace settlement Australia signed in 1951 was historically unprecedented in its generosity to a defeated adversary. Japanese reparations were satisfied by mandatory purchases of Japanese goods that gave Tokyo privileged access to its former victims’ markets.Footnote 146 Economically, the currency that flowed into Japan enabled “the Japanese to re-equip and modernize their plants” and “to expand in an amazing way.”Footnote 147 Purged wartime elites were reintegrated into government. Crucially, despite Japan’s Article 9 peace constitution and immediate US control over Japan’s Self-Defense Forces, binding restrictions on Japanese rearmament were perceived as slight to nonexistent, subject only to ad hoc enforcement by the US. In terms of the model, Australian concessions to support Japan’s economic recovery and inclusion in Pacific defense arrangements were costly signals that Australia shared US anti-communist security preferences and would serve as a reliable ally.

US observers recognized these signals. Acheson, Dulles, and their colleagues were impressed by Prime Minister Robert Menzies’s vow of “assistance in swinging [Australian] public opinion around to realities of Japanese situation, with special emphasis upon … denying Japan and its industrial complex to Soviets.”Footnote 148 The Americans acknowledged “a greater measure of [Australian] support than in the past for our Far Eastern policies in general and particularly as they relate to Japan,”Footnote 149 concluding that “the views Mr. Menzies expressed when he was in Washington were [regarding the Japanese treaty] in large measure close to ours.”Footnote 150 Assistant Secretary of State Dean Rusk wrote Acheson that Australia had, “in connection with negotiation of the Japanese peace treaty, now accepted the principle of eventual Japanese contribution to its own defense.”Footnote 151 National Intelligence Estimate 19 (of April 1951) noted that Canberra was “reconciled to the necessity of Japanese defensive rearmament” and “desire[d] safeguards against both Communist expansionism and resurgent Japanese militarism.”Footnote 152

In response, American leaders updated their beliefs about the compatibility of Australian and US security preferences. In March 1950 the US ambassador to Australia emphasized the “sincerity of [Spender’s] intention and [the] importance [the] new Australian Government attaches to [the] US phase of its foreign relations,” noting that “every known act of [Menzies’] government since taking office indicates it really means business” in combating communism, and that it “has gone out of its way to strengthen [the] US-Australian relationship. In particular, it is endeavoring to meet our position re … [the] Communist problem.” The State Department soon updated as well, noting the “marked change in the orientation and direction of Australian foreign policy” since 1950, and that “Spender is desirous of establishing the closest and most cooperative relations with the United States and has in effect made this objective a cardinal point of his foreign policy.”Footnote 153 The Joint Chiefs of Staff affirmed in December 1950 that Australia could be trusted to “contribute … to the security of the [Asia-Pacific] area.”Footnote 154 Dulles thereafter deemed Australia perhaps the most loyal US ally, with Canberra having “stoutly faced up to [the] situation” and served as “our strong supporters” in combating communism.Footnote 155

These updated US beliefs culminated in the ANZUS alliance in the summer of 1951, within days of the Japan peace settlement. Although the Japan treaty was “a signal [that the US] expected the Japanese to rearm soon,”Footnote 156 which the Australians deplored, its signing generated credible assurances that Australia would support the US anti-communist strategy in Asia even when it conflicted with Australia’s other perceived interests. This allowed Spender to overcome US abandonment concerns and secure the alliance that had been an elusive holy grail for Australian governments for decades.

Conclusion

A fundamental barrier to alliance formation is the risk of future abandonment, which is underpinned by misaligned preferences between the prospective ally and patron: the ally may be insufficiently resolved to fight on the patron’s behalf, but misrepresent its intentions to reap the benefits of the patron’s investment in the security partnership. Overcoming this barrier thus constitutes a reassurance problem. How can the prospective ally signal that it shares the patron’s goals with sufficient credibility to convince the patron to commit to an alliance?

We have argued that the prospective ally’s bargaining behavior toward third parties is a potent means of achieving such reassurance. By taking a hard bargaining position with the patron’s rivals, or making concessions to the patron’s existing clients, prospective allies can credibly signal that they will uphold alliance obligations and thereby overcome abandonment concerns. Consequently, these incentives to reassure the patron and secure an alliance can promote war between the prospective ally and the third-party rival, on the one hand, and promote rapprochement between the prospective ally and the patron’s existing client, on the other. Thus, war and alliance formation interact in mutually reinforcing ways: since fighting a common rival reassures its patron and secures an alliance, a prospective ally has greater incentives to fight whenever such reassurances are necessary.

Indeed, a secondary result is that when the alliance at stake is sufficiently valuable, the prospective ally rejects all offers from the rival. In this case, inefficient conflict arises even without asset indivisibility, commitment problems, or incomplete information between the belligerents themselves. Rather, it occurs due to the third-party patron’s incomplete information about the ally’s type, which generates a reputational incentive to send a costly reassurance signal by fighting. This potential cause of war has been overlooked by bilateral bargaining models, but our results imply that it could arise in a multilateral setting.

This paper is the first to explore the interaction between pre-alliance bargaining, alliance formation, and conflict, but there is plenty more to be done. On the theory side, we consider the effects of patrons’ abandonment concerns, but the converse—entrapment concerns—are an equally likely barrier to alliance formation. Intuitively, a patron’s entrapment fears should have the reverse effect of abandonment concerns with alliance at stake, incentivizing the prospective ally to make concessions to a third-party rival instead of stronger demands, in order to reassure the patron that their preferences converge. Empirically, our approach has been to illustrate the operation of our causal logic using in-depth historical case studies, while also attempting to establish the breadth of our argument by finding instances of each mechanism in a variety of contexts. Future work should employ large-N methods to systematically evaluate the generalizability of our mechanisms and assess the frequency and magnitude of their effects under different conditions.

Supplementary Material

Supplementary material for this article is available at <https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818325100817> <https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/NGKYXZ>.

Acknowledgments

We thank Brian Blankenship, Tom Christensen, Ben Goldsmith, Kyle Haynes, Tyler Jost, Andrew Kennedy, Michaela Mattes, Brad Smith, Marija Taflaga, Scott Wolford, and the IO editors and anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on prior versions of this article.

Footnotes

1 We use “alliance” as shorthand for any security relationship in which one state commits to transfer resources to another, thereby augmenting their joint capabilities. This can take several forms, which we elaborate on later.

2 Morrow Reference Morrow2000; Snyder Reference Snyder1984, Reference Snyder1997. We use a standard definition of abandonment as failure to join a conflict when alliance terms require it.

3 There is a large literature on interstate reassurance that addresses conflict avoidance with potential rivals under security dilemma dynamics in a bilateral setting. See, for example, Haynes Reference Haynes2019; Haynes and Yoder Reference Haynes and Yoder2020; Jervis Reference Jervis1978; Kydd Reference Kydd2005; Kydd and McManus Reference Kydd and McManus2017; Schultz Reference Schultz2005; Yoder Reference Yoder2019a, Reference Yoder2019b. The focus here is instead on cooperation with potential allies in the context of abandonment concerns in a multilateral setting.

7 Kim Reference Kim2016. In their empirical study of multilateral alliance formation, Fordham and Poast Reference Fordham and Poast2016 likewise assume that states are completely informed of the degree to which their preferences converge (see also Poast Reference Poast2019).

13 The first and third distinctions also apply to Blankenship and Lin-Greenberg Reference Blankenship and Lin-Greenberg2022 and to Sukin and Lanoszka Reference Sukin and Lanoszka2024.

14 Gannon and Kent Reference Andres and Kent2021.

15 Benson and Smith Reference Benson and Smith2023. Yoder Reference Yoder2020a, Reference Yoder2020b also models multilateral reassurance, but does not address the causes of alliance formation or war.

17 Yarhi-Milo, Lanoszka, and Cooper Reference Yarhi-Milo, Lanoszka and Cooper2016. Of course, the patron must sink investment into the alliance before the ally is faced with the decision about whether to support the patron in a conflict; otherwise the investment could simply be withheld.

18 A recent exemplar is Lanoszka Reference Lanoszka2022; for exceptions see Wolford Reference Wolford2014, Reference Wolford2015.

20 This is also in part why contemporary China has broadly refrained from substantial alliance investments. Zhang Reference Zhang2025.

22 For a similar specification, see Wolford Reference Wolford2023. We conceive of the first-stage asset as comprising issue(s) of local or regional scope, where A has the capacity to intervene against R unilaterally, whereas P is precluded from intervening by geographical, logistical, domestic, or other constraints. The second-stage asset then represents the broader international order where P and R are competing more comprehensively. We also straightforwardly assume second-stage preferences are endogenous to first-stage preferences, which is all that is required for our results to hold. For example, in our case study, China’s and Russia’s preferences for the political orders both on the Korean Peninsula and globally were much closer to each other’s than to those of the US, even though there were certainly disagreements among them.

23 This specification relaxes the standard assumption of common priors to show that the results hold even if R and P hold differing beliefs about A’s type, which is certainly a realistic possibility. In terms of second-order beliefs, we assume that R observes P’s priors, whereas P’s beliefs about R’s priors are irrelevant since R makes no moves after P’s decision node. Importantly, all results are robust to retaining common priors: there is always some range of ${k_{\rm{R}}}$ under which the reported equilibria hold in the special case where $\rho = q$ .

24 P’s payoffs from the first-stage outcome are inconsequential, and thus assumed to be zero without loss of generality.

25 This captures the “patron’s dilemma,” wherein one party decides whether to transfer net resources to another in the form of military integration or money and matériel. Yarhi-Milo, Lanoszka, and Cooper Reference Yarhi-Milo, Lanoszka and Cooper2016.

26 Blankenship Reference Blankenship2020; Spindel Reference Spindel2023. $u$ is not necessarily a single up-front transfer but also captures the stream of benefits A expects to receive from P over the duration of the alliance.

28 Assuming constant preferences over the assets in each stage does not affect our results as long as preferences are correlated across local (first-stage) and global (second-stage) issues. This is almost certainly true. See Goldfien, Joseph, and McManus Reference Goldfien, Joseph and McManus2023.

29 We assume away the risk of war, another obvious cost of supporting P.

30 For simplicity, abandonment is costless for A. Introducing a dissolution cost, $d$ , to A for breaking the alliance would only serve to narrow the range of $\alpha $ for which A is an abandoner from $\left[ {0,{{c} \over {w}}} \right]$ to $\left[ {0,{{c - d} \over w}} \right]$ . But since we assume that one type is an abandoner with an exogenous probability, adding this variable would not affect the results in any way.

31 Section 1 of the appendix provides a full equilibrium analysis.

32 Within these equilibrium classes, there are three SE and four acceptance PE. Alliance is at stake in two of the SE and one of the acceptance PE, where alliance is defined to be at stake when P would ally if and only if A rejects R’s offer.

33 The acceptance PE also require that $w$ be below a particular threshold when offer $x_{\bar A}^{\rm{*}}$ would put alliance at stake. Otherwise pooling on rejection occurs (see the later subsection, “Pooling Equilibrium on Reject”).

34 For a full characterization of all acceptance PE, see section 1.3 of the appendix.

35 For a full characterization of all SE, see section 1.2 of the appendix.

36 By this definition, there are two SE with alliance at stake (characterized in sections 1.2.1 and 1.2.2 of the appendix) and one without, and one acceptance PE with alliance at stake (characterized in section 1.3.1 of the appendix) and three without.

37 Formally, alliance is at stake in the acceptance PE if and only if three conditions are satisfied: (1) P’s priors dictate no alliance in response to pooling ( $q \le {{u} \over {w}}$ ); (2) P forms off-path beliefs $q'\ge{{\rm{u}} \over {\rm{w}}}$ ; and (3) the benefits of A’s support against R outweigh P’s investment in the alliance ( $w \ge u$ ). These conditions imply that P would ally off path in response to rejection, but not in response to pooling on acceptance.

38 See Proposition 2 in the appendix. Because $w \overline \alpha \gt c$ by definition, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ is always greater with alliance at stake than without.

39 This threshold of $w$ depends on the specific equilibrium; see Lemmata 3, 4, and 6 in the appendix.

40 Formally, when $w$ is sufficiently high, the minimum offer the supporter will accept exceeds 1. This threshold of $w$ is defined in Proposition 3 in the appendix.

41 Clare and Danilovic Reference Clare and Danilovic2010; Jervis Reference Jervis1988; Schelling Reference Schelling1966; Walter Reference Walter2006. The only formalization of this dynamic in international relations of which we are aware is Chatagnier Reference Chatagnier2015, although it is also reflected in the classic chain-store paradox (Selten Reference Selten1978). Crescenzi Reference Crescenzi2007 models the belief-formation mechanism by which fighting confers reputation for toughness, but does not extend it to motivations for fighting in the first place.

42 Fearon Reference Fearon1995. Others have modeled different mechanisms by which multilateral settings can promote war: sufficiently divergent preferences when bargaining over policy issues (Gallop Reference Gallop2017) and incomplete information about an opponent’s capabilities relative to its third-party rival (Tarar Reference Tarar2023).

43 Although A keeps the entire transfer from P even if it abandons, the alliance commitment from the supporter is self-enforcing, since the supporter by definition cares enough about the asset to join P’s side against R in stage 2. Fighting R in stage 1 helps reveal the supporter’s type precisely because the asset, and therefore the prospect of alliance, is more valuable to the supporter than to the abandoner. The supporter is therefore more willing to bear the costs of war in stage 1, even though we assume the two types benefit equally from the direct transfer from P.

44 See Proposition 4 in the appendix. There are two SE in which alliance is at stake, which are distinguished by P’s off-path beliefs. For one of these SE, Result 3 holds only when $w$ falls in an intermediate range. This is due to an expansion of the rejection PE when $w$ exceeds the upper bound of that range (see next subsection).

45 The rejection PE requires that P’s prior beliefs dictate no alliance and that offers $x_{\underline A }^*$ and $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ put alliance at stake. For a full characterization, see section 1.4 of the appendix.

46 The set of thresholds $w$ must exceed for the rejection PE to hold are defined in Lemmata 3 and 4 in the appendix.

47 These cases are speculative to varying degrees, and we do not claim them as any more than plausibility probes.

48 Gannon and Kent Reference Andres and Kent2021.

49 Fineman Reference Fineman1997, 125; see also Raymond Reference Raymond2019.

50 Fineman Reference Fineman1997, 104.

51 Footnote Ibid., 117.

52 MacMillan Reference MacMillan2007, 137–38; see also Yang Reference Yang2002.

54 Jakobsen and Rynning Reference Jakobsen and Rynning2019.

55 Quoted in Mombauer Reference Mombauer2013, 214; see also 199.

56 Quoted in Footnote ibid., 223.

57 Quoted in Footnote ibid., 247.

59 Hearder Reference Hearder1996, 833; see also Rathbone Reference Rathbone2008, 31; Rupasov Reference Rupasov2024.

60 Clark Reference Clark2012, 137–38.

61 Quoted in Otte Reference Otte2007, 71.

63 Footnote Ibid., 764.

65 For a general treatment of this case, see Szabo Reference Szabo2007.

67 Schumann and Schweizer Reference Schumann and Schweizer2008, 169.

68 There is also circumstantial evidence that the French were convinced Austria would be a reliable ally by their observation of Austria’s hard-line bargaining in its disputes with Britain, which the French came to recognize “could simply not be reconciled.” Schweizer Reference Schweizer and Black1987, 247.

69 Carley Reference Carley2019, 723–24.

70 Footnote Ibid., 704.

71 Chen Reference Chen2001, 49–53; Westad Reference Westad2003, 166–67, 255, 297, 311. This transfer of resources from patron to client is captured by $u$ in the model. China received a USD 300 million loan as part of the Sino–Soviet alliance, and economic assistance to China absorbed an astounding 7 percent of Soviet GDP by the mid-1950s. See Shen and Xia Reference Shen and Xia2015, 88–91, chap. 4.

72 Westad Reference Westad2003, 165–66; see also Shen and Xia Reference Shen and Xia2015, 21–23.

73 Westad Reference Westad2003, 166–67, 253, 262–63, 268; Zhang, Zhang, and Yao Reference Zhang, Zhang and Yao2006, 106–109.

74 Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue Reference Goncharov, Lewis and Xue1993, 31.

75 Footnote Ibid., 36; see also 32–33, 41.

76 Footnote Ibid., 34.

77 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 51.

78 Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue Reference Goncharov, Lewis and Xue1993, 44, 8.

79 Garver Reference Garver1994, 10; see also Chen Reference Chen2001, 53; Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue Reference Goncharov, Lewis and Xue1993, 42–44, 47; Shen and Xia Reference Shen and Xia2015, 58–61.

80 Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue Reference Goncharov, Lewis and Xue1993, 134. Although Stalin was wary about Soviet involvement in Korea given the threat of US intervention, this dampened neither his enthusiasm for Chinese intervention in the conflict without Soviet cover, nor the degree to which he updated his beliefs in response to it. Weathersby Reference Weathersby1993.

81 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 48, 50.

82 Footnote Ibid., 59.

83 Westad Reference Westad2003, 311–12.

84 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 57.

85 Westad Reference Westad2003, 320. According to the logic of our model, authorizing the war would have been net-costlier if Mao did not share Soviet security goals because he would not have benefited as much from the alliance. This generates separation and thus credibility that, given Mao’s willingness to precipitate a war that threatened to extend to China, he was firmly committed to fight for Soviet aims.

86 Westad Reference Westad1996, 224.

87 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 57.

88 Chen Reference Chen2001, 55.

90 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 70–73.

91 Shen and Xia Reference Shen and Xia2015, 91.

92 Goncharov, Lewis, and Xue Reference Goncharov, Lewis and Xue1993, 200; see also 195.

93 Quoted in Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 260.

94 Shen and Xia Reference Shen and Xia2015, 63, 69.

96 Christensen Reference Christensen1992, 139.

97 Hao and Zhai Reference Hao and Zhai1990, 106. As they write, “To Mao’s mind, if China stood by when North Korea was in peril; then the Soviet Union could also stand by when China was in peril.”

98 Chen Reference Chen1994, 85–91; Foot Reference Foot1991, 418; Foot Reference Foot1996, 480; Whiting Reference Whiting1960, 151–58.

99 Christensen Reference Christensen2011, 71.

100 Christensen Reference Christensen1992, 138, emphasis added

101 Mastro Reference Mastro2019, 37, 42; see also Stueck Reference Stueck1995, 159. Moreover, when Mao finally did engage the US, he asked the Soviets to mediate, increased troop deployments, and ensured that he had Stalin’s approval for all concessions, all of which served to ensure that Stalin could not perceive China as lacking resolve. Mastro Reference Mastro2019, 39.

102 Lee Reference Lee2023 employs a similar logic in showing that having a common ally decreases rivalry duration, but does not examine reassurance or prospects for alliance formation.

103 C holds prior beliefs that A is a supporter with probability $\psi $ and an abandoner with probability $1 - \psi $ .

104 A separate first-stage asset is necessary because C and A both share P’s ideal point regarding the asset in dispute with R. Thus, the latter policy space contains no disagreement over which A and C can bargain.

105 Omitting these additions would not affect the results; they are included purely to demonstrate robustness to a more realistic specification.

106 Here, the separating offer dominates a low offer that induces pooling on rejection because (unlike R in the baseline model) C has no incentive to “signal jam.” Alliance between A and P is beneficial to C, because C shares P’s bargaining position and thus gains from an increase in P’s bargaining leverage versus R.

107 As before, there are four acceptance PE, one with alliance at stake and three without, and three SE, two with alliance at stake and one without.

108 For a full characterization of all PE, see section 2.2 of the appendix.

109 For a full characterization of all SE, see section 2.1 of the appendix.

110 See proposition 6 in the appendix. Note that because $w\overline \alpha \gt c$ by definition, $x_{\overline A}^{\rm{*}}$ is always lower with alliance at stake than without.

111 These sources of incomplete information are unmodeled, but the conclusion follows straightforwardly since A accepts all offers.

112 Formally, when $u$ is above a particular threshold, the minimum offer the supporter will accept falls below zero. See proposition 6 in the appendix.

114 Rabinovich Reference Otte2004, 6; see also Sadat Reference Sadat1978.

116 Stein Reference Stein1999, 103–104.

117 Scott Reference Scott1978, 405, 415.

118 Langer Reference Langer1964, 229.

119 Footnote Ibid., 237.

120 Baugh Reference Baugh2014, 125.

121 FRUS Reference Fordham and Poast1947, vol. 3, doc. 366; vol. 6, doc. 258; Robb and Gill Reference Robb and Gill2019, 31 n156.

122 FRUS 1948, doc. 550.

123 FRUS 1950, vol. 6, doc. 96.

124 Robb and Gill Reference Robb and Gill2019, 17.

125 This is reflected in the heterogeneous timing and content of US security relationships in Asia, even at the height of Cold War tensions, due to differential US beliefs about prospective allies’ reliability. Cha Reference Cha2016.

126 FRUS 1949, vol. 7, pt. 2, 1216.

127 Footnote Ibid., vol. 7, pt. 2, doc. 318.

128 22 Minute From Dexter to Shaw, 27 October 1950, National Archives of Australia, available at <https://www.dfat.gov.au/about-us/publications/historical-documents/Pages/volume-21/22-minute-from-dexter1-to-shaw>.

129 Quoted in Cha Reference Cha2016, 127–28; see also LaFeber Reference LaFeber1997, 273–75.

130 Cha Reference Cha2016, 129.

132 Millar Reference Millar1978, 126–27, 228.

133 Top Secret, for Full Cabinet, Department of External Affairs, Pacific Defence Pact: Forthcoming Exploratory Talks with Mr. John F. Dulles, National Archives of Australia, A4639 A4639XM1, vol. 8, 5104728.

135 FRUS 1951, vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 38.

136 Footnote Ibid., vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 70.

137 FRUS 1949, vol. 7, pt. 2, doc. 116.

138 FRUS 1949, Footnote Ibid., vol. 7, pt. 2, doc. 124.

140 FRUS 1951, vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 34.

141 Footnote Ibid., vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 33.

142 45 Minute From Watt to Spender, 9 February 1951, National Archives of Australia, available at <https://www.dfat.gov.au/about-us/publications/historical-documents/Pages/volume-21/45-minute-from-watt-to-spender>.

143 44 Minute From Tange to Watt, 8 February 1951, National Archives of Australia, available at <https://www.dfat.gov.au/about-us/publications/historical-documents/Pages/volume-21/44-minute-from-tange-to-watt>.

144 45 Minute From Watt to Spender, 9 February 1951, National Archives of Australia, available at <https://www.dfat.gov.au/about-us/publications/historical-documents/Pages/volume-21/45-minute-from-watt-to-spender>.

145 Relationships between Australia and China, 19 February 1951, National Archives of Australia, A4639 A4639XM1 vol. 8, 5104728.

146 LaFeber Reference LaFeber1997, 276–77, 291–95.

147 Footnote Ibid., 293-94.

148 FRUS 1950, vol. 6, doc. 741.

149 Footnote Ibid., vol. 6, doc. 104.

150 Footnote Ibid., vol. 6, doc. 108; see also doc. 99.

151 FRUS 1951, vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 650.

152 Footnote Ibid., vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 556.

153 FRUS 1950, vol. 6, doc. 96.

154 FRUS 1951, vol. 6, pt. 1, doc. 122.

155 FRUS 1952–1954, vol. 12, pt. 1, docs. 156, 183.

156 LaFeber Reference LaFeber1997, 291.

References

Baugh, Daniel. 2014. The Global Seven Years War 1754–1763: Britain and France in a Great Power Contest. Routledge.10.4324/9781315844633CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beckley, Michael. 2015. The Myth of Entangling Alliances: Reassessing the Security Risks of US Defense Pacts. International Security 39 (4):748.10.1162/ISEC_a_00197CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, Brett V. 2012. Constructing International Security: Alliances, Deterrence and Moral Hazard. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139225694CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, Brett V., Meirowitz, Adam, and Ramsay, Kristopher W.. 2014. Inducing Deterrence Through Moral Hazard in Alliance Contracts. Journal of Conflict Resolution 58 (2):307335.10.1177/0022002712467936CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, Brett V., and Smith, Bradley C.. 2023. Commitment Problems in Alliance Formation. American Journal of Political Science 67 (4):1012–25.10.1111/ajps.12693CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blankenship, Brian D. 2020. Promises Under Pressure: Statements of Reassurance in US Alliances. International Studies Quarterly 64 (4):1017–30.10.1093/isq/sqaa071CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blankenship, Brian D., and Lin-Greenberg, Erik. 2022. Trivial Tripwires? Military Capabilities and Alliance Reassurance. Security Studies 31 (1):92117.10.1080/09636412.2022.2038662CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carley, Michael Jabara. 2019. Fiasco: The Anglo-Franco-Soviet Alliance That Never Was and the Unpublished British White Paper, 1939-1940. International History Review 41 (4):701728.10.1080/07075332.2018.1458043CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cha, Victor D. 2016. Powerplay: The Origins of the American Alliance System in Asia. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chatagnier, John Tyson. 2015. Conflict Bargaining as a Signal to Third Parties. Journal of Theoretical Politics 27 (2):237–68.10.1177/0951629813518829CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, Jian. 1994. China’s Road to the Korean War: The Making of Sino-American Confrontation. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Chen, Jian. 2001. Mao’s China and the Cold War. University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Christensen, Thomas J. 1992. Threats, Assurances and the Last Chance for Peace: The Lessons of Mao’s Korean War Telegrams. International Security 17 (1):122–54.10.2307/2539160CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, Thomas J. 2011. Worse than a Monolith: Alliance Politics and Problems of Coercive Diplomacy in Asia. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Clare, Joe, and Danilovic, Vesna. 2010. Multiple Audiences and Reputation Building in International Conflicts. Journal of Conflict Resolution 54 (6):860–82.10.1177/0022002710372741CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Christopher. 2012. The Sleepwalkers: How Europe Went to War in 1914. Penguin.Google Scholar
Cohen, Michael D. 2023. Different Fears, Same Alliance: Multilateralism, Assurance and the Origins of the 1951 United States–New Zealand–Australia Alliance. Journal of Peace Research 60 (2):322–36.10.1177/00223433221077302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crescenzi, Mark JC. 2007. Reputation and Interstate Conflict. American Journal of Political Science 51 (2):382–96.10.1111/j.1540-5907.2007.00257.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crescenzi, Mark JC, Jacob D, Kathman, Katja B, Kleinberg, and Reed M, Wood. 2012. Reliability, Reputation, and Alliance Formation. International Studies Quarterly 56 (2):259–74.10.1111/j.1468-2478.2011.00711.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fang, Songying, Johnson, Jesse C., and Ashley Leeds, Brett. 2014. To Concede or to Resist? The Restraining Effect of Military Alliances. International Organization 68 (4):775809.10.1017/S0020818314000137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fearon, James D. 1995. Rationalist Explanations for War. International Organization 49 (3):379414.10.1017/S0020818300033324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fineman, Daniel. 1997. A Special Relationship: The United States and Military Government in Thailand, 1947–1958. University of Hawaii Press.10.2307/j.ctt6wqvw9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Rosemary. 1991. Making Known the Unknown War: Policy Analysis of the Korean Conflict in the Last Decade. Diplomatic History 15 (3):411–32.10.1111/j.1467-7709.1991.tb00138.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Rosemary. 1996. Leadership, Perceptions, and Interest: Chinese-American Relations in the Early Cold War. Diplomatic History 20 (3):473–82.Google Scholar
Fordham, Benjamin, and Poast, Paul. 2016. All Alliances Are Multilateral: Rethinking Alliance Formation. Journal of Conflict Resolution 60 (5):840–65.10.1177/0022002714553108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
FRUS. 1947. Foreign Relations of the United States. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
FRUS. 1948. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
FRUS. 1949. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
FRUS. 1950. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
FRUS. 1951. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
FRUS. 1952–1954. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Gallop, Max. 2017. More Dangerous Than Dyads: How a Third Party Enables Rationalist Explanations for War. Journal of Theoretical Politics 29 (3):353–81.10.1177/0951629816682884CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andres, Gannon, J., and Kent, Daniel. 2021. Keep Your Friends Close, But Acquaintances Closer: Why Weakly Allied States Make Committed Coalition Partners. Journal of Conflict Resolution 65 (5): 889918.Google Scholar
Garver, John. 1994. Polemics, Paradigms, Responsibility, and the Origins of the US–PRC Confrontation in the 1950s. Journal of American–East Asian Relations 3 (1):134.10.1163/187656194X00166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibler, Douglas M. 2008. The Costs of Reneging: Reputation and Alliance Formation. Journal of Conflict Resolution 52 (3):426–54.10.1177/0022002707310003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldfien, Michael A., Joseph, Michael F., and McManus, Roseanne W.. 2023. The Domestic Sources of International Reputation. American Political Science Review 117 (2):609628.10.1017/S0003055422000855CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goncharov, Sergey, Lewis, John, and Xue, Litai. 1993. Uncertain Partners: Stalin, Mao and the Korean War. Stanford University Press.10.1515/9781503622111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hao, Yufan, and Zhai, Zhihai. 1990. China’s Decision to Enter the Korean War: History Revisited. China Quarterly 121:94115.Google Scholar
Haynes, Kyle. 2019. A Question of Costliness: Time Horizons and Interstate Signaling. Journal of Conflict Resolution 63 (8):1939–64.10.1177/0022002718822719CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haynes, Kyle. 2024. Arms Transfers and Extended Deterrence. Journal of Politics 86 (3):983–96.10.1086/729960CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haynes, Kyle, and Yoder, Brandon K.. 2020. Offsetting Uncertainty: Reassurance with Two-Sided Incomplete Information. American Journal of Political Science 64 (1):3851.10.1111/ajps.12464CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hearder, Harry. 1996. Clarendon, Cavour and the Intervention of Sardinia in the Crimean War, 1853–1855. International History Review 28 (4):819–36.10.1080/07075332.1996.9640764CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henry, Iain D. 2020. What Allies Want: Reconsidering Loyalty, Reliability, and Alliance Interdependence. International Security 44 (4):4583.10.1162/isec_a_00375CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horowitz, Michael C., Poast, Paul, and Stam, Allan C.. 2017. Domestic Signaling of Commitment Credibility: Military Recruitment and Alliance Formation. Journal of Conflict Resolution 61 (8):1682–710.10.1177/0022002715612576CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iriye, Akira. 1989. Japan’s Drive to Great-Power Status. In Cambridge History of Japan, Vol. 5: The Nineteenth Century, edited by Jansen, Marius, 721–82. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CHOL9780521223560.014CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iwanami, Yukari. 2024. Asymmetric Burden-Sharing and the Restraining and Deterrence Effects of Alliances. Journal of Peace Research 61 (5):711–25.10.1177/00223433231158146CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Izumikawa, Yasuhiro. 2018. Binding Strategies in Alliance Politics: The Soviet–Japanese–US Diplomatic Tug of War in the Mid-1950s. International Studies Quarterly 62 (1):108120.10.1093/isq/sqx070CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jakobsen, Peter Viggo, and Rynning, Sten. 2019. Denmark: Happy to Fight, Will Travel. International Affairs 95 (4):877–95.10.1093/ia/iiz052CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 1978. Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma. World Politics 30 (2):167214.10.2307/2009958CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 1988. War and Misperception. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 18 (4):675700.10.2307/204820CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, Jesse C. 2017. External Threat and Alliance Formation. International Studies Quarterly 61 (3):736–45.10.1093/isq/sqw054CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karawan, Ibrahim. 2015. Egypt and the Western Alliance: The Politics of Westomania? In The Middle East and the Western Alliance, edited by Spiegel, Steven, 163–81. Routledge.10.4324/9781315685205-11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Tongfi. 2011. Why Alliances Entangle But Seldom Entrap States. Security Studies 20 (3):350–77.10.1080/09636412.2011.599201CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Tongfi. 2016. The Supply Side of Security: A Market Theory of Military Alliances. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Koga, Kei. 2024. Tactical Hedging As Coalition-Building Signal: The Evolution of Quad and AUKUS in the Indo-Pacific. British Journal of Politics and International Relations 27 (1):109134.10.1177/13691481241227840CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kydd, Andrew H. 2005. Trust and Mistrust in International Relations. Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691188515CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kydd, Andrew H., and McManus, Roseanne W.. 2017. Threats and Assurances in Crisis Bargaining. Journal of Conflict Resolution 61 (2):325–48.10.1177/0022002715576571CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LaFeber, Walter. 1997. The Clash: A History of US–Japan Relations. Norton.Google Scholar
Langer, William. 1964. European Alliances and Alignments 1871–1890. Vintage.Google Scholar
Lanoszka, Alexander. 2022. Military Alliances in the Twenty-First Century. Wiley.Google Scholar
Lee, Bomi K. 2023. Triangles, Major Powers, and Rivalry Duration. Journal of Conflict Resolution 67 (6):1128–54.10.1177/00220027221134781CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leeds, Brett Ashley. 2003a. Alliance Reliability in Times of War: Explaining State Decisions to Violate Treaties. International Organization 57 (4):801827.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leeds, Brett Ashley. 2003b. Do Alliances Deter Aggression? The Influence of Military Alliances on the Initiation of Militarized Interstate Disputes. American Journal of Political Science 47 (3):427–39.10.1111/1540-5907.00031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leeds, Brett Ashley, and Johnson, Jesse C.. 2011. Defence Pacts: A Prescription for Peace? Foreign Policy Analysis 7 (1):4565.Google Scholar
Lowe, Peter. 1997. The Origins of the Korean War. 2nd ed. Addison Wesley Longman.Google Scholar
MacMillan, Margaret. 2007. Nixon and Mao: The Week That Changed the World. Random House.Google Scholar
Mastro, Oriana Skylar. 2019. The Costs of Conversation: Obstacles to Peace Talks in Wartime. Cornell University Press.10.7591/9781501732218CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mattes, Michaela. 2012. Reputation, Symmetry and Alliance Design. International Organization 66 (4):679707.10.1017/S002081831200029XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
McManus, Roseanne W., and Yarhi-Milo, Keren. 2017. The Logic of “Offstage” Signaling: Domestic Politics, Regime Type, and Major Power–Protege Relations. International Organization 71 (4):701733.10.1017/S0020818317000297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, Thomas. 1978. Australia in Peace and War: External Relations, 1788–1977. Australian National University Press.Google Scholar
Mombauer, Annika. 2013. The Origins of the First World War: Diplomatic and Military Documents. Manchester University Press.10.4324/9781315838090CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrow, James D. 1994. Alliances, Credibility and Peacetime Costs. Journal of Conflict Resolution 38 (2):270–97.10.1177/0022002794038002005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrow, James D. 2000. Alliances: Why Write Them Down? Annual Review of Political Science 3:6383.10.1146/annurev.polisci.3.1.63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nish, Ian. 2003. Origins of the Anglo–Japanese Alliance: In the Shadow of the Dreibund. In The Anglo–Japanese Alliance, 1902–1922, edited by O’Brien, Phillips Payson, 825. Routledge.Google Scholar
Otte, Thomas. 2007. The China Question: Great Power Rivalry and British Isolation, 1894–1905. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199211098.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poast, Paul. 2019. Arguing About Alliances. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rabinovich, Itamar. 2004.Waging Peace: Israel and the Arabs, 1948–2003. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rathbone, Mark. 2008. Piedmont in the 1850s. History Review 62:2831.Google Scholar
Raymond, Gregory. 2019. War As Membership: International Society and Thailand’s Participation in World War I. Asian Studies Review 43:132–47.10.1080/10357823.2018.1548570CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robb, Thomas, and Gill, David. 2019. Divided Allies: Strategic Cooperation Against the Communist Threat in the Asia-Pacific During the Early Cold War. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rupasov, Alexander I. 2024. The Crimean War and the Kingdom of Sardinia. Herald of the Russian Academy of Sciences 93:S303S308.10.1134/S1019331623090101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadat, Anwar el. 1978. In Search of an Identity: An Autobiography. Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Schelling, Thomas C. 1966. Arms and Influence. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Thomas. 2004. Alliances, 1815–1945: Weapons of Power and Tools of Management. In Systems, Stability and Statecraft: Essays on the International History of Modern Europe, edited by Wetzel, David, Jervis, Robert, and Jack, S. Levy, 192222. Palgrave MacMillan.10.1007/978-1-137-06138-6_10CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schultz, Kenneth A. 2005. The Politics of Risking Peace: Do Hawks or Doves Deliver the Olive Branch? International Organization 59 (1):138.10.1017/S0020818305050071CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schumann, Matt, and Schweizer, Karl. 2008. The Seven Years War: A Transatlantic History. Routledge.Google Scholar
Schweizer, Karl. 1987. The Seven Years War: A Systems Perspective. In Origins of War in Early Modern Europe, edited by Black, Jeremy, 242–60. John Donald.Google Scholar
Scott, Ivan. 1978. The Making of the Triple Alliance in 1882. East European Quarterly 12 (4):399422.Google Scholar
Selten, Reinhard. 1978. The Chain Store Paradox. Theory and Decision 9 (2):127–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shen, Zhihua, and Xia, Yafeng. 2015. Mao and the Sino–Soviet Partnership, 1945–1959: A New History. Lexington Books.10.5040/9781666999235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Bradley C. 2021. Military Coalitions and the Politics of Information. Journal of Politics 83 (4):1369–82.10.1086/711625CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Glenn H. 1984. The Security Dilemma in Alliance Politics. World Politics 36 (4):461–95.10.2307/2010183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Glenn H. 1997. Alliance Politics. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Spindel, Jennifer. 2023. Arms for Influence? The Limits of Great Power Leverage. European Journal of International Security 8 (3):395412.10.1017/eis.2023.3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, Kenneth. 1999. Heroic Diplomacy: Sadat, Kissinger, Carter, Begin and the Quest for Arab-Israeli Peace. Routledge.Google Scholar
Stueck, William. 1995. The Korean War: An International History. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sukin, Lauren, and Lanoszka, Alexander. 2024. Credibility in Crises: How Patrons Reassure Their Allies. International Studies Quarterly 68 (2):sqae062.10.1093/isq/sqae062CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szabo, Franz. 2007. The Seven Years War in Europe: 1756–1763. Routledge.Google Scholar
Tarar, Ahmer. 2023. Crisis Bargaining in the Shadow of Third-Party Opportunism. International Studies Quarterly 67 (2):sqad039.10.1093/isq/sqad039CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walter, Barbara F. 2006. Building Reputation: Why Governments Fight Some Separatists But Not Others. American Journal of Political Science 50 (2):313–30.10.1111/j.1540-5907.2006.00186.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, Max. 2021. Brokers of Conflict: On Subsidies, East Indian Trade, and the Electorate of Hanover in the Diplomatic Revolution of 1756. PhD diss., Columbia University.Google Scholar
Weathersby, Kathryn. 1993. The Soviet Role in the Early Phase of the Korean War: New Documentary Evidence. Journal of American–East Asian Relations 2 (4):425–58.10.1163/187656193X00149CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westad, Odd Arne. 1996. Fighting for Friendship: Mao, Stalin and the Sino-Soviet Friendship Treaty of 1950. Cold War International History Project Bulletin (8–9):224–26.Google Scholar
Westad, Odd Arne. 2003. Decisive Encounters: The Chinese Civil War, 1946–1950. Stanford University Press.10.1515/9781503620094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Allen S. 1960. China Crosses the Yalu: The Decision to Enter the Korean War. Macmillan.10.1515/9781503620728CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wivel, Anders. 2020. Constant Activism in a War with No End: Security, Status and Strategic Culture in Danish Foreign Policy. Internasjonal Politikk 78 (3):411–20.10.23865/intpol.v78.2536CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolford, Scott. 2014. Showing Restraint, Signalling Resolve: Coalitions, Cooperation and Crisis Bargaining. American Journal of Political Science 58 (1):144–56.10.1111/ajps.12049CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolford, Scott. 2015. The Politics of Military Coalitions. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781316179154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolford, Scott. 2023. Great Power Intervention and War. International Studies Quarterly 67 (1):sqad003.10.1093/isq/sqad003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yang, Kuisong. 2002. Changes in Mao Zedong’s Attitude Toward the Indochina War, 1949–1973. Working paper 34, Cold War International History Project.Google Scholar
Yarhi-Milo, Keren, Lanoszka, Alexander, and Cooper, Zack. 2016. To Arm or to Ally? The Patron’s Dilemma and the Strategic Logic of Arms Transfers and Alliances. International Security 41 (2):90139.10.1162/ISEC_a_00250CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoder, Brandon K. 2019a. Hedging for Better Bets: Power Shifts, Credible Signals, and Preventive Conflict. Journal of Conflict Resolution 63 (4):923–49.10.1177/0022002718772349CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoder, Brandon K. 2019b. Retrenchment As a Screening Mechanism: Power Shifts, Strategic Withdrawal, and Credible Signals. American Journal of Political Science 63 (1):130–45.10.1111/ajps.12395CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoder, Brandon K. 2020a. Power Shifts, Third-Party Threats, and Credible Signals: Explaining China’s Successful Reassurance of Russia. International Politics 57 (5):885917.10.1057/s41311-019-00183-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoder, Brandon K. 2020b. Reassurance with Multiple Audiences. Unpublished manuscript, Australian National University, Canberra.Google Scholar
Zhang, Baichun, Zhang, Jiuchun, and Yao, Fang. 2006. Technology Transfer from the Soviet Union to the People’s Republic of China: 1949–1966. Comparative Technology Transfer and Society 4 (2):105167.10.1353/ctt.2006.0024CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, Ketian. 2025. Alliances with Chinese Characteristics? The Contents and Rationale of China’s Strategic Partnerships. International Politics, published online 2 June.10.1057/s41311-025-00701-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Spatial graph of actors’ preferences and types

Figure 1

Figure 2. Extensive form of the baseline model (R’s payoffs omitted for legibility)

Figure 2

Figure 3. A’s equilibrium response for the baseline model. Arrows indicate the effect of having alliance at stake

Figure 3

Figure 4. A’s equilibrium response for the model extension. Arrows indicate the effect of having alliance at stake

Supplementary material: File

Yoder and Cohen supplementary material

Yoder and Cohen supplementary material
Download Yoder and Cohen supplementary material(File)
File 326.5 KB