4.1 Introduction
Imagine it is 2060. Wild weather has swept through The Netherlands. The famous system of Delta Works has kept North Sea surges at bay, but the Rhine River has flooded, transforming swathes of the country into an inland sea (KNMI 2015).Footnote 1 Justice N’Doure from Senegal has just received news that her place of work – the International Court of Justice (ICJ) located in the Peace Palace in The Hague – will be temporarily moved to higher ground in the east of the country. She has been informed that personal belongings from offices in the building may be collected from a checkpoint near the Peace Palace. N’Doure has recently travelled from heatwave conditions in Senegal, which have devastated her country’s crops. She finds an emergency worker willing to take her by boat to the checkpoint. As they approach, she notices that the contents of the Peace Palace library have been swept out by the floodwaters, and books are floating away. She reaches over the gunwale of the boat and picks up a tome. By a strange twist of fate, it is the 2025 volume of the Annual Reports of the International Court of Justice, which contains judgements of the Court in its Advisory Opinion on climate change.Footnote 2 The volume is water-damaged but still readable. She begins to read.
Of course, no one knows what the world will look like in 2060 (or 2080 or 2100) but the scene sketched here is within the current (grim) predictions of scientists. The point of this story is to highlight a theme of this chapter: that climate change requires a reconsideration of traditional concepts of legitimacy in relation to institutions. This new understanding of legitimacy will need to embrace a more expansive concept than has previously been utilised, given that projected climate impacts pose serious risks to the entire international society and its institutions. As we shall see, concepts that have worked up until now need to be modified to be made fit for purpose in this new reality.
Elsewhere in this book, we argue that the democratic ideal of inclusivity provides a powerful rationale for proxy-style representation of future generations. We note, however, that representative-style institutions or mechanisms are only one possibility: mainstreaming future generations’ interests in policy- and law-making may be more effective. Thus, new institutions for future generations require justification. Such justification can be made against the baseline of having no such institutions (non-implementation baseline) or in comparison to other competing proposals (comparative baseline) (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 141). To illustrate, is creating a new UN Special Envoy for Future Generations a better option than not having such an institution? Alternatively, is such an institution comparatively more effective when assessed against other proposals (relative baseline) proposed at this particular time and place, involving, for example, mainstreaming future generations’ interests in various existing programmes and policies (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 141)?
Effectiveness is only one of several criteria for justifying and evaluating such institutions. Simon Caney’s influential framework for evaluating institutions for the future involves the following criteria: effectiveness, moral legitimacy, political sustainability, and political accessibility (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 140–42).Footnote 3 Legitimacy and effectiveness are closely related to the values of justice, solidarity, and vulnerability elaborated in Chapter 3. While justice, solidarity, and vulnerability represent, in a way, the foundations of the democratic idea, legitimacy and effectiveness represent formal criteria that are necessary for the material values to be implemented in the political processes. There is, therefore, a complementary relationship between them.
Assessing the effectiveness of institutions oriented towards the future presents challenges. One obvious challenge is that the effectiveness of a particular institution cannot be assessed until the future unfolds. Moreover, if we seek to assess long-term effectiveness, this creates a clear challenge. On the other hand, this problem can be overstated: it will be evident to varying degrees when assessing the effectiveness of any institution. One way of (at least partly) overcoming this challenge is to consider the performance of comparable institutions. For example, Jonathan Boston (Reference Boston2016) suggests that, when considering the possible effectiveness of an ombudsman for future generations, we could look at the empirical record of comparable ombudsman for children or other vulnerable groups. Measuring effectiveness can involve using an internal yardstick (an institution’s own objectives) or an external yardstick (whether an institution addresses a problem more broadly). In this chapter, we use a hybrid approach that combines both elements.
It is also important to note at the outset that we define ‘effectiveness’ broadly. It is not limited to monetary values, which can flow from an uncritical, neoliberal-type framing. Thus, a particular institution for future generations may be effective in a broader sense of promoting particular values that filter through to policy-making, which then promotes more favourable values from a justice and democracy point of view – even where an economic rationalist evaluation would find it difficult to quantify the exact impact of the particular institution in monetary terms.
We turn first to a general discussion of criteria for evaluating proxy-style institutions for future generations (Section 4.2), then proceed to elaborate criteria for assessing the democratic legitimacy of international institutions (Section 4.2.1) and international tribunals (Section 4.2.2), before turning to criteria for effectiveness (Section 4.2.3), accessibility, and political sustainability (Section 4.2.4). We conclude with some final observations (Section 4.3).
4.2 Criteria for Evaluating Institutions to Represent Future Generations
Both the legitimacy and effectiveness criteria elaborated in this chapter involve value judgements embedded in normative framings. These include an intergenerational justice value – reflected in the idea that future generations should enjoy the human rights necessary to lead a decent life, and their full range of capabilities, as well as a democratic value with the idea that future people should enjoy the capacity to govern themselves effectively (Hoffmann & Dijk Reference Hoffmann and Dijk2023). This entails the idea that the interests of future generations should be protected by enabling their participation in contemporary deliberative practices through proxy representation. Consistent with the pragmatist methodology of this book, these criteria involve an incremental extension of the application of existing values to new contexts.
Effectiveness is, in turn, linked to accessibility and political sustainability. Accessibility refers to the political feasibility of a reform proposal, addressing the question of whether it is likely to be implemented in the real world. A proposed reform might be attractive from a normative point of view but score low on accessibility, meaning that it ultimately lacks effectiveness because it is unlikely to be implemented. Political sustainability refers to whether a reform proposal will be sustained into the future, which, again, is a precondition for its ultimate effectiveness.
4.2.1 Democratic Legitimacy of International Institutions
It is crucial to proceed with a clear understanding of the interrelated concepts of legitimacy and effectiveness. In this book, we apply the following criteria to assess the democratic legitimacy of international institutions.
(a) Procedural (input legitimacy), involving inclusive/fair representation, accountability, and transparency and deliberation (discursive quality);
(b) Source-based (input legitimacy), involving expertise, legal legitimacy, tradition, and discourse; and
(c) Substantive (output legitimacy), involving effectiveness and equity.
The criteria are derived from Sylvia Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Antto Vihma (Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 405), Klaus Dingwerth (Reference Dingwerth2007, Reference Dingwerth2014: 1124–47), and Daniel Bodansky (Reference Bodansky1999).Footnote 4 The criteria for legitimacy of Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma and Bodansky are for legitimacy tout court. Recognising that democratic principles are not the only basis for legitimacy, Dingwerth (Reference Dingwerth2007: 28, 34) argues convincingly that including deliberation strengthens legitimacy, as it involves greater participation of those affected and also entails a discursive quality of the rule-making process. Democratic legitimacy also meshes well with the rationale for proxy-style mechanisms of representation argued for in Chapter 3. The criteria set out earlier are tailored to the context of this book, which includes both the decisions of international tribunals – the ICJ (Chapter 6) and UN Rights of the Child Committee (Chapter 7) – and an international institution for future generations, a proposed UN Special Envoy for Future Generations (Chapter 8). Each criterion is explained later.
It is important to note that we use legitimacy to refer to normative, rather than sociological or subjective legitimacy. Normative legitimacy refers to whether a claim of authority is well founded in some objective sense. Sociological or subjective legitimacy refers to societal acceptance of authority as a sociological fact (Bodansky Reference Bodansky1999: 601; Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen & Vihma Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 409).
Legitimacy and effectiveness are distinct but strongly interconnected concepts. Under these criteria, on the one hand, substantial effectiveness (output legitimacy) contributes to democratic legitimacy. On the other hand, meeting the requirements of the various elements of procedural (input legitimacy) in turn contributes to effectiveness. Section 4.2.2 sets out specific criteria for the democratic legitimacy of international tribunals (a subset of the broader category of international institutions), before turning to deal with the effectiveness of both international tribunals and institutions for future generations more generally (Section 4.2.3).
The criterion of input or procedural legitimacy involves ‘inclusive representation’ and captures the idea that, for a decision to be democratically legitimate, all those affected by the decision should have a say in the making of the decision: the ‘all affected principle’ (AAP) (Ball Reference Ball, Dobson and Eckersely2006: 137; Goodin Reference Goodin1996: 835; Goodin Reference Goodin2007: 40; Pitkin Reference Pitkin1967: 209). Future generations cannot participate directly in decisions being made now in relation to climate change but can do so through a proxy. The proxy can make reasonable assumptions about the interests of future generations, referring to their vulnerability and including their need for the stable climate and functioning ecosystems upon which their welfare will depend (Vanderheiden Reference Vanderheiden2008: 129). In addition, while beyond the scope of this book, the mandate of a proxy should also reflect moral duties to ecosystems and non-human species (Hoffmann & Dijk Reference Hoffmann and Dijk2023: 79).
In the context of proxy representation of future generations, youth representation of future generations can enhance legitimacy. While the findings of empirical research on whether young people are more concerned about the future than older people are mixed (Gonzalez-Ricoy & Rey Reference Gonzalez-Ricoy and Rey2019: 7), the interests of young people overlap significantly more with the interests of persons not yet born than do the interests of older people. Moreover, climate change will threaten the interests of people who are now younger over a larger span of their lives than the interests of people who are now older. Reflecting this truth, young people have initiated school strikes around the world, as well as launching climate litigation, where they purport to speak not just on behalf of their own interests, but also on behalf of future generations (Donger Reference Donger2022).
The sub-criteria of ‘accountability and transparency’ are problematic in the context we are discussing because it would seem impossible to hold a proxy for future generations accountable to persons not yet born. Nevertheless, accountability can (at least indirectly) be achieved by ensuring that the proxy operates consistently with a mandate that reflects the interests of future generations (Lawrence Reference Lawrence, Cordonier Segger, Szabó and Harrington2021: 607). Moreover, the proxy could be held to account by non-governmental organisations (NGOs) having a role in monitoring the proxy’s performance. Transparency in the proxy’s activities is an important precondition for this monitoring to take place (Hale Reference Hale2008: 73).
The sub-criterion ‘deliberation’ reflects the view that the process of deliberation is an essential element of democratic legitimacy, according to theories of deliberative democracy (Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007: 23). As Dryzek and colleagues observe:
Deliberative democracy reconceptualizes governance as effective, inclusive, and transformative communication encompassing citizens and policymakers. The basic idea, applicable globally no less than at other levels of governance, is that the legitimacy of any collective decision rests on the right, capacity, and opportunity of those subject to or affected by that decision (or their representatives) to participate in deliberation that is consequential for the content of the decision
Deliberation is often seen as a vehicle for conveying citizen’s views to representative institutions, thereby ensuring their democratic nature (Saward Reference Saward2008). According to this approach, ‘deliberation’ must have particular attributes to be a touchstone of democratic legitimacy: it must be free of coercion and involve participants who give reasons for their proposals and are willing to critically assess others’ proposals oriented towards reaching a consensus based on reasoned argument (Dingwerth Reference Dingwerth2007: 24, 31).
In Chapter 3, we demonstrated that deliberative democracy is a central approach within the debate on democratic theory. By focusing on the institutionalisation of the process of opinion and will formation through various forms of (proxy) representation, this approach is promising in terms of its theoretical and practical implications for the institutional recognition of future generations. Deliberative democracy provides a strong justification for a proxy to represent the interests of future generations in the deliberative process.Footnote 5 Indeed, Dryzek and Niemeyer (Reference Dryzek and Niemeyer2008: 481) have argued in favour of a particular version of deliberation that involves articulating discourses rather than positions. If we consider proxies for future generations articulating the interests of persons not yet born, rather than representing them as such, this opens the possibility of a new mechanisms, such as a UN Special Envoy for Future Generations, meeting this criterion (see Chapter 8).
In Japan, social experiments in deliberative democracy have assigned particular groups to represent future generations (as of 2060) and others to represent existing generations (Hara et al. Reference Hara, Yoshioka, Kuroda, Kurimoto and Saijo2019: 1609; see also Uwasu et al., Reference Uwasu, Kishita, Hara and Nomaguchi2020). The groups were tasked with seeking consensus on policy priorities between these two groups. A fascinating result of these early studies is that negotiations between the groups resulted in a consensus in favour of a substantial number of policy priorities which favoured the interests of future generations (Hara et al. Reference Hara, Yoshioka, Kuroda, Kurimoto and Saijo2019: 1612). These studies suggest that human beings – when made fully aware of long-term impacts of policies – may be willing to support policies which benefit the interests of future generations. Moreover, representatives of future generations can negotiate on their behalf and creatively explore the possibility of finding policy settings which address both long- and short-term interests. Through this process, the aim would be to change the mainstream policy discourse to better reflect the interests of both current and future generations (Hara et al. Reference Hara, Yoshioka, Kuroda, Kurimoto and Saijo2019: 1615–16). In addition, proxy-style representatives of future generations could foster further similar types of social experiments and use the findings as a catalyst to move from such research experiments into real-life policy-making.
The criterion of ‘source-based legitimacy’ (input legitimacy) refers to information or knowledge that is seen as authoritative: expertise, legal legitimacy, tradition (including institutionalised processes which can be difficult to change), and discourses (Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen & Vihma Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 410–11).Footnote 6 In terms of proxy-style representatives of future generations, ‘expertise’ could refer, for example, to the knowledge that a UN Special Envoy for Future Generations has (or could draw upon) in relation to the types of policies which are most likely to be effective in relation to protecting the interests of future generations. A well-resourced UN Special Envoy (with expert staff) would increase its legitimacy (expertise). Such a mechanism could also draw on scientific expertise in relation to the impact of climate change on future generations by relying on the authoritative reports of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) and consulting with this body.
‘Legal legitimacy’ involves authority based on being in accordance with law, which at the international level involves institutions acting in a manner consistent with the treaty which has established them – which, in turn, derives its legitimacy from states’ consent to it (Bodansky Reference Bodansky1999: 604–5).
‘Tradition’ as a source of legitimacy can include, for example, the legitimacy of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) and Paris Agreement (2015) regime as the legitimate form of intergovernmental governance to address climate change (Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen & Vihma Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 410).Footnote 7 The case studies in this book involve innovative forms of proxy representation of future generations, involving new institutions (for example, the UN Special Envoy for Future Generations) and existing institutions taking on new roles (for example, the ICJ and the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child). The legitimacy of these forms may be enhanced by the existing legitimacy of the institutions in question; even the legitimacy of the new UN Special Envoy may be affected by the perceived legitimacy of similar UN special envoys.
The sub-criterion of ‘discourse’ can involve legitimacy being linked to particular discourses that are perceived as authoritative by relevant stakeholders. In this book, we draw on elements of discourses that already enjoy considerable support to justify proxy-style mechanisms for the representation of future generations, such as discourses relating to solidarity and sustainable development, which includes the principle of intergenerational equity. These discourses can help justify and bolster the legitimacy of new, proxy-style institutions for future generations (see Section 8.2). But some versions of sustainable development that prioritise development over sustainability can work in the contrary direction (see Section 8.5).
Concepts of sustainability and intergenerational equity have a particular legal form and thus constitute legal discourses that have been taken up both in global climate negotiations in the UN system and in climate litigation around the world. Indeed, policy-makers have started to come under pressure from legal action taken against governments using international tribunals – climate litigation – which gives rise to questions about the democratic legitimacy of such tribunals.
The criterion ‘substantive (output legitimacy)’ covers effectiveness (see further 4.2.3). In this book, we treat effectiveness as a distinct criterion but note that enhancing effectiveness can contribute to the overall legitimacy of a mechanism or institution through its effect on output legitimacy.
Equity as a sub-criterion reflects the idea that substantive legitimacy involves both contributing to solving a particular problem and improving justice. Given the context of extreme global inequality, it is crucial that mechanisms do not just change behaviour or solve a particular problem, but also enhance justice. The connection with effectiveness is that norms or mechanisms perceived to be both legitimate and fair are more likely to be complied with (Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen & Vihma Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 413).
A weakness in the criteria for democratic legitimacy set out earlier is that they rest on deliberative practice only up to the present time, without in any way involving the practice or voices of future generations. This problem can be addressed by expanding our understanding of legitimacy. When political decisions are made that affect future generations, from a democratic theoretical perspective (which aims at the integration of all those affected by a decision), these decisions can only be considered legitimate if they appropriately consider the impacts on future generations’ needs or interests.Footnote 8 Legitimacy only makes sense, then, if it is understood as also including what we refer to as ‘future legitimacy’. This can also be justified from a normative standpoint: because, if decisions do not recognise and consider the needs and living conditions of future generations, they also disregard their vulnerability and cannot be considered legitimate from the standpoint of intergenerational justice.
The concept of ‘future legitimacy’ is underpinned by the concept that all generations are of equal value, thus requiring an assessment of legitimacy in terms of both current and future generations. Assessing a new UN Special Envoy for Future Generations against this benchmark would thus require an evaluation from the perspective of future generations. This, in turn, requires imagining that one is living decades in the future, in a world that is increasingly negatively impacted by climate change, and looking back to determine whether such a UN Special Envoy created now was sufficient to address the underlying threat posed by climate change to the international community and all its institutions, with all the consequences for intergenerational justice entailed in this threat.
An objection to this concept of ‘future legitimacy’ could be raised on the grounds that it would inherently prioritise the interests of future generations over current generations. To address this problem, it could be argued that the overarching legitimacy of a particular international institution must be based on the area of overlap between its legitimacy as traditionally understood – what we will refer to as ‘present legitimacy’ – and its ‘future legitimacy’. This would ensure that legitimacy was conceived in a manner which – in terms of its normative framing – did not prioritise either future or current generations’ interests but sought to maximise both.
4.2.2 Democratic Legitimacy of International Tribunals
International tribunals can be considered a subset of the broader category of international institutions. At a general level, therefore, the democratic legitimacy of such tribunals is related to the extent to which they fulfil the criteria (elaborated earlier) which apply to all international institutions. We will see, however, that these criteria require some adaptation to the specific functions that international tribunals perform.
The function of such tribunals is not singular, but includes the resolution of disputes, clarification of international law rules, and the promotion of justice (to which we will return in a moment). The functions of the ICJ are set out in its Statute – a treaty – which refers to the function of the Court as being to ‘decide in accordance with international law such disputes as are submitted to it’ (Statute of the International Court of Justice 1945: art. 38). At a formal level, the authority of the ICJ – and therefore its legitimacy – is derived from state consent to this treaty (Merrills Reference Merrills2011: 116–19). At first blush, it would seem that the Court should only apply international law and not develop it, but, on closer examination, the ICJ has several implicit functions. These include – as the principal judicial organ of the United Nations – supporting the UN’s overall goal of maintaining peace and security and settling international disputes ‘in conformity with the principles of justice and international law’ as expressed in the Charter of the United Nations (1945: art. 1(1); Giladi & Shany Reference Giladi, Shany, Espósito and Parlett2023: 107).Footnote 9 A further implicit function is the role of the Court in developing, not just applying, international law (Giladi & Shany Reference Giladi, Shany, Espósito and Parlett2023: 107). Indeed, commentators point out that the ICJ plays a much more activist role than is apparent from looking its Statute (Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bodandy and Venzke2013: 52–7). Thus, where international law rules are unclear, the ICJ plays an important law reform role through interpreting rules in a particular direction or even further developing rules in a way that allows international law to adapt to new circumstances, in a manner extending well beyond the role of the Court as described in its Statute (Tams & Tzanakopoulos Reference Tams and Tzanakopoulos2010).
Our argument is that, where international tribunals perform this function, courts such as the ICJ should undertake this task by applying a normative framework, according to which the role of the court – whatever other functions it has – should be the promotion of justice, extended to include intergenerational justice.Footnote 10 Thus, the first prong of our argument is that the effectiveness of the ICJ rests on the extent to which the tribunal acts to promote justice, extended to include intergenerational justice. This rests on the argument that furthering justice is an implicit goal of the Court. As we have seen, furthering equity or justice is a criterion for assessing output legitimacy, which involves examining closely the function or goals of the particular institution. Importantly, this is also a criterion for effectiveness, given this has been defined as including equity (see text described earlier).
In making this argument, we note that this does not preclude international tribunals also playing a key role in promoting other values, such as the resolution of disputes and the facilitation of trade. Our argument is that international tribunals ought to promote justice and, thus, protection of the most vulnerable groups. This rests on the fact that the international community has accepted in the Charter of the United Nations (1945: art. 1(3)) and a raft of global human rights instruments, including the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UNGA 1948), the idea that all people, regardless of when and where they are born, are entitled to human rights (Beyleveld, Düwell & Spahn Reference Beyleveld, Düwell and Spahn2015; Lawrence & Köhler Reference Lawrence and Köhler2018: 645–46). It flows from this that the international legal order should promote justice defined as ensuring the protection of human rights (Buchanan Reference Buchanan2004; Ratner Reference Ratner2015).
If one accepts that the international legal order should promote justice defined as protection of human rights, it follows that the legal order should also promote intergenerational justice, based on the premise that the entitlement to human rights is both universal and extends into the future (Caney Reference Caney and Humphreys2009).Footnote 11
To make the further argument that international tribunals ought to be democratically legitimate, we contend that several specific criteria must be met. These correspond with the general procedural (input legitimacy) criteria outlined earlier, which involve inclusive/fair representation, accountability, and transparency and deliberation (discursive quality). These criteria are modified to consider the context of international tribunals and the need to be responsive to the interests of future generations.
Thus, as a subset of all international institutions, international tribunals ought to be democratically legitimate and act on behalf of the people, the demos. In addition, the demos must be extended to include both current and future generations. Acting on behalf of the demos requires both:
impartiality and independence, in terms of ensuring procedural fairness in relation to court/tribunal processes; and
responsiveness to the demos, involving transparency, deliberation, and participation, including the involvement of affected individuals in the particular processes (von Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 151–2). (As we shall see in the case studies on international tribunals, this involves responsiveness to the interests of future generations through proxy-style procedural mechanisms.)
In addition, international tribunals must meet the requirements of output legitimacy (see further).
The content of these further requirements of democratic legitimacy in the context of international tribunals are drawn from principles developed in Western Europe under the Treaty on European Union (TEU) (EU 2008; Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 136 et seq.). These rules emerged through extensive deliberative processes involving democratic states over 20 years. Prima facie, this would seem open to criticism as being a narrowly Eurocentric approach; the answer to criticism is that these rules happen to have emerged in Europe but could have emerged anywhere (Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 136). Their validity stems from the strength of the deliberative process which gave rise to the principles and from the involvement of democratic states in this process (Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 137). Furthermore, there is a strong link to the pragmatist methodology of this book, in that these elements of democratic legitimacy have been proven to work well in practice.
As mentioned earlier, international institutions need to meet criteria of current and future legitimacy. Assessing an international tribunal and its decisions against the benchmark of future legitimacy would require making an evaluation (for example, of an ICJ Advisory Opinion on climate change decided in 2025) from the perspective of future generations. This, in turn, requires imagining that one is living in a future world looking back to determine whether such a decision taken by the Court was sufficient to address the underlying threat of climate change (to the international community and all its institutions, including the Court), with the consequences for intergenerational justice entailed in this threat.
As pointed out earlier, the overall legitimacy of an institution would be found in the area of overlap between present and future legitimacy, thus ensuring the maximisation of future and current generations’ interests.
Bringing these thoughts together, the legitimacy of an international tribunal (both present and future) is dependent on the extent to which it performs its functions (that is, linked to its effectiveness) and the extent to which it promotes justice (extended to include intergenerational justice) are integral to these functions. There is a tension here in that, if a tribunal such as the ICJ ignored its Statute and proceeded to invent international law rules in areas where the rules are clear, it would potentially undermine its legitimacy. As Julius Stone (Reference Stone1954: 368) pointed out, tribunals such as the ICJ are dependent on retaining legitimacy in the sense of state consent. An overly creative ICJ would very quickly undermine its legitimacy in this sense.
On the other hand, the concept of future legitimacy underscores the importance of legitimacy from the standpoint of future generations. This is vital in terms of adjusting the concept to the threat climate change poses to the very existence of all institutions, including the ICJ. This provides an additional lens for viewing legitimacy, which is more responsive to the context in which the law-making process takes place. Thus, an ICJ decision that was too timid in relation to the threat of climate change would undermine both its present and future legitimacy.
We can now map out criteria for assessing the democratic legitimacy of international tribunals and see how these relate to the overarching criteria applicable to all institutions set out earlier (Section 4.2.1). Thus, for the purposes of this book, the democratic legitimacy of an international tribunal is assessed on the extent to which it:
1. operates consistently with the treaty which establishes its mandate, to which states have consented – corresponding to the general criteria element of source based (input legitimacy) in the form of legal legitimacy;
2. operates based on procedures ensuring the inclusive and fair representation of both current and future generations with, in particular:
impartiality and independence in terms of ensuring procedural fairness in relation to court/tribunal processes; and
responsiveness to the demos, involving transparency, deliberation, and participation, including the involvement of affected individuals in the processes, with future generations involved through proxy-style procedural mechanisms.
appropriately considers the impacts on future generations, their needs, or interests, thus ensuring future legitimacy. This involves assessing legitimacy in terms of both current and future generations, with an evaluation being made as to whether a decision made by an international tribunal today would be legitimate from the perspective of future generations. (This could include imagining a world decade from now that has been increasingly negatively impacted by climate change and looking back to assess whether a decision taken by a particular tribunal today was sufficient to meet the needs of intergenerational justice.) These elements correspond to the general criteria elements of procedural (input legitimacy) involving inclusive/fair representation, accountability and transparency, and deliberation (discursive quality).
3. demonstrates expertise both in the form of legal expertise but also drawing on scientific knowledge relating to climate change – corresponding to the general criteria element of source based (input legitimacy) in the form of expertise; and
4. demonstrates output legitimacy defined in terms of taking decisions that:
◦ are effective both in terms of fulfilling the particular functions of the international tribunal as set out in its statute/mandate and contributing to strengthening international law rules relating to climate change and their implementation (see Section 4.2.3); and
◦ enhance substantive justice, extended to include intergenerational justice – corresponding to the general criterion of substantive (output legitimacy), involving effectiveness and equity applicable to all international institutions.
The case studies in this book on the ICJ and UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (see Chapters 6 and 7) demonstrate how the normative framework argued for in Part I can play a positive role in promoting intergenerational justice without undermining the legitimacy of the particular tribunal. These case studies demonstrate that there are possibilities for maximising current and future legitimacy.
4.2.3 Effectiveness
Caney (Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 137–40) points out that short-term policies are not harmful per se; on the other hand, short-termism can be extremely harmful in relation to problems like climate change, where it involves shifting the burden to the next generation. He observes that assessing the effectiveness of future-oriented institutions involves making a judgement about the extent to which such institutions overcome causes of wrongful short-termism; this is his key criterion for effectiveness (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 140). He also notes that the causes of harmful short-termism involve institutional and human psychological factors. On the institutional side in democracies, there is the harmful impact of short electoral cycles which induce politicians to focus on the short term, while ignorance of the future impact of policy-making is compounded by the dominance of lobbyists pushing short-term, sectoral interests. In addition, there are short-term media cycles, auditing processes, and performance indicators (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 137–46).
The climate crisis is an example of a creeping environmental problem where incremental impacts make it harder to galvanise support for decisive, responsive action. This is compounded by the lack of identifiable future victims – which are usually represented by abstract statistics. Psychological factors involving positive illusions, procrastination, and self-interest also play a role. Caney sensibly points out that institutional reform proposals need to seek to reduce the impact of underlying negative psychological factors, or at least prevent these factors from impacting the policy-making process. Where possible, he points to the possibility of harnessing these factors to promote long-term interests (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 145–6).
Increased input legitimacy can result in greater effectiveness, which can, in turn, contribute to legitimacy. Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma (Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009) define the concept of effectiveness as having two dimensions. First, effectiveness refers to the extent to which a norm, rule, or institution achieves a specified objective or goal in relation to a particular norm or institution. Second, ‘problem-solving effectiveness’ refers to how a particular norm can impact behaviour where this is required to solve a particular problem (Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen & Vihma Reference Karlsson-Vinkhuyzen and Vihma2009: 405).
We saw earlier that the output legitimacy criteria used here involve an effectiveness criterion defined in terms of how well the particular institution functions in meeting the goals set out in its mandate (as interpreted by the particular tribunal and its constituencies, in the case of international tribunals), as well as how well it contributes to the strengthening and implementation of international law rules relating to climate change. This has synergies with a goal or functions approach to assessing the effectiveness of international tribunals (Shany Reference Shany2012, Reference Shany2014). In the ICJ Advisory Opinion (Chapter 6) and UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (Chapter 7) case studies, this effectiveness assessment also factors in how well the tribunal addresses the questions put to it by the parties (in the first case) and by the UN General Assembly (in the second case).
The international law rules on climate change are mostly contained in the UN climate treaty regime and in customary international law. Turning to the former, we use the Paris Agreement (2015) as a yardstick or goal for measuring effectiveness in the climate change context. The objectives of the Paris Agreement are set out in Article 2(1) as follows:
This Agreement, in enhancing the implementation of the Convention, including its objective, aims to strengthen the global response to the threat of climate change, in the context of sustainable development and efforts to eradicate poverty, including by:
1. holding the increase in the global average temperature to well below 2°C above pre-industrial levels and pursuing efforts to limit the temperature increase to 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels, recognising that this would significantly reduce the risks and impacts of climate change;
2. increasing the ability to adapt to the adverse impacts of climate change and foster climate resilience and low greenhouse gas emissions development, in a manner that does not threaten food production; and
3. making finance flows consistent with a pathway towards low greenhouse gas emissions and climate-resilient development (Paris Agreement 2015).
In summary, the Paris Agreement objectives include the 1.5°C/2°C mitigation goal, adaptation, climate resilience, and sustainability, plus financial flows consistent with low emissions/climate-resilient development. The Paris Agreement objectives are to be read in conjunction with Article 3 of the UNFCCC (1992), which includes the principle of equity – including by implication intergenerational equity, albeit expressed vaguely.Footnote 12
Importantly, for our purposes, effectiveness is understood as including not only just the formal international law rules but also the potential for these rules to flow on to influence behaviour, of both states but non-state actors. This approach is consistent with Steinar Andresen’s concept of effectiveness, that is broken down into ‘output’, ‘outcome’, and ‘impact’ elements, which can sharpen analysis in this area (Andresen Reference Andresen, Rajamani and Peel2021: 990). The ‘output’ involves the formal rules of a regime. In contrast, the ‘outcome’ variable examines actual behaviour. ‘Impact’ refers to the problem-solving ability of a regime. Our case studies assess the outcome and impact of the mechanisms/institutions, while recognising the methodological challenges in drawing conclusions about causal links (Andresen Reference Andresen, Rajamani and Peel2021: 991).
Thus, in the case studies of proxy representation set out in Part III, we evaluate particular international mechanisms in terms of their effectiveness, defined in accordance with:
1) how well they promote justice (including intergenerational justice) and the values of inclusiveness, solidarity, and addressing vulnerability (a normative dimension);Footnote 13
2) how well they contribute to strengthening international law rules relating to climate change and their implementation, thus contributing to the modification of the behaviour of states and non-state and substate actors in the direction of these rules; and
3) in relation to international tribunals: how well they perform the functions specified in their particular statute both generally and in relation to the specific mandate for the particular case in question; for example, the UN General Assembly mandate for the ICJ Advisory Opinion on Climate Change (see Chapter 6) or the scope of the complaint, in the case of the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (see Chapter 7).
Element (b) is, in turn, defined in accordance with the Paris Agreement 1.5/2°C overarching mitigation target, adaptation for current and future generations, climate resilience, low greenhouse gas emission development, and financial flows consistent with low emissions/climate-resilient development. It also includes the extent to which the mechanism strengthens customary international law rules relating to state responsibility for climate-related harms, involving liability, restitution, and compensation.Footnote 14 While these rules are backward looking, they are nevertheless relevant in terms of future generations’ interests. This is because strong rules in this area can provide benefits for current generations but also incentives for the mitigation of greenhouse gas emissions, with positive consequences for future generations, and can also help fund adaptation efforts, both now and in the future.
Furthermore, we argue (see Section 6.5) that the ‘principle of harm prevention’ involving state responsibility for anthropogenic climate change-related harms should be extended to include harm to future generations. There are tensions here because some states are likely to be opposed to such an extension because it would conflict with their view that they should not be held responsible for past greenhouse gas emissions (Section 6.5). This highlights the fact that two of our case studies (Chapter 6 on the ICJ and Chapter 7 on the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child) involve mandates that combine ‘future-related’ elements with other ‘non-future related’ elements; for example, relating to international legal obligations for ongoing climate change related harm, and/or responsibility in relation to harm which has already occurred. This entails the particular tribunal balancing the interests of current and future generations, which will not always push in the same direction; this complicates the evaluation of effectiveness. This complication is not an issue in relation to the case study on the proposed UN Special Envoy for Future Generations (Chapter 8) because this involves a ‘future-oriented’ mechanism with a mandate envisaged to have a particular focus on future generations’ interests. The UN Special Envoy will most likely have a mandate to highlight such interests and feed this information to decision-makers who will have the task of balancing current and future generations’ interests.
We acknowledge that the functions of the ICJ, as set out in its Statute, and the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child are not to protect the climate system. However, as we demonstrate in the case studies, each tribunal has been tasked with examining international law rules broadly (in the case of the ICJ) and more narrowly (in the case of the UN Committee on the Rights of the Child)Footnote 15 in terms of their interaction with climate change. Further, given our argument that international tribunals should interpret international law rules in a manner that furthers justice (including intergenerational justice), we assess the extent to which these international tribunals, consistent with their particular mandates, interpret international legal rules in a manner which contributes to making more effective the substance and implementation of international law rules relating to climate change in a manner which furthers justice.
At this point, it is important to note the strong connection between democratic legitimacy and effectiveness. International tribunals that are democratically legitimate are more likely to be effective. Legal systems rely on subjects of the law accepting a court’s decisions to fulfil their functions (Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 154). Democratic processes usually promote acceptance (Bogdandy & Venzke Reference Bogdandy and Venzke2014: 155); for this reason, enhancing the democratic legitimacy of international tribunals tends to enhance their effectiveness.
This is consistent with scholars’ observations that international institutions that are perceived to be legitimate are likely to be more effective (Franck Reference Franck1990; Stokke & Vidas Reference Stokke and Vidas1998). Thus, we consider effective decisions of an international tribunal to be decisions which fulfil the particular functions of the tribunal or court as set out in its statute/mandate, as interpreted by the international tribunal and key constituencies. Given the climate change context of this book, we include the additional criterion that effectiveness is measured in terms of the contribution made by the decision of the international tribunal to strengthening international law rules relating to climate change.
The effectiveness of the decisions of these international tribunals needs to be considered broadly, in that their decisions interact with national law in a variety of ways. Thus, an ICJ advisory opinion (which is non-binding) might, for example, delineate principles of international environmental law which are then taken up by a national court in a climate litigation case and/or made binding or operative within a particular national legal order through incorporation in legislation. While under-researched to date, anecdotal evidence suggests that ICJ rulings do feed into professional discourses at both the national and global decision-making level (Giladi & Shany Reference Giladi, Shany, Espósito and Parlett2023: 117).
As we noted earlier, assessing the effectiveness of future-oriented institutions also encompasses the extent to which they address the causes of harmful short-termism. Thus, in evaluating whether institutional proposals to represent future generations contribute to achieving the Paris Agreement goals set out above, we take a broad approach to assessing how these particular goals will be furthered, including through addressing sources of far-ranging, harmful short-termism in relation to climate policy (including institutional and social psychology factors). One significant cause of harmful short-termism is lack of awareness of the long-term impacts of policies. Proxy-style institutions can play a helpful role in combating harmful short-termism by raising awareness of the long-term impacts of laws and policies. Global proxy-style institutions can also have a catalytic role in putting pressure on states to adopt appropriate institutions at the national level. These various dimensions are discussed in relation to each of the case studies.
As observed in Chapter 1, the ultimate effectiveness of proposed new institutions for future generations cannot be judged in advance. As Jonathan Boston cautions, designing institutions for future generations is ‘as much an art than a science’, given the complex causal factors involved in accounting for short-termism (Boston Reference Boston, Linehan and Lawrence2021: 96). Nevertheless, new proxy-type mechanisms for representing future generations have the potential to put pressure on existing institutions to better incorporate the interests of future generations in their decision-making processes. The increasingly catastrophic impacts of climate change – and mounting evidence that the status quo is clearly not working – suggest that experimental proxy-style institutional mechanisms to represent future generations should urgently be pursued, even where the likelihood of success is slim. Given the intergenerational dimension, it is vital to consider effectiveness in terms of both the probability and magnitude of success. Importantly, the strategy of exploring proxy-style mechanisms can be pursued in parallel with efforts to mainstream future generations’ interests in policy- and law-making.
4.2.4 Accessibility and Political Sustainability
In this context, accessibility refers to whether and how likely it is that we can get from ‘here’ to ‘there’ (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 142).Footnote 16 In other words, is a proposal likely to be implemented in the real world? Political sustainability refers to whether a proposed new institution can be sustained into the future – obviously a precondition for its effectiveness (Caney Reference Caney, González-Ricoy and Gosseries2016: 141). Here, factors include whether the institution is embedded in a constitution, for example, thus making it more difficult to dismantle. At the international level, this could include whether the institution is embedded in a global treaty – which can create some resistance to its being rapidly undone. The structure of finances is also crucial in this respect, in terms of whether an institution is vulnerable to budget cuts. This risk can be lessened, for example, if the budget necessary for a particular future-oriented institution is part of the core budget of an international organisation.
4.3 Final Observations
The argument we make in this chapter mirrors the argument made by John Dryzek in relation to the arrival of the Anthropocene, which has focused attention on human impacts on functioning global ecosystems, thus providing impetus for an urgent and compelling case for reform of global institutions. The Anthropocene entails the idea that human beings are a dominant source of change to the planet, including its climatic system (Keys et al. Reference Keys, Galaz and Dyer2019). Linked to this is mounting empirical evidence that the Earth’s climatic system is approaching tipping points with potentially catastrophic consequences (Michel, Swingedouw, & Ortegav 2022: 5176; see also Cho Reference Cho2021). This has led Dryzek (Reference Dryzek2015) to call for a rethink of political institutions, which should be tailored for this new era on the basis of ‘ecosystemic reflexivity’ as a first overriding virtue.Footnote 17 ‘Ecosystemic reflexivity’ involves integrating improved ways of listening to ecological systems – entailing broader participation of both nature and future generations – into human institutions (Dryzek Reference Dryzek2015: 12).
This idea of fundamentally rethinking institutions is reflected in the concept of future legitimacy introduced in this chapter, which involves expanding legitimacy to consider the existential threat climate change poses to international society, its legal system, and institutions.
Returning to the thought experiment which opened this chapter, when Justice N’Doure rereads the ICJ Report of the judgement in the climate change advisory opinion, she will inevitably read it through the contextual lens of 2060. By incorporating a thought experiment of this kind into our concept of legitimacy, we hope to demonstrate that it is possible to conceive of the idea of legitimacy in a way which more accurately reflects the climate change context. As we have already noted, there is a risk that this approach could favour intergenerational justice and the interests of future generations over the needs of contemporaries and intragenerational justice. However, this risk can be minimised by using the legitimacy criterion to cover those areas of overlap between the two frames of legitimacy (present and future) to ensure that we maximise both intragenerational and intergenerational justice and maximise effectiveness, given the link between legitimacy and effectiveness. We saw that some empirical studies have demonstrated that assigning persons to act on behalf of future generations can potentially lead to creative policy- and law-making that involves policy solutions which meet the interests of both contemporaries and future generations. This provides grounds for hope that proxy-style institutions for future generations can have positive impacts in policy- and law-making.
The effectiveness framework we present here involves criteria linked to the objectives of the Paris Agreement, as well as the idea that future-oriented institutions need to address the causes of harmful short-termism. While there are some clear-cut ways in which proxy-style institutions can serve this role – for example, through highlighting the impacts of rules or policies on future generations – it is striking that, to date, there is scant literature on how these processes work in relation to the particularities of international law and related institutions. International law and institutions are the creature of states, but they also have their own particular dynamics. International law does not operate directly within states but tends to be mediated through national institutions and mechanisms.Footnote 18 This poses further levels of complexity in terms of analysing how a particular proxy-style institution representing future generations can address causes of harmful short-termism. This constraint in analysing the effectiveness of proxy-style institutions at the international level is considered in the case studies in Part III. It is certainly an area where more research is needed to ensure reform efforts have the best chance of success.