In Poets as true Genius is but rare,
True Taste as seldom is the Critick’s share.
Hold thine own, and work thy will!
Year will graze the heel of year,
But seldom comes the poet here,
And the Critic’s rarer still.
Samuel Johnson: The Person and the Critic
The critical study of Johnson has burgeoned over time, and the rich variety of his reception on different terms and in different places is testament to his cultural reach.Footnote 3 Johnson is enjoyed both inside and outside the academic fold. His readership has traditionally extended to university students and to teachers of literature of the British eighteenth century, but the work of Johnson to a remarkable degree also speaks to learned professionals in areas of practice touched by his personal interests and expertise, including the law, politics, journalism and medicine. There remains a significant audience of common readers. Recent examinations of Johnson’s life and work address all these departments and, within the field of literary and critical history, perspectives have evolved with the progress of literature and criticism. As Hans-Georg Gadamer has argued in his reflections on “Historically Affected Consciousness,” “Historical tradition can be understood only as something always in the process of being defined by the course of events.”Footnote 4 The past does not change; but our perspective upon it does: Different parts of historical tradition come to light as the present fades into the past.
It is time, therefore, to return to Johnson’s writing about writing. Numerous book-length studies and scholarly analyses of Johnson have appeared since the end of the Second World War. And consequent in part upon the rise of an American “New Criticism,” an emphasis on the written texts has replaced the capacious image of the Victorian and Edwardian conversational sage fostered by Boswell’s Life of Johnson (1791).Footnote 5 One such volume is the 1952 monograph on Johnson as critic by Jean Hagstrum. In later years there have appeared theoretically engaged, themed investigations by such scholars as Steven Lynn (1992) and Charles Hinnant (1994).Footnote 6 At about the same time, nuanced commentaries by Fred Parker (1989, on the Shakespeare criticism) and Greg Clingham (2002, on the Lives) have helped bring life, mind and critical text together.Footnote 7 Many valuable studies have moreover addressed particular issues of Johnson’s criticism for anthologies, guides, selections or essay collections. Johnson’s critical and creative relation to specific poets prominent as subjects of his criticism has produced more extended treatments, and the 2010 study of Johnson’s Milton by Christine Rees is an eminent example.Footnote 8 All these items constitute the active, widely distributed life of the field, and no history of literary criticism could make acceptable sense without a chapter, or section, devoted to Johnson.Footnote 9 But over the last twenty years general monographs specializing in the criticism have proved rare.
Books on the criticism may never finally resolve the tensions between the critical writing and the person of Johnson, nor eliminate the mental paradigm shifts we have to make when measuring Johnson’s historical meaning against his critical pertinence. Nevertheless, set against the broad horizon of interest, this volume aims to consolidate bonds between the accessible traits of Johnson’s personality and the nature of his critical writings. “Johnson’s utterances are valuable,” Matthew Arnold has written, “because they are the utterances of a great and original man.”Footnote 10 And it is to capture productive tensions within this relationship that I emphasize throughout Johnson’s criteria of the heart. Johnson’s reading of many authors and works generates a corpus of emotional experience realized as principles of art. We identify the principles that Johnson derives from the best and the worst of poetry, and we see these standards in the light of his moral and intellectual commitments in contexts of life and literature; we compare one judgment with another; but we also relate Johnson’s poetical estimates to the large and complex personality actualized through critical judgment and the artistry he brought to its expression. “Judgment is forced upon us by experience,” writes Johnson in his “Life of Pope”: “He that reads many books must compare one opinion or style with another; and when he compares, must necessarily distinguish, reject, and prefer” (Lives, vol. iv, p. 5). Johnson defined the methods of his criticism in these remarks, and through them he pursued truth in literary judgment at a moral and even religious level.
Biographical and personal narratives “enchain the heart [of the reader] with irresistible interest,” writes Johnson (Rambler 60, Works iii, p. 319); the “mournful distraction of Ophelia fills the heart with tenderness” (Works viii, p. 1011). This latter remark evokes Johnson’s heartfelt response to the tragic heroine of Shakespeare’s Hamlet, but also recalls his openness to the plight of other female characters from the plays who inspire unguarded sympathy. The emotional register – again Johnson’s motive for elevating the pleasures of the biographical arts – is a point of reference, a criterion, a baseline of excellence.Footnote 11 A network of demands, technical, linguistic and intellectual, constitute Johnson’s test of art; but the heart’s role as a principle of judgment is primary.
Key Questions: History, Text and Context
The discussions which follow examine Johnson’s criteria from poetical, biographical, controversialist, philosophic, editorial and structural points of view. Each category permits me to consider one or more leading traits of Johnson’s intellectual and artistic personality. In one or another way, these traits focus present problems of interpretation, and they foreground aspects of Johnson’s critical character I have analyzed in previous studies composed over recent years at different times. I have adapted and rethought a number of earlier essays where appropriate; but I have also supplemented them in order to connect and complement their themes and to trace the path to new conclusions about Johnson and criticism. I present my selected topics for discussion as parts of a single critical-historical enterprise, an intellectual project in the history of criticism that makes Johnson its case in point. I hope thereby to enhance appreciation of Johnson’s critical integrity and to recognize more fully the heart of the man that is at the heart of the critical work.
I therefore explore at various stages the reasons for the reputation Johnson has acquired and how well this reputation is founded. How, I ask, might we continue to think historically while reading the texts of his criticism more closely; and what happens to our idea of his criticism when we make comparisons with figures commonly associated with Johnson or seeming to reflect the critical norms of his period? Behind the “Artistry and Thought” of my subtitle are touchstones of poetry, argument, philosophy, history, text and rhythm. Each art, constituent of art or object of artistic examination provides for evaluation of Johnson at a suitable level. Such terms draw attention to voice, emotional incitements, choice of language, models of thought, textual status, critical conduct and style and a way of listening to the language in the process of judging the criticism. I begin then by showing how Johnson’s critical expression conveys an experience as inspiriting as poetry – as if it were poetry, as if, that is, the organization of the words on the critical or biographical page functioned with a completeness and depth, a rhythm or pulse, or evinced a “latent meaning” more typically accorded to poetry than prose.Footnote 12 “His mind was so full of imagery,” writes his biographer Boswell, “that he might have been perpetually a poet” (Boswell, vol. v, p. 17). Johnson’s is one unaccredited variant of the “Impassioned Prose” that Virginia Woolf identified in her essay of that title when thinking of Sir Thomas Browne, Thomas De Quincey, John Ruskin, Emily Brontë, Thomas Carlyle and Walter Savage Landor.Footnote 13 But Johnson’s prose passion is not that of writers who have rebelliously sought innovation. There is no poetical unshackling of prose syntax nor sign of the streamed consciousness of Johnson’s great admirer and advocate, Virginia Woolf herself. “In the best examples of ‘impassioned prose,’” writes Woolf, “The prose writer has subdued his army of facts; he has brought them all under the same law of perspective. They work upon our minds as poetry works upon them.”Footnote 14 Johnson’s impassioned prose is a crafted product of what Christopher Ricks, following Coleridge, has called “The Best Words in the Best Order.”Footnote 15
The Poetry of Criticism
It is to this end that I examine how the modern American poet David Ferry has transformed into the music of poetry Johnson’s prose depiction of the physical disabilities endured by Alexander Pope (Lives, vol. iv, pp. 54–55). The pathos and pitch of this arresting section of the “Life of Pope,” highlighted by Ferry’s adaptation, I place alongside Johnson’s bleak narrative of the decline and death of Jonathan Swift (Lives, vol. iii, pp. 207–08). Together these two passages of personal tragedy reveal a liberating absence of sentimentality combined with a poignancy more intense for withholding explicit emotional display. There is doubtless an ingredient of what Carl Gustav Jung calls “objective cognition” or intellectual remoteness “in which the observer stays completely objective.”Footnote 16 But in both examples we see that Johnson joins detachment with an unshrinking grasp of what it means for human beings to suffer. The same sympathetic intelligence reappears in Ferry’s poem “That Evening at Dinner,” where we read back to the suffering humanity depicted within the Lives from Ferry’s poetical reworking of the devastating logic of Johnson’s review of Soame Jenyns’s Free Enquiry into Nature and Origin of Evil of 1757.
That Johnson suffers in his turn informs his critical practice. And here his mastery of Latin is a primary psychic shield of his emotional defences, a resort of Johnsonian classical expertise that restrains the indulgence of emotional excess. The distancing effect of the ancient language allows unbearable feeling expression. Two years after the death of his beloved Tetty, Johnson records in his diaries that “Fluunt lacrymae” (“The tears flow”; Works i, p. 53). It is only later, in one of the letters to Hester Thrale Piozzi of July 8, 1784, written after unwelcome news of her second marriage, the fallout that ensued and the agony of regret, that Johnson can dispense with the protections of Latin and write remorsefully to his old friend in his life’s last year that “The tears stand in my eyes” (Letters, vol. iv, p. 344). Remembering, in old age, the experience of being taught to swim by his father in the Lichfield mill-stream as a boy, Johnson composes “In Rivum a Mola Stoana Lichfeldiae Diffluentum” (“On the stream flowing away from the Stowe Mill at Lichfield”; Works vi, pp. 342–43), made English verse by Ferry as “The Lesson.” Translation brings out at this point how some memories may be too painful in any language but that of Latin.
Johnson’s emotional nature makes the heart the arbiter of final appeal in matters of critical resistance and preference. When feeling is absent from English poetry Johnson’s evaluations are strongly negative. His crushing remarks on Lycidas, a poem purporting to lament the death of a college friend via the fancies of pastoral cliché, are notorious. The Metaphysical poets, to their discredit, sacrifice what the heart requires to cold and clever conceits, and they emerge less excellent than they might have been. Even Dryden, the great poet of the last age, was not much acquainted with the “simple and elemental passions” (Lives, vol. ii, p. 148). Emotional language is embedded in Johnson’s most rigorously analytical passages. Thus, the spectator attending a play laments the tragic event not because any bad thing has happened in her own life but because the stage performance suggests what might. The plight of the audience is that of the mother who “weeps over her babe, when she remembers that death may take it from her” (Works vii, p. 78). But it is again restraint – when there is something to restrain – that wins Johnson’s strongest assent. He responds adversely to untoward displays of emotion in the greatest of literary practitioners: Shakespeare’s most celebrated declamatory speeches can be “commonly cold and weak” (Works vii, p. 73). The holding back of explicit emotion Johnson exalts in an exceptional scene from Henry VIII, his editorial commentary rejecting the pervasive sentimentalism of his day for something deeper.
Critical Contestation and Poetry’s Historical Remains
Ferry’s verse reimaginings of Johnson make “poetical” the right term for his tragically charged passages of “impassioned” biographical prose and cohere with his call for emotion in poems. In the discussions of Part ii, however, I turn to comparison between Johnson and critics of poetry who write with other criteria to the fore. Johnson’s own critical past has not completely faded and old arguments still count. To this end I examine the response by Johnson to a critical predecessor both feared and ridiculed in his day, the relentless antagonist of Pope, scorned among the “Dunces” of Pope’s great satire, the irascible John Dennis. First when writing on Shakespeare and then in his “Lives” of Addison and Pope (1781) Johnson engaged with Dennis at surprising length. He finds critical and human flaws of a serious kind but also the shared interest that makes rational disagreement possible. We see that Dennis engenders Johnson’s respect; together they preserve the tradition of bold disputatiousness that marks out English criticism.
By the time of Johnson’s maturity Dennis’s combative style had with some exceptions softened into the more detached demeanor of philosophical aesthetics, the critical abstractions of belles lettres or the vast unearthings of Johnson’s antiquarian contemporary Thomas Warton. In the second chapter of Part ii I compare and contrast Johnson’s and Warton’s arts of poetical history and I chart both unity of purpose and a parting of the ways. For Johnson’s learned colleague old poems revealed the “history of society” (Warton’s History, vol. ii, p. 209). In Johnson’s Lives of the Poets they enhanced the pleasures of the world in which he lived and they helped mitigate its pains. Warton was more willing to bear “the burden of the past,” but the distinction focuses their narrative methods more closely.Footnote 17 We find in Warton a new model of poetical history that is a major advance on earlier traditions of compendia, collections of “beauties” and biographical dictionaries of poets.Footnote 18 This stands in critical tension with the distinctive historical insights of Johnson’s Lives and discovers a different role for narrative in revealing the process of change over time in poetry.
The methods of Johnson and Warton, the one critical and the other antiquarian, nevertheless explain with joint authority how poetry “was brought into the State in which we now behold it.”Footnote 19 The logic of becoming is shared. Poetical history tells a story, records change, introduces new truth-claims into critical discussion, heightens consciousness of context and permits a combination of generalization, detailed analysis and direct quotation.Footnote 20 Historical form itself is opened to question. New narratives arise from the period’s broadening of taste as works hidden in the distant past of nonclassical poetry are retrieved for the present. “Literary history,” writes David Perkins, “differs from history because the works it considers are felt to have a value quite different from and often far transcending their significance as part of history. In other words, literary history is also literary criticism.”Footnote 21 In both Johnson and Warton we encounter “the history of poetry” as a critical genre; but a secondary effect is that the disciplines of history raise criticism above the rampant opinion-mongering, interest, party, peevishness and triumphalism of forms Pope had satirized and in which Dennis had revelled. Through closer assimilation of the critic to the historian, the critic of poetry attracted increasingly serious regard.
Thought, Life and Time
That Shakespeare’s plays contain thought, and are themselves acts of thought, has intrigued philosophers interested in the medium of thinking dramatically: I discuss their opinions in the first of two chapters of Part iii. The Johnson whose heart is touched by the fate of Ophelia appreciates Shakespeare more highly than any poet of his own age, and portrayals of human nature by Shakespeare he sees as preempting insights that formal methods of philosophy would later reveal. While the fashions of intellectual life change with time, Johnson famously notes that the world of Shakespearean dramatic representation expresses the uniformity of a “general nature” that both animates thought and qualifies its reach.
The second chapter of Part iii compares and contrasts Johnson and Montaigne and examines the promise of bringing them together. The late sixteenth-century Essais of Montaigne, translated by Shakespeare’s friend John Florio in 1603 and by Charles Cotton in successive editions from 1685, embrace the classics with a free-minded flexibility that a conventional “neoclassical” diagnosis cannot account for.Footnote 22 A banned book in France throughout the period,Footnote 23 Montaigne enjoyed prestige in the English eighteenth century, but his comparability with Johnson has rarely been developed very far. The results of such pairings can be unpredictable, providing a sideways look at the history of literature and the evolution of thought. As cases in point I highlight for comparison the “ondoyant et divers” (“wavelike and varying”) form and matter of Montaigne, the outlook of Johnson’s Shakespearean “mingled” drama and the consolatory philosophy of Rasselas.Footnote 24 That Johnson does not often refer explicitly to Montaigne does not rule out how treatments of pleasure, the nature of happiness, reading, life and death can suggest unforced parallels that should be pursued. Johnson enjoys parity with Montaigne in the extended community of European philosophical life on which Bacon and Erasmus had made their distinctive mark.
Part iv, “Time, Truth and History,” elaborates related issues in philosophy also pertinent to literary evaluation. While Time is a perplexity of philosophy it is evidently a “mode of existence” (“most obsequious to the imagination”) to which Johnson can appeal in making critical judgments. To this purpose I turn again to Johnson’s critique of the unities of place and time when defending Shakespeare (Works vii, pp. 75–81). Johnson advocates “general nature” as a critical test independent of historical time and examines the ironies of time’s passage in Rasselas. But he allows that poetry must sometimes be appreciated according to the norms and standards prevailing in its period of composition, as when he explains the changing tastes that had made Pope’s Iliad (1715–20) seem artificial by 1781. Other contexts include the burdens Pope imposed upon himself when he undertook the translation, began to see the labors ahead and realized that when running against Time he was doomed to come second. A melancholy sensitivity to time’s passing is a major anxiety throughout the Diaries, Prayers, and Annals collected in the Yale edition (Works i), and in his private moments time’s unnegotiable divisions of calendar and clock are a perpetual reminder to Johnson of his own fallings short under the eye of his Maker. When as a critic Johnson complains of tediously unendurable literary works he measures what is lost from life by reading them, a loss that cannot be regained.
In the second chapter of Part iv I examine how far Johnson prefers works based on actual events recorded in historical time. Could Johnson, whose criteria are of the heart, really be so literal-minded? I suggest that the “undisputed history” underpinning Dryden’s celebrated music ode Alexander’s Feast, and the same demand expressed in slightly different terms in connection with the story of Pope’s Eloisa (my two test cases), appear to add value for Johnson. In both of Johnson’s responses, historical narratives compound the experience of art and provide a stabilizing reality that checks unfettered fancy. But comparison with other Johnsonian judgments of poetical work also rooted in history reveals that an artistic dependence on real events verified by the historical record is no substitute for the imagined and imaginary world that brings the facts of history to life. The Truth that Johnson seeks from poetry, unclouded by the numinous or mystical – as these instances show – is something the heart must naturally favor.
Surveying the Whole
To probe the criteria of Johnson requires authoritative texts, and as part of understanding Johnson’s current accessibility as a critic I examine how new editorial procedures can mediate his critical significance, what these procedures have in common and how they diverge. Part v, “Editing Lives, and Life,” is one of the first assessments of the critical consequences for our evaluation of Johnson of two full-scale editions of the Lives, these being the first of such an ambitious nature to appear since 1905, when George Birkbeck Hill published his version in three volumes. I suggest how the new editions evidence the enduring stature of Johnson and I ask what editorial practices we should defend. The purpose is to get under the skin of the critic whose meanings we think we know well. The late editions bring fresh scrutiny to bear on the primary evidence of the text; their devotion to detail shows how much Johnson’s criticism has continued to matter, how much remains unknown or is now known for the first time. Roger Lonsdale’s editing of the Lives for Oxford University Press (2006) and the tireless efforts of the team of scholars who brought the Yale edition successfully to press (2010) recall Johnson’s own scholarly endurance.
In my final chapter, I suggest how the newly edited Lives illuminate a “latent meaning” and call upon our awareness of the collection’s abstract form. Johnson here offers a vision of life more complete and richer in detail than perhaps any other of his works, and this vision comes into sharper focus as his own life approaches its close. The illustration of personal experiences, authorial circumstance, degrees of skill, variations of style and states of mind evokes the “general nature” of a coherent poetical community that is a variety of human world. The play between tragic and comic biographical strokes, tension and release, elements of the remembered, the mistaken and the forgotten recall the incongruities and symmetries of the world created by Shakespeare’s “mingled” drama (Works vii, p. 66). The narrative transitions between “Lives” have artistic effects. We see that the Lives started out as a commercially driven project with inclusions largely determined by the London booksellers, but then became significantly transformed. Johnson reshapes the material of his commission by enlarging some prefatory remarks into book-length works; but he also evokes the flux of individual lives (and within “Lives”), and weaves a fabric of experience in his movements between them. Under this aspect one can fancy the Lives having more in common with the multiformity of Chaucer, Ovid or the Lucretian themes of Montaigne, or indeed Shakespeare, than any rule-bound neoclassic enterprise. The new editions help recover the whole work as a unit of value that cannot be found in selections and excerpted texts designed with easy accessibility in mind. The volumes restore an artistic organization lost to convenience and utility.
Cultural Displacement and the Judgment of the Heart
It is a measure of Johnson’s survival of historical change that he remains a target of the judgmental criticism he once practiced, and an Appendix to this study takes issue with the dismissive handling of his key judgments by one of the most formative and formidable British critics of the twentieth century, F. R. Leavis.Footnote 25 The arguments Leavis has with Johnson over Shakespeare and Milton show how criticism two hundred years after Johnson could employ strategies of critical history – conscious or unconscious – that limit his pertinence. I suggest ways in which Leavis contradicts himself when interpreting Johnson; but I also observe that Johnson has remained a critical antagonist worth arguing with, a last bastion – for Leavis and for others – of an archaic culture requiring displacement for criticism to move on. Leavis’s interaction with critical history, as I proceed to explain, gives an account of the culture of the critical past that is pointedly reductive. Histories of critical values, I suggest, may be traced on terms current within the period but subject to a less confidently ungrounded interpretation. “The sovereign Rule for treating of Manners,” writes René Rapin in Thomas Rymer’s powerful 1674 translation of the French critic,
is to copy them after Nature, and above all to study well the heart of Man, to know how to distinguish all its motions. ’Tis this which none are acquainted with: the heart of man is abyss, where none can sound the bottom: it is a mystery, which the most quick-sighted cannot pierce into, and in which the most cunning are mistaken.Footnote 26
Or as Rapin’s contemporary the poet Nicolas Boileau-Despréaux advocated in line 96 of Chant 3 of his versified L’art poétique: “aller au coeur la route la plus sûre.” (“to take the surest passage to the heart”).Footnote 27 So it is that when Johnson compares the merits of Joseph Addison’s celebrated tragedy of Cato with the greater dramatic power of Shakespeare’s Othello, he finds “artificial and fictitious manners” and “just and noble sentiments” delivered in “diction easy, elevated and harmonious.” But, crucially for Johnson, the hopes and fears of Cato “communicate no vibration to the heart” (Preface to Shakespeare, Works vii, p. 84). However numerous and strong the qualifications that Johnson makes, such a judgment is fatal.
Johnson’s criteria of the heart suggest a critical history ungoverned by the specters of a contemporary “neoclassicism,” a latter-day “liberal-humanism” or the cultural catch-all that Leavis typically prefers: the “Augustan.” (The list could be longer.) Reading Johnson’s criticism requires not jumping to the conclusions that find these classifications early, if at all. Critical inconsistency may be taken to prove a defective method and inferior intelligence. But much as the enigmas special to poetry invite us to read and read again the words of a difficult poem as they sink progressively deeper into our consciousnesses, so the artistry of Johnson’s criticism presents us with a textual and human experience that no overarching theorem could predict or contain. After all, “One cannot really speak of poetry,” as Friedrich Schlegel has observed, “except in the language of poetry.”Footnote 28 And a poem, according to Neil Astley in the Introduction to his poetical anthology Staying Alive, “lives in its language”: “the paraphraseable meaning is less than the poem itself.”Footnote 29 Johnson’s criticism, as Johnson called Dryden’s, is “the criticism of a poet” (Lives, vol. ii, p. 120) and comes hauntingly, melodiously and sometimes rapturously to life where paraphrase falls short. Johnson’s reputation as the great rationalist critic of the English tradition deserves full weight; but his criteria of the heart may be his own best guarantee of staying alive.