Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-nx7b4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-09-11T21:29:41.393Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Virtuous Life of Pleasure: Aristotle, Contemplation, and Corporate Sustainability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 September 2025

Melissa Fitzpatrick*
Affiliation:
https://ror.org/00xhj8c72 Loyola Marymount University , USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article sketches an answer to the call for a normative foundation for the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability and also enriches an understanding of firm objectives that ought to be otherwise than profit by offering a rendering of Aristotelian virtue ethics—what I call the virtuous life of pleasure—that highlights how contemplative activity or theorein cultivates, and is essential to, virtue and eudaimonia. My claim is that the virtuous life of pleasure not only characterizes how to live the most meaningful and pleasant life, rendering it good and thus worth pursuing, but it is also, as a flourishing life, the normative foundation for safeguarding the intrinsic value of nonfinancial corporate aims, as the paradox perspective prescribes. It does so by establishing a principle of enough, which seeks to preserve integral, interdependent parts as ends in themselves and as constitutive of a larger ecosystem.

Information

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for Business Ethics

The gravity of the ecological crisis is an enduring part of our daily reality, and businesses are among the most culpable for environmental degradation, due to their excessive toxic waste dumping, carbon emissions, and natural resource extraction (Johnsen Reference Johnsen2020; Shrivastava Reference Shrivastava1994). Stakeholders are increasingly demanding that firms embrace objectives beyond profit maximization (Lankoski and Smith Reference Lankoski and Smith2018), especially objectives that promote the health of the planet (Simon-Kucher 2024). As Johnsen (Reference Johnsen2020, 2) writes: “The prevailing mantra is that ecological degradation can be counteracted by businesses that develop and implement ecological solutions … and reconcile environmental concerns with economic profits.” Businesses ought to meaningfully commit to corporate sustainability—but how?

The mainstream defense of corporate sustainability is the “business case” (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023, 139), which views environmental initiatives as a means to the company’s economic bottom line—conditional variables in a firm’s cost-benefit analysis, vulnerable to quick elimination if they conflict with profit (Johnsen Reference Johnsen2020). The leading alternative to the business case is the “paradox perspective” (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2015), which heeds the challenge companies face to continue their core business practices while also, paradoxically, addressing environmental goals as ends in themselves. Although the paradox perspective is a promising alternative to the business case, it lacks a normative foundation, which would deepen our understanding of both why it should be, and how it can be, implemented (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018). Therefore, to justify a shift toward the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability and make it viable, we need a suitable moral grounding—that is, an account of why it is good and ought to be pursued (Scanlon Reference Scanlon1998)—that recognizes the reality of conflicting albeit co-constitutive goods and does not systematically subordinate some to others.

The main contribution of this article is to sketch a normative foundation for the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018) and to also enrich an understanding of firm objectives that ought to be otherwise than profit (Lankoski and Smith Reference Lankoski and Smith2018). To do so, I propose that we recollect Aristotle’s conception of what I call the virtuous life of pleasure, which is, I will argue, controversially anchored in Aristotle’s notion of contemplative activity or theorein. Footnote 1 Aristotle is clear that theorein, a fixed attention on and deep appreciation of intrinsic goods, is the most virtuous and pleasant activity that we are capable of as humans. It is vital to our well-being, for all walks of life, and it is also an essential foundation for our acquisition and practice of virtue, as it is what facilitates us cherishing and being motivated to protect what is intrinsically good as constitutive of the whole or common good. It is indeed bold to suggest that business, the world of productivity, ought to be more contemplative, but I will flesh out the ways in which the activity proper to it—the deep, pleasant appreciation of intrinsic value—normatively grounds virtuous behavior and the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability.

An important premise in my argument is that individual change agents—that is, company leaders—are those who decide to pursue sustainability as a corporate value, as organizational leaders have a substantial impact on corporate behavior (Visser Reference Visser2007; Hambrick Reference Hambrick2007). Core values in organizations derive from what company leaders take to be good and are largely driven by them. Thus, I will engage in analyses at both the individual level and the organizational level, applying the individual-level insights to the organization level. This premise is grounded in the Aristotelian view that corporations are ultimately expressions of the virtues (or vices) of the individuals who comprise them (Solomon Reference Solomon1999; Macintyre Reference Macintyre2007). Organizational values emerge from their “individual level origins,” that is, the individuals who think and make decisions on behalf of the organization (Balarezo and Corcuera Reference Balarezo, Corcuera, Castro and González-Masip2020; Bernacchio, Foss, and Lindenberg Reference Bernacchio, Foss and Lindenberg2024).

To make my case, I begin, in Section 1, by engaging the discourse on corporate sustainability and individual well-being in relation to the business case for corporate sustainability and the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability. I do this to set up Aristotelian virtue ethics, that is, Aristotle’s account of eudaimonia, as the most suitable normative ground for the paradox perspective, contra utilitarianism, which grounds the business case (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018). In Section 2, I provide an individual-level analysis, interpreting Aristotle’s claims about theorein as an essential dimension of eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle Reference Ostwald1999), and explicating what the contemplative, virtuous life of pleasure looks like beyond the life of the philosopher—emphasizing why it is worth pursuing for any and every individual, including those in business. In Section 3, I provide an organizational-level analysis, justifying how this development of Aristotle’s account of eudaimonia at the individual level normatively grounds the paradox perspective in organizations. I turn to Patagonia as a paradigmatic example of an organization grounded in both my depiction of the virtuous life of pleasure and the paradox perspective, acknowledging the challenges that still exist for companies beholden to structures that make its implementation difficult.

My claim is that the virtuous life of pleasure, which is cultivated by the habituation of theorein, not only characterizes how to live the most meaningful and pleasant life, rendering it good and thus worth pursuing, but it is also, as a flourishing life, the normative foundation for safeguarding the intrinsic value of nonfinancial corporate aims. It does so by establishing a principle of enough, which seeks to preserve integral, interdependent parts as ends in themselves and as constitutive of a larger ecosystem.

1. CORPORATE SUSTAINABILITY AND EUDAIMONIA

In this section, I will engage the discourse on corporate sustainability and individual well-being in relation to the business case for corporate sustainability and the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability. I do so to set up Aristotelian virtue ethics, that is, Aristotle’s account of individual well-being, as the most suitable normative ground for the paradox perspective, contra utilitarianism, which grounds the business case. Corporate sustainability involves the balance of three interconnected, interdependent, co-constitutive principles: economic prosperity, social equity, and environmental integrity, that is, keeping life on earth within planetary boundaries (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023).Footnote 2 These three principles are “intrinsically connected” and represent the necessary conditions for sustainable development (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023, 141; Bansal Reference Bansal2005). Though the definition of corporate sustainability also includes social equity, I will primarily focus on the co-constitutive relationship between economic prosperity and environmental integrity.Footnote 3

Because corporate sustainability is a normative and therefore prescriptive construct, it must be implemented by individual change agents within organizations who think it is good and decide that it is worth pursuing (Visser Reference Visser2007). Vucetich and Nelson (Reference Vucetich and Nelson2010, 543) rightly claim that “if we attain sustainability, it will not only require critical changes in technology, but also the most profound shift in ethical thought witnessed in the last four centuries.” This is because, as a prescriptive concept, advocating sustainability goals requires individuals who understand and value ecological health as good and earnestly strive to resist environmental degradation—ultimately understanding that our well-being is deeply bound to ecological health. This understanding is currently not the status quo in business.

Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati’s (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017) analysis of the limitations of the business case and the relationship between sustainable development and individual well-being exposes an essential human motivation that goes beyond utility-driven cost-benefit analysis. The authors call for us to readjust our values by moving away from pecuniary terms to describe well-being, as these are grounded in “the calculative mentality that pervades contemporary thinking about sustainable development” (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 302). They join Küpers (Reference Küpers2005) in an effort to “integrate the hedonic (the pleasurable), with the eudaimonic (the meaningful) as mutually reinforcing aspects of becoming well” Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 307). Among the chief aims in their study is to challenge the equation “well-being = wealth” as a pervasive “root metaphor,” which is itself an inevitable implication “of a much more basic set of common assumptions regarding the nature of human agency,” and, as an essential dimension of that, what we think constitutes our subjective well-being, that is, happiness (2017, 302).

The Business Case

The image that explains the business case for corporate sustainability and, more generally, the business perspective on who we are and what we take to be good, is homo economicus (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017; Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos, and Thoene Reference Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos and Thoene2018). Homo economicus is guided by means-ends calculation and motivated by self-interest and utility, that is, pleasure or the satisfaction of preferences (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017). For homo economicus, decision-making is governed by the principle of utility, which involves deciphering the most efficient means to maximizing utility. As such, pleasant outcomes take precedence over intention and, thus, the ends can justify the means (Mill Reference Mill and Sher2001, chap. 2). Quoting Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 303): “The conception of the market economy that informs most contemporary textbooks is based on the assumption that economic agents (be they consumers, producers, employers, employees, etc.) are rational utility maximizers,” who are adept at “optimizing output with a given input.” In the perpetual quest for utility-driven outcomes, homo economicus over-habituates the pursuit of instrumental or extrinsic goods—that is, what is good for the sake of something else in the future (circumstantially or conditionally good)—while intrinsic goods—that is, good for their own sake (universally or commonly good)—fade from view. For the utility maximizer, the calculated pursuit of the hedonic eclipses the intrinsic desirability of the eudaimonic, as the eudaimonic may not immediately provide pleasure.

Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati’s (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017) analysis builds upon Hahn et al.’s (Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2015) depiction of the trouble with the business case for corporate sustainability and concomitant advocacy for the paradox perspective as the most viable alternative to it. The business case for corporate sustainability eliminates any tensions between conflicting corporate goals by allowing one goal, the economic bottom line, to effectively imperialize the others (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018). The business case’s calculative cost-benefit analysis not only fails to recognize the intrinsic value of nonfinancial initiatives (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018, 238), it also prevents the actors within an organization from identifying, encouraging, or enjoying anything beyond instrumental value. A steadfast commitment to the economic bottom line is the organizational-level manifestation of utility-maximization in the sense that it is driven by a cost-benefit analysis. And profit, the result of the consumption of goods that yield satisfaction, is what, prima facie, maximizes satisfaction for all.

The other issue with the business case’s subordination of sustainability aims to the economic bottom line is that a company’s ability to actually benefit the environment is compromised (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023). This is because the moment the economic bottom line is threatened by environmental aims, environmental aims are eliminated, and it is back to unsustainable business as usual. If sustainability is nothing other than a business risk or opportunity—a conditional variable in a utilitarian cost-benefit analysis—it remains vulnerable to disregard if it contradicts the financial bottom line (Johnsen Reference Johnsen2020).

The Paradox Perspective

As an alternative to the business case for corporate sustainability, Hahn et al. (Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2015) offer the paradox perspective, which necessitates working through, rather than eliminating, the inevitable tensions among competing corporate initiatives with intrinsic value (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018). The paradox perspective has a “strong normative core” in the sense that social and environmental concerns “represent objectives for their own sake, irrespective of their ability to further financial or shareholder interests” (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018, 240; Donaldson and Preston Reference Donaldson and Preston1995). The paradox perspective focuses on honoring the tensions that arise among competing initiatives within corporations, urging corporations to paradoxically promote the intrinsic values of competing interests (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018, 238). In addition to this, “framing sustainability tensions through a paradox lens enables scholars to consider the complexity of sustainability problems, the intrinsic value of social and environmental elements, and their systemic nature” (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023, 142).

Drawing from Maletič et al. (Reference Maletič, Maletič, Dahlgaard, Dahlgaard-Parkand and Gomišček2014), Hahn et al. emphasize that the paradox perspective calls for “organizational ambidexterity” (2018, 238). They insist that the paradox perspective’s plurality of ostensibly contradictory objective functions pushes organizations to innovate: “accepting and pursuing competing sustainability objectives due to their inherent value brings into proximity competing demands; it highlights hidden connections and unconventional responses, thus creating ‘spaces of possibility’” that would otherwise go unnoticed in the service of the economic bottom line (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018, 244; Byrch et al. Reference Byrch, Milne, Morgan and Kearins2015). The paradox perspective thereby opens the firm up to new, creative possibilities for action (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023; Johnsen Reference Johnsen2020). This is distinct from the business case, which limits not only the type of solutions a firm can provide but also inhibits certain forms of creative thinking in organizations; for example, innovation that is driven by the earnest pursuit of ecological health, rather than profit. For the business case, there is only one end—the company’s financial bottom line—and any other perceived ends are in fact a mere means (as a risk or opportunity) to that bottom line. The paradox perspective, therefore, enhances our conception of the objective functions and purpose of business (Lankoski and Smith Reference Lankoski and Smith2018), promoting earnest innovation that safeguards intrinsic goods like environmental well-being.

A Normative Foundation for the Paradox Perspective

Hahn et al. (Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018, 241) stress that the paradox perspective needs a normative foundation that provides “suitable moral grounds to justify the demand that firms balance different, equally relevant but competing sustainability challenges” and stands opposed to the “utilitarian foundation” for the business case. Most importantly, a normative foundation for the paradox perspective requires a motivation to protect environmental aims as ends in themselves, as this is what differentiates it from the business case. This means it must be grounded in an account of human agency that recognizes, desires, and protects intrinsic goods—understanding that they are valuable.

Because the business case is guided by the principle of maximizing satisfaction by whatever means necessary, it reduces our conception of ourselves to utility-driven homo economicus, which inevitably misses vital aspects of what we desire, value (i.e., take to be good), and do in practice for the sake of our well-being (Crockett Reference Crockett2005; Bina and Vaz Reference Bina and Vaz2011; Arjoon et al. Reference Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos and Thoene2018). Utilitarianism provides an insufficient normative foundation for human well-being because pleasure is not the only thing that human beings desire, value, and pursue. Although well-being (the eudaimonic) is connected to utility (the hedonic), and well-being is pleasurable, they are distinct and only virtuously integrated through theorein, as I will flesh out in Section 2. Aristotle stresses that pleasure is not intrinsically good because pleasure should not be chosen in every circumstance, whereas virtue is intrinsically good and should be chosen in every circumstance by anyone, irrespective of the pleasure that follows (Aquinas Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 695, 877).

With the paradox perspective in view, Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017) turn to Summers and Smith’s (Reference Summers and Smith2014) analysis of the Millennium Ecosystem Assessment (MEA, 2005) to unearth the essential features of subjective well-being, that is, what humans desire and are therefore motivated by. The authors note that subjective well-being, distinct from objective need, involves subjective desire, which encompasses more than the strategic calculation that seeks to maximize utility (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017). The type of non-calculative subjective desire that the authors emphasize in their analysis is the human desire for a form of “sovereignty” that goes beyond “utility, efficiency, or productivity” (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 309). To elaborate on this, the authors turn to George Bataille’s notion of sovereign or useless consummation (distinct from consumption) (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 304). That is, our desire and freedom to do what “makes no practical sense,” such as beholding a pristine natural landscape (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 309). Essential to useless consummation is an experience of freedom that is not subjected to the logic of utility.

With Bataille’s account of subjectivity in mind, the authors offer “non-calculative sovereignty” as an alternative to “homo economicus’ calculative autonomy” and “believe that this capacity to include, rather than exclude the important role of subjective experience in human behaviour ultimately makes it a more appropriate conceptual basis for thinking about sustainable development” (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 303). This model of human agency stands in stark contrast to the utilitarian agent that undergirds the business case for corporate sustainability (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 304), utilitarianism involving a cost-benefit analysis that aims to maximize net satisfaction for salient stakeholders—ultimately in service of the economic bottom line (Friedman, Reference Friedman1970). Bataille’s notion of noncalculative sovereignty provides a sense of the self that is not perpetually calculating (dwelling in the past and future), or producing and consuming material commodities, but rather a self that is present to and energized in their experience, “completely absorbed in one’s experience in the moment … unperturbed by any particular aim or concern for the future” (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 305). This is a self that is attuned to what makes life worth living.

This insight is crucial. However, relying on a notion of sovereign consummation (which involves a lack of restraint) to better understand sustainability invokes a sense of uninhibited license, domination, and freedom that the “free” market craves and emulates in its all-too-often frivolous and ecologically reckless pursuit of utility. The authors recognize this dilemma, wondering how “‘sovereignty,’ i.e., the squandering of resources on unproductive and useless activities” can “be reconciled with responsible stewardship of our planet’s finite resources?” (Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017, 306). They respond by explaining that Bataille did not face the ecological concerns we face today, and that perhaps the crucial takeaway is the human desire to be, like a sovereign, beyond calculation.

Although noncalculative sovereignty provides a decisive depiction of a normative motivation that is otherwise than utility, it does not provide a sufficient normative foundation for the paradox perspective, which calls for organizations to balance co-constitutive, albeit competing corporate aims. As I will argue in the next section, Aristotle’s virtuous life of pleasure fills this lacuna, grounding the non-productive human motivation (beyond calculation) that Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017) locate in Bataille, through his rendering of well-being, eudaimonia, and his crucial distinction and depiction of the relationship between intrinsic goods and instrumental goods. Aristotle is a critical ally in helping us better understand a normative motive that is otherwise than utility without wholly forsaking it, because, as I will argue, for Aristotle, the hedonic and the eudaimonic are integrated aspects of well-being, united by theorein. Immersing oneself in intrinsic value, for its own sake, is what makes life both joyful and worth living.

To build on Painter-Morland, Demuijnck, and Ornati’s (Reference Painter-Morland, Demuijnck and Ornati2017) important individual-level analysis, and to strengthen our understanding of the noncalculative dimension of who we are that values intrinsic goods and then balances them with other goods, I will turn to Aristotle’s account of theorein (contemplative activity) as an indispensable dimension of eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics.

2. INDIVIDUAL-LEVEL ANALYSIS: THEOREIN AS VITAL TO EUDAIMONIA

In this section, I will illustrate how Aristotle’s normative theory harmonizes instrumental and intrinsic goods, and how theorein—understood as a fixed attention on and deep appreciation of intrinsic goods, a pleasant access to the whole—is constitutive of virtuous behavior, and thus of well-being or eudaimonia. Despite very brief mentions in Bragues (Reference Bragues2006), Sison and Fontrodona (Reference Sison and Fontrodona2012), and Hartman (Reference Hartman2013), Aristotle’s understanding of theorein has not, to the best of my knowledge, been thoroughly analyzed as constitutive of eudaimonia in business ethics literature to date. However, it is crucial that we incorporate it because we cannot provide a normative foundation for safeguarding intrinsic goods at both the individual and organizational levels without it.

Beyond this, it is important to turn to the source—in this case, Aristotle himself—when engaging normative ethical theories because they are grounded in robust accounts of human nature and well-being, governed by a clear conception of normative, motivating reasons; that is, they are based on investigations about the good (Bragues Reference Bragues2006; Wolcott Reference Wolcott2015). I will do so with the help of Talbot Brewer’s retrieval of Aristotle’s ethics, to illuminate how the contemplative life is not just one superior way of life among others (Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum1990) but is in fact an aspect of life that we all need to care about within and beyond business. In short, anyone who is eudaimon contemplates because contemplation is the activity by which we recognize and appreciate intrinsic goods, which are essential to eudaimonia.

Eudaimonia, Theorein, and the Pleasure of Virtue

For Aristotle, ‘good’ (telos, the aims we desire) has two distinct meanings: “(1) things which are intrinsically good, and (2) things which are good as being conducive to the intrinsically good” (EN, 1096b13-16). He is clear that we need both types of goods to live well, though the former are sought for their own sake, while the latter are instrumental, sought for the sake of something else—above all, happiness (eudaimonia). Eudaimonia is the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue (arete) or excellence. To act virtuously is to habituate dispositions that make us excellent at actualizing who we truly are, our proper function (ergon), which is reasoning. This enables us to live pleasant, flourishing lives (EN, 1097a30-35). To be eudaimon is to reason well.

Reason, for Aristotle, conceptually breaks down into two chief faculties: one dealing with what is necessary (universal truth, that which is true always, for everything, truth according to the whole [kat’holon],Footnote 4 i.e., intrinsic goods), the other dealing with what can be deliberated and calculated (what can be otherwise, relative truths, i.e., instrumental goods that secure intrinsic goods) (EN, 1139a17–1139a18). Phronesis or practical wisdom is the virtue pertaining to this latter faculty, while sophia or theoretical wisdom is the virtue pertaining to the former, that is, our capacity to behold, understand, and cherish the “ultimate meaning of things” (Bragues Reference Bragues2006). Theorein is the activity proper to sophia, operative at any moment that we are attending to intrinsic value—that is, to things that are good not only for me, but universally good, and thus in themselves—as the recognition of intrinsic value involves grasping or beholding “the things most honorable by nature,” which go beyond human beings because “man is not the best thing in the world” (EN, 1141b5; Roochnik Reference Roochnik2009). Theorein pursues an understanding of truth (e.g., what is the good? What is justice? What does it mean to live in accord with nature?), not practical results.

Given Aristotle’s account of what reason is, it seems clear that eudaimonia as excellent reasoning requires both of these intellectual virtues (Aquinas Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 923; Gurtler Reference Gurtler2003 and Reference Gurtler2008). Phronesis allows us to apply virtue in the context of particular circumstances that could be otherwise, but sophia, through theorein, allows us to understand virtue itself—that is, why virtuous activity is intrinsically good and an end in itself, situating our activity as a part that relates to, and is one with, what is beyond ourselves. As an intellectual activity, theorein involves cherishing, beholding, or keeping one’s gaze fixed on intrinsic goods (Ostwald Reference Ostwald1999, 315; Brewer Reference Brewer2009). This is to say that sophia, constituted by theorein, grasps and appreciates the values that govern practical wisdom. Phronesis requires a deep understanding of universally intrinsic goods (e.g., courage, moderation, generosity, justice, knowledge, nature, etc.) to choose how to proceed in particular circumstances after careful deliberation (Walker Reference Walker2018). When we contemplate, we access intrinsic goods, which we then protect and recreate as they shape our decision-making process. Quoting Aristotle, “we suppose Pericles and those of that sort [statesmen] to be prudent—because they are able to contemplate (theorein) the good things for themselves and those for human beings” (EN, 1140b5-10; Roochnik Reference Roochnik2009). The prudence of a virtuous leader hinges on their refusal to sacrifice what is intrinsically good for the community. The practice of virtue, therefore, requires theorein.

To return to the importance of integrating the hedonic with the eudaimonic as integrated aspects of well-being, Aristotle stresses that pleasure and pain are vital to eudaimonia because everything we choose and avoid is rooted in these (EN, 1104b30–1105a15). Because eudaimonia is that toward which everything aims, pleasure and eudaimonia are tightly bound, but distinct, meaning pleasure has a motivating force, though we must decipher which pleasures are worth pursuing—namely, those associated with reason, as “the pleasure proper to virtuous activity is good, and the pleasure proper to vicious activity is bad” (Aquinas Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 896). Vicious pleasures are those associated with excess, instrumental goods (e.g., money) and bodily compulsions (Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 640–43), while virtuous pleasures are those associated with intrinsic goods (Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 689, 904). As Aristotle puts it, the virtuous, desirable activity is always principle, not pleasure (Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 888). Virtue is desirable and choice worthy regardless of the pleasure that follows, and even if no pleasure were to follow (Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 877), though pleasure will eventually accompany and perfect virtuous activities (Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 886). As stated in Section 1, the pleasure that accompanies virtue may not be (and often is not) immediate, but through habit (EN, 1103a19-23), we come to recognize that attending to what is intrinsic valuable—what is meaningful—is pleasant.

Theorein, as the fixed attention on and deep appreciation of intrinsic goods, is thus completed by the most meaningful type of pleasure we can experience as human beings—and it is also the most meaningful activity we are capable of (Aquinas Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 907). Theorein is what ultimately integrates the hedonic with the eudaimonic, as we experience the rational pleasure of being present with truth, what is commonly good, attending, as much as we can, to what is beyond, albeit interconnected with, ourselves. This pleasant experience of being present to the whole is perhaps best understood as a style of thinking and attitude or mood. That is, a mood of communion rather than individuation, as we recognize that we and other phenomena are part of and unified with something other than our individual selves (Brewer Reference Brewer2009). When there is no experience of the past and future, we are not individuals isolated in a vacuum, but rather integral parts that are essentially connected to and at home within a greater whole; we are an integral part of a common good (Sison and Fontrodona Reference Sison and Fontrodona2012).

Pleasure plays an important role in virtue ethics because the experience of pleasure further anchors us in the virtuous activity at hand and keeps it “unobstructed”—complete, whole, and at rest, rather than in motion (EN, 1153b10-15; Brewer Reference Brewer2009). For Aristotle, time is the measure of motion, so to say that pleasure is complete, whole, and at rest is to say that it is experienced without a sense of time. The pleasure that accompanies virtue is the experience of timelessness or “losing track of time” in the sense that we are immersed in the activity at hand, utterly present to and enjoying the experience of something good in itself, that is, as an end in itself, and thus as a part connected to the whole. While pleased, future aims fade from view, meaning there is a cessation of calculation (Brewer Reference Brewer2009). When we calculate, we are divided in the sense that we are deciphering means to projected ends in the future; whereas when we contemplate, we are complete and whole in the sense that we are savoring the present qua appreciating intrinsic value and being in communion with whatever we are contemplating, as it connects with everything in its environment. “Environment” here means natural, but also social and economic environing worlds (wholes).

The contemplator attains “a higher degree of happiness than anyone” (Brewer Reference Brewer2009; EN, 1179a30) because there is nothing more essential to being human or more delightful than theorein (Roochnik Reference Roochnik2009, 78; Walker Reference Walker2018). But a life that consists solely in theorein, ostensibly void of calculation and instrumental aims, is not a human life, but rather the life of a god (EN, 1177b25-30; Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum1990). This brings us back to Aristotle’s definition of eudaimonia as excellent reasoning—reason itself having two prongs. In order for us to truly flourish, we must exercise both phronesis and sophia, which is to say that eudaimonia requires practical virtues and theorein. Beyond this, phronesis seeks to secure sophia (Walker Reference Walker2018), as it is a “more excellent” intellectual capacity, and it does so in the sense that theorein grasps the intrinsic goods—that is, values—by which we are able to decipher how to deliberate and choose in practice by way of phronesis (EN, 1145a1-10; Aquinas Reference Aquinas and Litzinger1964, 604).

Although we all need sufficient external goods, as this is an important part of eudaimonia (EN, 1099b30), those who contemplate simply need less: “self-sufficiency and moral action do not consist in an excess of possessions … It is enough to have moderate means at one’s disposal, for the life of a happy man whose activity is guided by virtue will be happy” (EN, 1179a1-10). The reason that those who are adept at theorein have less need for external goods is that those who engage in theorein come to appreciate truths that show us the intrinsic value and goodness of non-material things, especially our own, non-productive (useless) and non-consumptive activities. The experience of theorein—the pleasant experience of communing-with rather than individuating-from our environment, granting us access to the whole—reveals and reminds us that as individuals, humans are but small pieces within the whole of a large, interrelated web of life; and, echoing Aristotle, that we are not the most important feature of the universe.

In contemplation, we see that we share the world with (human and nonhuman) others. We also realize that we need less material goods because these things, despite their apparent utility, are much less meaningful than other things. When contemplating, we are humbled, in wonder and awe, before something that is more than us as individuals, and in that experience recognize that each thing has its place and ought to be cherished and preserved, for its own sake, as an end in itself and as interrelated with the common good. This includes ourselves, as part of humanity, as well as the natural world, as the home upon which humanity and all forms of life depend. This appreciation of intrinsic goodness acquired through theorein, which habituates the overthrowing of homo economicus, leads to an ecological perspective on the world and our place within it, because of its orientation toward the whole—“ecological” in the sense that we understand ourselves and our activities as integral parts of a something that is common or shared, the interrelated and interdependent system of the environment (Satchel, Kaaronen, and Latzman Reference Satchell, Kaaronen and Latzman2021; Taylor Reference Taylor1981).

Engaging in contemplation, therefore, leads us to the sort of wisdom that allows us to effectively combat the urge to take more than we need by feeling fulfilled in the present, helping us learn how to discern what boundaries should be drawn in light of a strong attunement to that which is good for its own sake and thus commonly good, including the environment. The contemplator pursues instrumental goods, because we also need them, but with more clearly defined limits given by the recognition and appreciation of the value of intrinsic goods—above all, eudaimonia. How precisely to construct those limits is clearer for the one who contemplates because they have understood and enjoyed the intrinsic value of what is commonly good, like the natural world, but also community-oriented virtues like moderation, courage, honesty, and generosity. Moral lines can and must be drawn for the sake of intrinsic goods. The person who habituates theorein, “fully actualizing [their] knowledge that [they] should not do something, will not in fact do it” (Roochnik Reference Roochnik2009, 74), because they have properly understood what is intrinsically good, and are thus motivated to safeguard those goods because they understand their value in themselves.

This appreciation of intrinsic goods ultimately establishes what I call a principle of enough, which insists that ends in themselves ought to be cherished and preserved as such, thereby mitigating our temptation to understand the maximization of utility as the good. Theorein is required for a principle of enough because in order to mitigate the bias of utility and preserve things beyond oneself that are in fact interconnected with oneself, one must be attuned to goods that are otherwise than utility—intrinsically valuable for their own sake, above all, eudaimonia. It is because of theorein that we can cherish and thus insist on protecting intrinsic goods as constitutive of the good of the whole, unwilling to sacrifice them for the sake of utility. Theorein reveals goods and values that are common, shared with others, thereby exposing our interrelation with, and interdependence on, what is beyond our individual selves.

Theorein Beyond the Philosopher

Although Aristotle seems to suggest that contemplation is limited to philosophers because they dedicate their lives to studying truth (Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum1990), I want to insist that it is a vital activity for all human beings. The deep cherishing and appreciation of intrinsic goods simply cannot be sacrificed if we truly want to be eudaimon, which we all in fact do—a fact that is confirmed in the social sciences (Cameron and Winn Reference Cameron, Winn, Cameron and Spreitzer2012). It is also important to stress that theorein is also not limited to the contemplation of any particular intrinsic good (Walker Reference Walker2018), but is an attitude we assume while striving to understand things for what they are, and being one with whatever we are doing for its own sake, not for the sake of an outcome (Roochnik Reference Roochnik2009, 75–77)—be it manual workmanship, collaborating with a team, immersing oneself in nature, or engaging in philosophical reflection. Within organizations, occasions for theorein could be facilitated through reflective exercises in meetings, community-building retreats, wellness programming, or designated time and spaces to disconnect from productivity more broadly (Duerr Reference Duerr2004), for example, to meditate, engage in conversation with colleagues, or enjoy nature; or through leisure-promoting policies that facilitate work-life balance, such as three-day weekends, paid mental health and personal days, and flexible work hours (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023).

In The Retrieval of Ethics (2009), Brewer, taking his cue from Macintyre’s After Virtue (2007), elaborates how virtue ethics provides a more relevant moral framework (than utilitarianism and deontology) because it makes sense of what each of us desire and find pleasurable in every walk of life, refusing to reduce us to output-oriented cogs in a production-oriented, utility-maximizing machine. Brewer analyzes the role of pleasure in human flourishing, stressing that to engage in an activity that you love and truly enjoy, you surrender yourself and “pay tribute” to its intrinsic goodness (Brewer Reference Brewer2009, 48). “Goodness” here refers to the value we see in the activities we love, including how they align with virtue. Building upon the analysis above, Brewer aptly describes the “attention-arresting” mode of engagement with intrinsic goodness as “unselfing” because when attending to an activity in this way, we are removed from distractions—above all, the “most banal and obsessive human distraction: the self” (2009, 64). The self he has in mind here is homo economicus, the utility-maximizing calculator—battling (perceived) scarcity.

Brewer also differentiates “sensory pleasure” from “attentive pleasure,” the former being pleasure that involves passively basking in instant gratification, while the latter involves actively and rationally appreciating the “vivid appearances of the value of our doings or circumstances” and the intrinsic goodness therein (2009, 132). This is the experience of theorein—the integration of the hedonic and the eudaimonic. Intrinsic value and the attentive pleasure that accompanies it pulls us from outcome-oriented concerns, as we are mesmerically attracted to and immersed in the timeless experience of the present (Brewer Reference Brewer2009, 64). And what is crucial here is that this experience of the present is always directed toward what is good according to the whole—that is, what is good not just for a particular set of circumstances, but good in itself. And again, the experience of the present is being in communion-with, rather than being individuated-from; the present reveals our deep relationship with what is beyond our (utility-maximizing) selves. This also means that homo economicus’s pursuit of self-interested and utility-oriented outcomes is disrupted and tempered, as it is captivated by intrinsic goodness—that which is not only good for me, but good for all. Contemplation thus allows us to properly understand ourselves and our activities as parts that contribute to and thus depend upon the common good.

It is therefore the habituation of theorein that allows us to shift our mindset from one that is governed by utility-maximization, homo economicus, to one that is able to comprehend and value an entirely different order of goods, namely, intrinsic goods (above all, eudaimonia), that provide reasons for action. The utility-maximizer is limited to utility as a motivation for action, whereas the contemplator understands that utility is but one reason for action—and one that must be balanced with, or even subjected to, things are good for their own sake and thus good for the whole. To give an example, a contemplator would understand that being honest with a customer is good because honesty is an intrinsic good, good for the whole, something that should be cherished and actualized regardless of its projected utility. Being honest may of course provide utility, but that is not the primary motivation. The primary motivation is safeguarding the intrinsic value of honesty as a virtue that is constitutive of well-being not only for oneself, but for all. In this case, the principle of enough shows the contemplator that there is a moral line that ought not be crossed, even if it may lead to less utility. The utility maximizer does not have access to this type of intrinsic motivation as such—a motivation that opens up new pathways for innovation and action, as I will show in Section 3.

In sum, a life rich in theorein, which nurtures eudaimonia, is the kind of life that we cannot help but desire as human beings, regardless of our respective vocation and occupation, as it allows us to embrace a vital rational activity—namely, cherishing things for their own sake—that we need to live well and enjoy. Theorein involves the simultaneous disruption of self-interested and outcome-oriented desires, and pleasant experience of ends in themselves beyond, albeit interconnected with, oneself. Appreciating intrinsic goods as such establishes a principle of enough, which insists that ends in themselves ought to be cherished and preserved as such and as constitutive of the good of the whole, and that they simply cannot be sacrificed for the sake of projected utility. Theorein shows that the production and consumption of instrumental goods must always be taken in relation to the preservation and flourishing of intrinsic goods: recognizing intrinsic goods, protecting them as such (not reducing them to mere means), cherishing them both as they are and as part of the balance that lets each member of the whole thrive—and, in so doing, contributing to the flourishing of ourselves and others as parts of an interrelated whole.

With this individual-level analysis in view, we can now turn to how the virtuous life of pleasure (eudaimonia), cultivated by theorein, provides a normative foundation for the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability at the organizational level.

3. ORGANIZATIONAL-LEVEL ANALYSIS: EUDAIMONIA MOTIVATING THE FIRM

In this section, I will build out how the virtuous life of pleasure (eudaimonia) as a normative core motivates change agents—that is, company leaders—to meaningfully pursue corporate sustainability by way of the paradox perspective. I will also illustrate how Patagonia embodies the paradox perspective through their understanding of economic prosperity and environmental integrity as co-constitutive.

Organizational values guide the decisions a corporation makes as an individual entity in the market, and these organizational values emerge from the values of individual change agents who think and make decisions for the company, based on what they take to be good and thus worth pursuing (Visser Reference Visser2007; Hambrick Reference Hambrick2007). The paradox perspective involves addressing environmental aims as ends in themselves and as co-constitutive of economic prosperity, meaning environmental integrity is not a mere means to economic prosperity, but is properly understood to be a necessary condition for it. Therefore, its implementation requires change agents who are motivated to cherish, uphold, and refuse to sacrifice nonfinancial aims for their own sake and as co-constitutive of economic prosperity—grasping the truth that we (and our companies) belong to a greater ecological whole. Organizations are not passive containers (Moore Reference Moore2015; Macintyre Reference Macintyre2007), but rather contexts for virtues to grow or diminish that require both intrinsic and instrumental goods; theorein is the activity through which individuals are able to grasp and are motivated to protect what is intrinsically good and thus virtuous. Theorein is also the activity through which individual change agents within companies are able to recognize that economic prosperity, guided by utility-maximization, should not be the company’s sole objective because economic prosperity is in fact interdependent on and interconnected with environmental integrity.

Analogous to a virtuous statesperson contemplating things that are good in themselves and good for human beings to ensure that the community (or society) flourishes, a virtuous change agent within an organization would contemplate what we, human beings, need to flourish; what the company’s purpose is in relation to the society in which we operate and in relation to the natural world from which we extract resources; and also what the biosphere—housing ourselves, our companies, and society—needs to flourish. This of course does not mean that the organization stops striving for economic prosperity, because it must (to continue to exist); the principle of enough, facilitated by theorein, insists that corporate goals beyond profit can be pursued so long as there is room for the bias of utility to take a backseat. And with this, the understanding that a firm can persist and prosper while ensuring that the welfare of the ecological whole is protected and sustained over time.

It then follows that the paradox perspective must be driven by organizational change agents who insist that the company simultaneously embraces the intrinsic values of those competing aims. And if this is the case, then a normative foundation for the paradox perspective requires change agents who are motivated by an appreciation of environmental aims as ends in themselves that should not be compromised by, subordinated to, or sacrificed for the sake of economic aims, and are also understood to be constitutive of the good of the ecological whole (of which the organization is a part). If environmental aims are only instrumentally, and thus conditionally valued for the sake of utility-based ends, as change agents advocating the business case would have it—failing to grasp their intrinsic value—they inevitably run the risk of not being seriously taken into consideration in corporate decision-making processes because they are nonessential. Thus, the moment a conflict arises among competing corporate aims, environmental aims will be subsumed by the economic bottom line, since they are not understood to be intrinsically good and connected to the whole. This also means the utilitarian calculus of the business case prevails; concern for the environment is a mere risk or opportunity, exploited for the sake of the firm’s competitive advantage.

Therefore, in order for change agents in corporations to be motivated to protect intrinsic goods, and to justify the effort to paradoxically build upon and destroy current unsustainable business activities (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018), they must be adept at theorein. This is because theorein is the only activity through which we grasp intrinsic value, disrupt and humble homo economicus’s relentless pursuit of utility-maximization for the sake of the meaningful, and see ourselves and our organizations as part of a greater whole in which each interdependent part has its place as an end in itself. Theorein’s pleasant access to the whole facilitates the virtuous quality of mind in organizational change agents that properly orders competing corporate aims as co-constitutive and equally essential. It tempers the relentless pursuit of utility by insisting that it is balanced with, and ordered alongside, environmental flourishing. A principle of enough facilitates this balancing process for change agents by providing clear, paradoxical limits on financial aims because environmental aims are understood to be intrinsically good and worth protecting as constitutive of the good of the ecological whole, of which the company is a part. This individual-level understanding, motivated by theorein, becomes the organizational-level ethos by grounding the organization’s core values, which dictate the company’s vision, policies, processes, and decisions.

The ultimate criterion guiding organizational change agents in the face of paradoxical aims is eudaimonia, which, given the role of intrinsic goods—that is, what is good for all—includes the common good (EN, 1094b10; Sison and Fontrodona Reference Sison and Fontrodona2012). Eudaimonia as an overarching criterion does not resolve paradoxes or neglect economic prosperity but, through theorein, pushes organizations to understand that ostensibly conflicting aims are in fact “two sides of the same coin” that will continue to “persist over time” (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023) and must be balanced—for the sake of individual well-being and the well-being of the whole that houses them and their communities, including organizations. As Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos, and Thoene (Reference Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos and Thoene2018, 150) stress, “the neo-classical organization, whose goal is to maximize shareholder value/profits through the pursuit of self-interest” relies on “the homo economicus assumption of the economic person … guided by principles of the ‘greatest good for the greatest number’ and efficiency.” The authors continue:

With respect to the virtuous organization, its goal is eudaimonia … an organization can be said to be virtuous to the extent to which the internal goods of the practice (excellence of the product or service) contribute to the common good … unethical practices occur when there is a disorder between internal and external goods … An exclusive focus on goods of efficiency can distort one’s perception and judgment through blind spots and moral slippages, which make it difficult to recognize the ethical issues and to determine what is the right thing to do (Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos, and Thoene Reference Arjoon, Turriago-Hoyos and Thoene2018, 150).

The virtuous life of pleasure prohibits these “blind spots” and “moral slippages” by allowing the company to be appropriately understood as an integral part of an ecological whole, therefore motivating the company to preserve that ecological whole and its constitutive parts. This is because change agents within the company appreciate the fact that organizational well-being and environmental well-being are one and the same, in that they are interdependent, interconnected, and co-constitutive, as the paradox perspective insists. This appreciative understanding then compels the company to innovate in a way that refuses to subordinate environmental integrity to profit, as this would erroneously presume that the company is detached and independent from the whole and what is good for the whole.

Patagonia

To further flesh out what this looks like at the organizational level, and how individual change agents within organizations can actualize this, I will analyze a concrete, paradigmatic example of a company that embodies a deep, contemplative appreciation of intrinsic goods that ought not to be compromised by or subordinated to profit-oriented aims: Patagonia. Patagonia has had the courage to innovate in the face of paradoxes, has unwaveringly safeguarded their core values, and has created a corporate culture of sustainability governed by eudaimonia, nurtured by theorein. In addition to cherishing the intrinsic value of environmental aims, the company has remained economically prosperous. Facilitated by change agents within the company, Patagonia engages in theorein through its motivation to reflect on humanity’s and business’s place within the biosphere, understanding that their company’s health (and every company’s health) depends on the health of the biosphere (the health of the whole), and through its practice of cherishing and appreciating this truth as a guiding principle for the company’s vision, policies, processes, and decisions.

In The Future of the Responsible Company (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023), Patagonia’s founder, Yvon Chouinard, and Director of Philosophy, Vincent Stanley, sketch the road to being a responsible company, in Patagonia’s sense of the term, after fifty years of success. By “responsible,” they mean the capacity, privilege, and desire to do what is right, simply because it is the right thing to do (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 25–29), a capacity grounded in theorein. Stanley and Chouinard show that any company can be a responsible company insofar as they are deeply committed to treating their people well and improving the environmental performance of their operations for their own sake (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 11); they even include practical checklists for company leaders who want to be more responsible. While the authors are well aware of the fact that Patagonia is often understood to be an exceptional company, outside of the status quo, they stress that Patagonia is “only exceptional at the margins. As mice and men share 99 percent of their genes, so do Amazon, Exxon, Twitter … and Patagonia” (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 32). Stanley and Chouinard acknowledge that other companies have external pressures that can make it more difficult to be responsible—for example, being publicly traded—but their claim is that the status quo simply needs to change, given the ecological crisis in which we find ourselves and the power of business (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023). The ecological truth of humans being a part of a greater whole, upon which we depend, sits at the core of Patagonia’s mission, internalizing all of the company’s policies, strategies, and processes. As the company puts it on their website, one of their core values is to “Protect our home planet. We’re all part of nature, and every decision we make is in the context of the environmental crisis challenging humanity” (Patagonia 2022).

In 2022, the company set the gold standard for corporate sustainability by making the earth their only shareholder; it is now owned by two non-profits that are dedicated to fighting climate change (Gelles Reference Gelles2022). With the paradox perspective in view, Patagonia has been at the forefront of environmental protection in North America for its own sake—founded by “a small band of climbers and surfers who had a love for the natural world” (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 32). The authors recount the early days of the company when they realized that hard-steel pitons for rock climbing “had become environmental villains,” and decided that, because of their love for the rocks themselves and the ecosystem to which they belonged, they had no choice but to phase them out and find an alternative (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 35). As they put it:

It was a huge risk … but the changes had to be made for reasons both moral and practical: the routes were beautiful and satisfying and shouldn’t be ruined; and to ruin them would put an end to, or greatly reduce the possibilities for climbing in the most popular areas, and thus eventually hurt our business … we learned by addressing the problem, we had forced ourselves to make a better product … doing the right thing motivated us—and turned out to be good business (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 35–36).

This is a clear example of how Patagonia engaged in theorein in the face of paradox. Here, the recognition of the intrinsic value of the environment (the rocks themselves and their connection to the good of the environment as a whole) appears paradoxically in tension with the financial security of the company, but in fact facilitated excellent innovation. The moral motive here again finds its ground in theorein: a deep appreciation of the intrinsic value of something that is otherwise than profit—and at least seemingly at odds with their company’s economic prosperity, although interconnected with and interdependent on it. As the authors put it, doing the right thing for its own sake “turned out to be good business,” though they did not do the right thing for the sake of profit, exemplifying the co-constitution of environmental integrity and economic prosperity. Echoing the paradox perspective’s aim to foster innovation that would not happen if profit subsumed other aims, another one of Patagonia’s core values is that they are not bound by convention (Patagonia 2022). The way the authors describe it again fits neatly with the theoretical description of the paradox perspective and the virtuous life of pleasure: “Our success—and much of the fun—lies in developing new ways to do things,” which is always also grounded in quality integrity, environmentalism, and justice (Patagonia 2022). The company embraces and enjoys the entrepreneurial spirit of business, albeit always as rooted in an unwavering commitment to the core values—intrinsic goods—that govern every company decision.

It perhaps goes without saying that Patagonia is financially successful with an estimated net value of $3 billion as of 2023, bringing in roughly $100 million a year (Pereira Reference Pereira2023). Though the authors admit, “we’re not sure we could stay healthy as a business without growing at least as fast as inflation. But as a company seeking to be responsible, we treat a high rate of growth as a risky option not a necessity” (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 72). For Patagonia, all of the company’s aims are constantly balanced, again, as interconnected and co-constitutive of each other; environmental aims are never subordinated to economic prosperity. To give another example, Patagonia telling customers (on Black Friday) to not buy what they do not need in their famous “Do Not Buy this Jacket” campaign (urging consumers to instead buy used or repair what they already have) is not only a testimony of their commitment to intrinsic value in practice. It is a testimony of the fact that corporate sustainability works when grounded in an earnest commitment to intrinsic value; safeguarding intrinsic value shines because, as argued in Section 2, it is something we in fact all desire. The company knew that discouraging the sales of their products could pose a risk to their economic bottom line, vital to the existence of the company, but customer loyalty prevailed. Although the campaign reinforced customer loyalty, that was not their aim. Their aim was to promote environmental well-being by urging consumers to reflect on and limit wasteful consumption practices. As Stanley and Chouinard (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 99–101) write:

But the balance sheet still counts. The word is apt. Unbalanced business leads to distracted managers who flail about with a runaway firehose rather than productively meeting the company’s needs and developing its opportunities … Are you investing in product innovation? This question is key for companies seeking to improve their social performance and reduce their environmental impact. You can’t do what lazy companies do—bleed suppliers for cost reductions to achieve greater efficacy or use cheaper but more environmentally harmful, often labor-exploitative materials to put more money in the bottom line. You and your people must figure out the right thing to do in the right way and then go about it, gradually if you must, but never losing sight of the endgame which is to keep the quality of your products high while satisfying your stakeholders, one of whom is the earth … Doing the right thing made money, just not the next day.

The essential takeaway here is that Patagonia truly walks the talk of virtue, which requires theorein, and exemplifies an economically prosperous company grounded in management that understands, embodies, and then pays forward the virtuous life of pleasure because it is good in itself.

When Stanley and Chouinard realized how toxic and unsustainable the textile industry was (in particular, the production of cotton), they knew Patagonia had no choice but to transform, investing in a very hands-on “enviro team,” closely inspecting production methods on-sight, as well as clean processes (e.g., regenerative agriculture) that refuse to compromise the health of the planet. Quoting the authors:

It dawned on us that our purpose was now driving the business model. There was no separation. The constraints we placed on ourselves had forced us to stay awake and innovate when most companies pursued ruthless—relatively mindless—efficiency, reducing costs year by year until the world moved on. We found the world moving our way. Innovation led to new and better products (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 128).

The same logic governed Chouinard’s decision to make the earth the only shareholder in the company rather than allow it to become “one of those irresponsible companies” that are pressured to maximize shareholder returns above everything else (Gelles Reference Gelles2022).

Patagonia is a paradigmatic example of the way in which a steadfast commitment to intrinsic goods as constitutive of the good of the whole undergirds the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability, thereby leading to the kind of sustainable innovations required to keep us within planetary boundaries. This can and in fact does lead to an amplifying effect within and beyond the company itself (Cameron and Winn Reference Cameron, Winn, Cameron and Spreitzer2012; Sison and Ferrero Reference Sison and Ferrero2015). Patagonia has provided sustainability-oriented counsel for a host of other companies, including publicly traded companies, like Walmart, and has also sought sustainability-oriented counsel from companies with higher B-corporation scores than them, like Dr. Bronner’s, to learn from their “We’re All-One or None!” company philosophy (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023). Echoing the authors, economic prosperity requires environmental integrity. They are co-constitutive. But the only way to meaningfully pursue economic prosperity is to understand that environmental integrity is intrinsically valuable: the preservation of which is non-negotiable. As Stanley and Chouinard write, “Eventually, the business world will recognize the economic and environmental equivalent of the astronomical truth that the Earth rotates around the sun, not the other way around. Our economy revolves around nature, not the other way around. As we destroy nature, we destroy our economy” (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 120–21).

The case of Patagonia is not meant to overlook or simplify the industry-specific challenges that companies face in an earnest attempt to shift toward a paradox perspective on corporate sustainability. Cost-effective and familiar path dependencies, for example, that companies have relied on for decades require substantial resources to overhaul (Troje Reference Troje2023). Organizational structures like public ownership often bind organizations to short-term thinking (Kaplan Reference Kaplan2018). And the complexity of deep, international supply chains discourage leadership from imitating what Patagonia has done—that is, investigating the reality of what they do abroad in the name of their brand and sending people to the frontlines to monitor and enforce responsible practices (Stanley and Chouinard Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023). The how dimension of meaningful corporate sustainability efforts requires contemplative understanding, ingenuity, and the courage to commit to being responsible, which is a tall order within an economic system that prioritizes utility above everything else. But as Stanley and Chouinard stress, “Whether a business is owned by an individual, a family, a joint-stock company, or the Earth, it can, if it chooses, work in concert with all sectors of society in the interest of the common good and nature” (Reference Stanley and Chouinard2023, 167). Structural changes within organizations cannot happen overnight, but for them to happen at all requires a motivation to preserve non-financial ends as ends in themselves, and as co-constitutive of economic prosperity, which theorein provides.

4. CONCLUSION

In this paper, I have sketched an answer to the call for a normative foundation for the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability and enriched an understanding of firm objectives that ought to be otherwise than profit by offering a rendering of Aristotelian virtue ethics, what I call the virtuous life of pleasure, that highlights how theorein cultivates, and is essential to, virtue and eudaimonia. Theorein grounds our understanding and expression of virtue and allows us to experience the type of pleasure—the blissful experience of being in communion-with, rather than individuated-from the whole—that makes life meaningful. Theorein also involves the simultaneous disruption of self-interested and outcome-oriented desires, and recognition and appreciation of ends in themselves beyond, albeit interconnected to, ourselves. It is ultimately the style of thinking and attitude or mood that integrates the hedonic into the eudaimonic.

Theorein helps us habituate overcoming the utility-seeking bias of homo economicus for the sake of eudaimonia, as we experience ourselves and our activities as constitutive of a greater ecological whole rather than radically detached from it. It does so by leading to a principle of enough that insists that ends in themselves, integral to the good of the whole, ought to be cherished and preserved as such. The virtuous life of pleasure is the most suitable normative foundation for the paradox perspective because it offers a more viable and accurate conception of who we are and what we desire (and why) than homo economicus, which grounds both utilitarianism and the business case. Contrary to the utility-maximizer, homo contemplativus recognizes that the hedonic is but one motivating reason for action, one that must be balanced with intrinsic goods—above all, eudaimonia. What is required for the paradox perspective is an understanding of, and motivation to protect, environmental ends as ends in themselves and as co-constitutive of economic prosperity, which the virtuous life of pleasure provides. It does so by insisting that an essential dimension of eudaimonia is the deep appreciation and pursuit of intrinsic goods, which is nurtured by the habituation of theorein.

Theorein is the rational activity that inspires this crucial individual-level understanding that is both essential to eudaimonia and that can foster meaningful change at the organizational level. In order for organizations to embody the paradox perspective, leaders within those organizations need to be motivated to balance and integrate competing goals by understanding, appreciating, and safeguarding the intrinsic goods that fortify the common good. Patagonia provides a paradigmatic example of this, illustrating that being a responsible company requires change agents who are committed to innovating in light of the fact that intrinsically valuable environmental ends cannot be subordinated to or sacrificed for the sake of economic prosperity—they must be understood as co-constitutive. Economic prosperity is interconnected with and interdependent on environmental integrity. Every decision that Patagonia makes is motivated by the insight that theorein provides—namely, that we are not isolated individuals in a vacuum—and, likewise, companies are not entities disconnected from their environment, but an integral and dependent part of it.

But again, the case of Patagonia does not mean that the implementation of the paradox perspective goes without challenges. Patagonia is a values-driven company, through and through, and as a private company, the change agents within the company have never been beholden to anything other than their values, which their employees happen to wholeheartedly share. My argument here has focused on providing a normative foundation for the paradox perspective, as actualized by company leaders (on top) who think and make decisions on behalf of the company, but this presumption comes with limitations. Corporations and their cultures are of course complex aggregates of individuals and relationships that do not always follow a top-down decision structure (Bright, Winn, and Kanov Reference Bright, Winn and Kanov2014), and individual values cannot always be straightforwardly applied to organizations (Moore Reference Moore, Akrivou and Sison2016; Quinn and Wellman Reference Quinn, Wellman, Cameron and Spreitzer2012). The relationship between individual and organizational responsibility is dynamic, ever-changing, and muddled by the fact that organizational conditions influence individual values and behavior—and vice versa (Painter-Morland Reference Painter-Morland2011; Constantinescu and Kaptein Reference Constantinescu, Kaptein, Laasch, Suddaby, Freeman and Jamali2020; Bromiley and Rau Reference Bromiley and Rau2016). Beyond this, the groups of individuals that make decisions on behalf of the company can and often do have conflicting values, and there can also be value conflicts among individuals across different levels of the organization.

These complexities raise the following questions: given various institutional strictures, is it always possible to work according to our personal values? How can common values be negotiated in the face of conflicts within and beyond governing entities in corporations? What is the role of theorein in facilitating the negotiation of common values? And how might organizational value change happen from the bottom-up—or from different levels within the organization?Footnote 5 I hope to have provided a normative justification for pursuing the paradox perspective on corporate sustainability, but these are all critical questions that have not been answered here and that deserve careful theoretical and empirical analysis in the future. With these questions in mind, the conclusions in this paper could productively be put into conversation with research in management on systems theory (Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023) and positive organizational scholarship (Cameron and Spreitzer Reference Cameron and Spreitzer2012; Sison and Ferrero Reference Sison and Ferrero2015; Constantinescu and Kaptein Reference Constantinescu, Kaptein, Laasch, Suddaby, Freeman and Jamali2020). It would also be fruitful to gather qualitative empirical data from companies embodying the paradox perspective to better understanding the concrete ways in which theorein is an integral part of their corporate culture.

It is important to stress that companies choosing to embody a principle of enough by cherishing and thus protecting environmental aims does not mean that the competitive wheels of capitalism need to stop turning altogether (Gladwin, Kennelly, and Krause Reference Gladwin, Kennelly and Krause1995), or that pecuniary motives entirely fade from view. It means that a long overdue ideological shift will begin to take place within a system that prioritizes utility-maximization at a disastrous ecological price for every member of the ecosystem. This will no doubt change economic progress and the pace of economic prosperity as we understand it today, albeit in a way that is more attuned to what we truly want and need to flourish on this planet—and to keep this planet flourishing for its own sake (Hickel Reference Hickel2020). This should not be understood as an ethical shift involving sacrifice but rather a vital, evolutionary step toward living more excellent, meaningful, and pleasant lives by understanding and paying tribute to what is essential to our well-being and to the well-being of the whole, of which we are an integral part. This is not only required for the type of ecological conversion that we ought to take to protect all life on earth but it is also necessary to better understanding who we really are, which is not merely homo economicus, but also homo contemplativus—and ultimately, homo ecologicus.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Vicente Muñoz-Reja for his invaluable comments on every iteration of the paper, and for the important conversations we had about the nature of contemplation and its relation to phronesis. I also sincerely thank the former co-editor-in-chief, Mollie Painter, and three anonymous reviewers for their generous, constructive, and encouraging feedback. The review process was extremely fruitful and significantly improved the central argument and the paper as a whole. The final version of the paper is indebted to all of these meaningful exchanges.

Melissa Fitzpatrick () is an assistant professor of business ethics and sustainability in the College of Business Administration at Loyola Marymount University, Los Angeles. Chief among her research interests is understanding how to foster a more sustainable community within and beyond the human world, and, as a vital foundation for that, how to overcome production and consumption-oriented values. She received her PhD in philosophy from Boston College, her MA in philosophy from Loyola Marymount University, and her BS in communication from Boston University. She is the co-author of Radical Hospitality: From Thought to Action.

Footnotes

1 In addition to being almost entirely absent in the literature on Aristotle in business ethics, Aristotle’s claims in Book X of the Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle Reference Ostwald1999; hereafter EN) have always been a point of controversy within Aristotle scholarship. To give just one example, Martha Nussbaum sees Book X.6-8 as something “clearly different” and “incompatible with the main line of argument in the EN” (1990, 368)—an un-Aristotelian, part of a set of “Platonic” outliers within Aristotle’s corpus that appears to abandon distinctly human goods (1990, 384). For an excellent solution to the perceived theoretical tension, see Gurtler (Reference Gurtler2003 and Reference Gurtler2008). Many of my interpretative claims here are inspired by Gurtler’s meticulous Aristotelian analysis.

2 “Co-constitutive” here means that these three aims are not instrumental to each other, but rather different sides of the same coin, so to speak. If one element were simply a means to another, it would be conditional, contingent, and thus unnecessary in itself. In the case of co-constitution, each of the elements implies the others. This means that social and environment aims are not pursued as a means to economic prosperity. Instead, the three elements constitute a system in which each part is essential, albeit as interdependent and in relation to the other elements. You cannot have one element without the other(s), because they essentially define and mutually influence each other—integral parts of a greater system (Hahn et al. Reference Hahn, Figge, Pinkse and Preuss2018; Carmine and De Marchi Reference Carmine and De Marchi2023).

3 I do so to keep my argument focused, but the analysis here could be extended to the social dimension of corporate sustainability as well, as the three elements are co-constitutive.

4 The “whole” (holon) is a very complex and obscure concept in Aristotle’s thought and a full explanation of it and its various uses requires a metaphysical analysis that goes beyond the scope of this paper—engaging what is often called the “problem of universals” therein, which relates to “form” in the Platonic tradition (see Yu Reference Yu2003 for an excellent analysis the concept in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Reference Apostle1979). For the purposes of this paper, the whole refers to what is universal not in a rigid Kantian sense (see Alzola Reference Alzola2015), but in the sense that it is a good or truth that is shared, i.e., a common (rather than particular) good in which various parts participate (see Mayhew Reference Mayhew1997 and Walker Reference Walker2018). To say that something is good according to the whole or in connection with the whole means that it is something that is unconditionally good, in itself, for its own sake and also in relation to everything else in the cosmos (Walker Reference Walker2018). As I will explain in this section, attending to the whole signifies a style of thinking and feeling (an attitude and mood) that grasps being-with and sharing a world with others, rather than being an individual agent in a vacuum maximizing utility. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for helping me clarify what this experience entails.

5 I thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing many of these important issues to my attention to help me develop and also delimit my argument.

References

REFERENCES

Alzola, Miguel. 2015. “Virtuous Persons and Virtuous Actions in Business Ethics and Organizational Research.” Business Ethics Quarterly 25 (3): 132.10.1017/beq.2015.24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, St. Thomas. 1964. Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Litzinger, C. I., O.P. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company.Google Scholar
Aristotle. 1979. Metaphysics. Edited and translated by Apostle, Hippocrates G.. Des Moines, IA: Peripatetic Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics. Edited and translated by Ostwald, Martin. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Arjoon, Surendra, Turriago-Hoyos, Alvaro, and Thoene, Ulf. 2018. “Virtuousness and the Common Good as a Conceptual Framework for Harmonizing the Goals of the Individual, Organizations, and the Economy.” Journal of Business Ethics 147: 143–63.10.1007/s10551-015-2969-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balarezo, Remy, and Corcuera, Paul. 2020. “Micro-Foundations of Corporate Sustainability.” In Knowledge Management for Corporate Social Responsibility, edited by Castro, Gregorio Martín-de and González-Masip, Jaime, 288314. Hershey, PA: IGI Global Scientific Publishing.Google Scholar
Bansal, Pratima. 2005. “Evolving Sustainably: A Longitudinal Study of Corporate Sustainable Development.” Strategic Management Journal 26 (3): 197218.10.1002/smj.441CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernacchio, Caleb, Foss, Nicolai, and Lindenberg, Siegwart. 2024. “The Virtues of Joint Production: The Ethical Foundations for Collaborative Organizations.” Academy of Management Review 49 (1): 155–81.10.5465/amr.2019.0389CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bina, Olivia, and Vaz, Sofia. 2011. “Humans, Environment and Economies: From Vicious Relationships to Virtuous Responsibility.” Ecological Economics 72: 170–78.10.1016/j.ecolecon.2011.09.029CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bragues, George. 2006. “Seek the Good Life, Not Money: The Aristotelian Approach to Business Ethics.” Journal of Business Ethics 67 (4): 341–57.10.1007/s10551-006-9026-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, Talbot. 2009. The Retrieval of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557882.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bright, David S., Winn, Bradley A., and Kanov, Jason. 2014. “Reconsidering Virtue: Differences of Perspective in Virtue Ethics and the Positive Social Sciences.” Journal of Business Ethics 119: 445–60.10.1007/s10551-013-1832-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bromiley, Philip, and Rau, Devaki. 2016. “Social, Behavioral, and Cognitive Influences on Upper Echelons During Strategy Process: A Literature Review.” Journal of Management 42 (1): 174202.10.1177/0149206315617240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrch, Christine, Milne, Markus J., Morgan, Richard, and Kearins, Kate. 2015. “Seeds of Hope? Exploring Business Actors’ Diverse Understandings of Sustainable Development.” Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal 28 (5): 671705.10.1108/AAAJ-08-2013-1438CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, Kim, and Spreitzer, Gretchen, eds. 2012. The Oxford Handbook of Positive Organizational Scholarship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, Kim, and Winn, Bradley. 2012. “Virtuousness.” In The Oxford Handbook of Positive Organizational Scholarship, edited by Cameron, Kim and Spreitzer, Gretchen, 231–43. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carmine, Simone, and De Marchi, Valentina. 2023. “Reviewing Paradox Theory in Corporate Sustainability Toward a Systems Perspective.” Journal of Business Ethics 184 (4): 139–58.10.1007/s10551-022-05112-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Constantinescu, Mihaela, and Kaptein, Muel. 2020. “Ethics Management and Ethical Management: Mapping Criteria and Interventions to Support Responsible Management Practice.” In Research Handbook of Responsible Management, edited by Laasch, Oliver, Suddaby, Roy, Freeman, R. E., and Jamali, Dima. New York: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Crockett, Carter. 2005. “The Cultural Paradigm of Virtue.” Journal of Business Ethics 62 (2): 191208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas, and Preston, Lee E.. 1995. “The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and Implications.” Academy of Management Review 20 (1): 6591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duerr, Maia. 2004. “The Contemplative Organization.” Journal of Organizational Change Management 17 (1): 4361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1970. “The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase its Profits.” New York Times Magazine, September 13. https://www.nytimes.com/1970/09/13/archives/a-friedman-doctrine-the-social-responsibility-of-business-is-to.html.Google Scholar
Gelles, David. 2022. “Billionaire No More: Patagonia Founder Gives Away the Company.” New York Times, September 15. https://www.nytimes.com/2022/09/14/climate/patagonia-climate-philanthropy-chouinard.html.Google Scholar
Gladwin, Thomas, Kennelly, James, and Krause, Tara-Shelomith. 1995. “Shifting Paradigms for Sustainable Development: Implications for Management Theory and Research.” Academy of Management Review 20 (4): 874907.10.2307/258959CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gurtler, Gary M. 2003. “The Activity of Happiness in Aristotle’s Ethics.” The Review of Metaphysics 56 (4): 801–34.Google Scholar
Gurtler, Gary M. 2008. “Happiness and Teleology in Aristotle.” Yearbook of the Irish Philosophical Society.Google Scholar
Hahn, Tobias, Figge, Frank, Pinkse, Jonathan, and Preuss, Lutz. 2015. “Tensions in Corporate Sustainability: Towards an Integrative Framework.” Journal of Business Ethics 127: 297316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hahn, Tobias, Figge, Frank, Pinkse, Jonathan, and Preuss, Lutz. 2018. “A Paradox Perspective on Corporate Sustainability: Descriptive, Instrumental, and Normative Aspects.” Journal of Business Ethics 148: 235–48.10.1007/s10551-017-3587-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hambrick, Donald C. 2007. “Upper Echelons Theory: An Update.” Academy of Management Review 32 (2): 334–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, Edwin. 2013. Virtue in Business: Conversations with Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139344265CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hickel, Jason. 2020. “What Does Degrowth Mean? A Few Points of Clarification.” Globalizations 18 (7): 1105–11.10.1080/14747731.2020.1812222CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnsen, Christian Garmann. 2020. “Sustainability Beyond Instrumentality: Towards an Immanent Ethics of Organizational Environmentalism.” Journal of Business Ethics 172 (4): 114.10.1007/s10551-019-04411-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, Steven. 2018. “Are U.S. Companies Too Short‐Term Oriented? Some Thoughts.” Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 30 (4): 818.10.1111/jacf.12313CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Küpers, Wendelin. 2005. “Phenomenology and Integral Pheno-practice of Embodied Well-be(com)ing in Organizations.” Culture and Organization 1 (3): 221–31.10.1080/14759550500204142CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lankoski, Leena, and Smith, N. Craig. 2018. “Alternative Objective Functions for Firms.” Organization & Environment 31 (3): 242–62.10.1177/1086026617722883CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macintyre, Alasdair. 2007. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. 3rd ed. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Maletič, Matjaž, Maletič, Damjan, Dahlgaard, Jens J., Dahlgaard-Parkand, Su Mi, and Gomišček, Boštjan. 2014. “Sustainability Exploration and Sustainability Exploitation: From a Literature Review Towards a Conceptual Framework.” Journal of Cleaner Production 79: 182–94.10.1016/j.jclepro.2014.05.045CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayhew, Robert. 1997. “Part and Whole in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy.” Journal of Ethics 1 (4): 325–40.10.1023/A:1009743012461CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 2001. Utilitarianism. Edited by Sher, George. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Moore, Geoff. 2015. “Corporate Character, Corporate Virtues.” Business Ethics: A European Review 24 (S2): 99114.10.1111/beer.12100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, Geoff. 2016. “Corporate Agency, Character, Purpose and the Common Good.” In The Challenges of Capitalism for Virtue Ethics and the Common Good, edited by Akrivou, Kleio and Sison, Alejo José. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha Craven. 1990. Love’s Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ostwald, Martin, trans. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Painter-Morland, Mollie. 2011. Business Ethics as Practice: Ethics as the Everyday Business of Business. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Painter-Morland, Mollie, Demuijnck, Geert, and Ornati, Sara. 2017. “Sustainable Development and Well-Being: A Philosophical Challenge.” Journal of Business Ethics 146: 295311.10.1007/s10551-017-3658-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patagonia. 2022. “Our Core Values.” https://www.patagonia.com/core-values/.Google Scholar
Pereira, Daniel. 2023. “Is Patagonia Profitable?” The Business Model Analyst, April 17. https://businessmodelanalyst.com/is-patagonia-profitable/.Google Scholar
Quinn, Robert E., and Wellman, Ned. 2012. “Positive Change Attributes.” In The Oxford Handbook of Positive Organizational Scholarship, edited by Cameron, Kim and Spreitzer, Gretchen, 751–62. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roochnik, David. 2009. “What Is Theoria? Nicomachean Ethics Book 10.7–8.” Classical Philology 104 (1): 6982.10.1086/603572CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Satchell, Liam Paul, Kaaronen, Roope Oskari, and Latzman, Robert D.. 2021. “An Ecological Approach to Personality: Psychological Traits as Drivers and Consequences of Active Perception.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 15 (5): 114.10.1111/spc3.12595CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shrivastava, P. 1994. “CASTRATED Environment: GREENING Organizational Studies.” Organization Studies 15 (5): 705–26.10.1177/017084069401500504CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon-Kucher. 2024. “Sustainability’s New Normal: What 2024 Consumers Expect.” June 12. https://www.simon-kucher.com/en/insights/sustainabilitys-new-normal-what-2024-consumers-expect.Google Scholar
Sison, Alejo José, and Ferrero, Ignacio. 2015. “How Different Is Neo-Aristotelian Virtue from Positive Organizational Virtuousness?Business Ethics: A European Review 24: 7898.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sison, Alejo José, and Fontrodona, Joan. 2012. “The Common Good of the Firm in the Aristotelian-Thomistic Tradition.” Business Ethics Quarterly 22 (2): 211–46.10.5840/beq201222218CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, Robert. 1999. A Better Way to Think about Business: How Personal Integrity Leads to Corporate Success. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780195112382.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Vincent, and Chouinard, Yvon. 2023. The Future of the Responsible Company: What We’ve Learned from Patagonia’s First 50 Years. Ventura, CA: Patagonia Books.Google Scholar
Summers, J., and Smith, L.. 2014. “The Role of Social and Intergenerational Equity in Making Changes in Human Well-being Sustainable.” AMBIO: A Journal of the Human Environment 43 (6): 718–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Paul. 1981. “The Ethics of Respect for Nature.” Environmental Ethics 3 (3): 197218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troje, Danielle. 2023. “Path Dependencies and Sustainable Facilities Management: A Study of Housing Companies in Sweden.” Building Research & Information 5 (8): 965–78.10.1080/09613218.2023.2216795CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Visser, Wayne. 2007. “Corporate Sustainability and the Individual: A Literature Review.” Cambridge Programme for Sustainability Leadership Paper Series 1: 115.Google Scholar
Vucetich, John, and Nelson, Michael. 2010. “Sustainability: Virtuous or Vulgar.” BioScience 60 (7): 539–44.10.1525/bio.2010.60.7.9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, Matthew. 2018. Aristotle on the Uses of Contemplation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781108363341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolcott, Gregory. 2015. “The New (Old) Case for the Ethics of Business.” Journal of Business Ethics 132 (1): 127–46.10.1007/s10551-014-2314-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yu, Jiyuan. 2003. The Structure of Being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic.10.1007/978-94-010-0055-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar