Hostname: page-component-54dcc4c588-b5cpw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-10-04T08:58:12.889Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

International society as an ontological security provider: a framework for analysis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 October 2025

Jason Ralph*
Affiliation:
School of Politics and International Studies, University of Leeds , Leeds, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

How might international society serve as an ontological security provider? Ontological security studies sees societies as both containers of anxiety and providers of security, but there is little research on how international society relates to this. Any answer to my question is further complicated by multiple takes (Lacanian, Kleinian, and Winnicottian) on the way the subject secures its self. I demonstrate how this multiplicity is accommodated by the conceptual heterogeneity of the ‘English School’ and offer three separate answers. Lacanian theory suggests a ‘pluralist’ international society can mitigate ontological insecurity because its institutions encircle ‘the lack’ that constitutes (collective) subjectivity. Kleinian theory supports the institutions of a ‘thin solidarist’ international society because it demonstrates how the collective action needed to protect the legal rights that recognise and secure the (collective) self does not necessarily cause anxiety. Drawing on Winnicott, Honneth argues that the (collective) self can only be fully secured if the institutions of a ‘thick solidarist’ international society go beyond legal recognition to socially esteem the contribution the subject makes to realising the common good. The analytical framework is applied to interpret and respond to Russia’s invasion of Ukraine, offering a timely intervention into debates on a post-liberal international order.

Information

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided that no alterations are made and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use and/or adaptation of the article.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press

How might international society serve as an ontological security provider? Ontological security studies (OSS) are familiar with the idea that societies ‘act both as containers for individual members’ anxieties and providers of defence systems against anxiety.’Footnote 1 There has, however, been little research on how international society relates to this point. Indeed, the literature stops short of this level of analysis, listing either ‘states, nations, ethnic groups, or minorities’ as the containers of anxiety and the providers of ontological security.Footnote 2 At the same time, the approach most associated with the study of international society – the English School (ES) – is yet to fully engage with ontological security as a concept, or as a research agenda in International Relations (IR).Footnote 3 The purpose of international society from the ES perspective is to provide ‘order’ or ‘a pattern of human activity that sustains elementary, primary, or universal goals of social life.’Footnote 4 This focus on a ‘pattern of human activity’ overlaps with OSS’s focus on the ‘routines’ that provide the subject (either individual or collective) with a secure sense of self.Footnote 5 The ES, however, concentrates on the ‘institutions’ that constitute international order (e.g., international law, balance of power, and diplomacy) and how they relate to ‘justice’ claims in general,Footnote 6 or as they relate specifically to human rights,Footnote 7 humanitarian intervention,Footnote 8 criminal prosecution,Footnote 9 international decision-making power,Footnote 10 or environmental stewardship.Footnote 11

Despite this gap between the ES and OSS, there is nothing to stop us from asking how the need to secure the self by living ‘vicariously’ through collective identity narratives is impacted by the social institutions that constitute international society.Footnote 12 In fact, there is a pressing reason why we should ask that question: some have argued that the liberal international order (LIO) is being undermined by the alienating consequences of its social institutions. More specifically, individuals within states, and states within international society, have experienced the anxiety of misrecognition, or ‘the gap between [a] … desired identity and how that person or group experiences being seen by others.’Footnote 13 In response, the ontologically insecure have turned to political movements that promise to overturn the institutions of the LIO and provide ontological security on different terms and to different groups.

The need to consider how international society (liberal or otherwise) might provide ontological security is therefore pressing, but that is far from straightforward. This is because within OSS, there are multiple arguments on the way the subject (individual or collective) secures its self, and how that process is influenced by ‘the Other,’ which can refer to another separate self or the institutions of (international) society.Footnote 14 The recent turn in OSS to the psychoanalytic theories of Lacan, Klein, and Winnicott (and I will add Honneth) captures this multiplicity. There are overlapping concerns across these approaches, but I am interested in the subtle differences that centre on the question of whether the subject realises its self through social institutions or in opposition to them. Lacanians tend to stress the possibility that the subject will lose its self in an overbearing society and will, as a response, transgress the social norms of the Other. Those drawing on the work of Klein and Winnicott emphasise the way subjects can securely identify with, and care for, the Other. Finally, Honneth, who is not a psychoanalyst but drew on Winnicott, argues that the subject can only fully realise its self if it draws ‘esteem’ from the performance of social roles that contribute to the collective good. The answer to the question of how international society serves as an ontological security provider is dependent on which reading of the subject one takes from OSS.

My answer cannot be singular, therefore. It is my contention, however, that this multiplicity can be accommodated by the conceptual and methodological heterogeneity of the ES approach. In Barry Buzan’s influential reading of the ES, an international society is constituted by rules, norms, and routines, which exist alongside an international system that is constituted by power-maximising or security-seeking states, as well as a world society where commitments to universalist ideologies transcend particular identities and state loyalties.Footnote 15 Even more helpful for my purpose is the way an international society of states is conceptualised as ‘pluralist’ or ‘solidarist.’ Pluralist institutions protect different identities by limiting the demands of international society, demands that – in the language of Lacanian OSS – create anxiety for a particular (national or otherwise collective) subjectivity.Footnote 16 Solidarist institutions, however, are more influenced by transnational ideologies and thus more demanding of the collective subject.Footnote 17 Where Lacanians might see this as anxiety-inducing, solidarist institutions can, from Honneth’s perspective, create the social roles that enable subjects to fully realise their separate self by identifying with a wider collective identity, contributing to the wider collective good in their own way, and then being socially recognised in ways that create self-esteem. My objective, therefore, is to demonstrate how the pluralist and solidarist distinction enables me to tailor the answer to my question so that it fits several different understandings of ontological (in)security.

To meet this objective, this paper has four sections. The first develops the Lacanian point that society (or ‘the big Other’) can be a source of ontological insecurity, and in these circumstances, the subject mitigates that insecurity by acting out the transgressive ‘fantasy.’ This speaks to the current argument that New Right ideologies are providing ontological security to disaffected communities by transgressing the liberal norms of international society.Footnote 18 It also reveals the potential for a form of agency that is more reflective because it ‘embraces anxiety.’Footnote 19 What that means for the structure of international institutions (as opposed to agency) is unclear, however, and potentially unhelpful. I turn, therefore, to another reading of Lacan. This argues that the anxiety of ontological insecurity is mitigated by the institutions of a pluralist international society. These institutions protect the shell of subjectivity – they ‘encircle the lack’ in Lacanian language – and that provides the space for self-determination. The antagonism of the friend (self) / enemy (other) fantasy, which is prominent in New Right ideologies, is replaced with something more substantive than the call to embrace anxiety. It is replaced with institutions that construct the political agonism of self-determining but mutually tolerant subjects. ES pluralists tend to refer to this as an ‘ethic of co-existence.’Footnote 20

The second section considers the implications for my question of a Kleinian approach to ontological security. This is important because the Kleinian argument that the subject can construct a self by identifying with (and even caring for) the Other reveals the possibility of a solidarist international society that provides ontological security by protecting a ‘thin’ layer of shared values: the sovereign rights (as expressed in international law) of other states. At this point, I look to Honneth because he makes clear the link between this kind of psychoanalysis (although he drew on Winnicott), its vision of the ontologically secure subject, and how that is realised through legal rights that codify sovereignty. I note, in the third section, however, that for Honneth, the legal institutions that recognise the (collective) self’s right to be what everyone else is (i.e., sovereign) do not enable the subject to fully realise its self (and thus escape anxiety). This is because these institutions do not recognise the self’s particular traits. Footnote 21 That shifts our attention from legal rights-based norms to social norms of (international) status and to a ‘thicker’ sense of shared values.Footnote 22 An international society based on shared social values provides ontological security by expressing solidarity with the subject – and thus ‘esteeming’ it – when it contributes to the realisation of those values. A solidarist international society, in other words, enables the collective subject recognised as a legally sovereign state to distinguish its self when it fulfils roles that are socially valuable. The final section illustrates the interpretive value of my framework by applying it to the question of Russian ontological insecurity and the invasion of Ukraine.

A pluralist and agonistic international society as an ontological security provider

Ontological security is a concept that originated in psychoanalysis.Footnote 23 It focuses on ‘the management of anxiety in the constitution of the self.’Footnote 24 It also appears in sociology, especially the work of Anthony Giddens.Footnote 25 The emphasis here is on the personal ‘need for cognitive consistency and biographical continuity – a security of ‘being’ – especially in a world shaken with the dislocations of late modernity.’Footnote 26 IR research has applied this concept to help explain state behaviour. Brent Steele, for example, argues that states ‘seek ontological security because they want to maintain consistent self-concepts and the “Self” of states is constituted through a narrative that gives life to routinised foreign policy actions.’ When events disrupt those narratives, actors ‘will seek to re-establish routines that can, once again, consistently maintain self-identity.’Footnote 27 More recently, leading voices in OSS have called for a return to the psychoanalytic (and existentialist) study of anxiety to address a normative concern that the sociological emphasis on consistency and routine is too conservative.Footnote 28 In response, OSS has turned to Lacanian psychoanalysis, but the implication for international society as an ontological security provider is currently unclear. In this first section, I will summarise what Lacanian psychoanalysis brings to OSS and identify those implications. As the left side of Table 1 illustrates, those implications vary depending on which reading one chooses.

Table 1. International society as an ontological security provider

From a Lacanian perspective, anxiety stems from a moment of self-recognition that is prior to social interaction. This is captured in Lacan’s theory of ‘the mirror stage’ in a child’s development. As Richard Lynch put it: ‘For Lacan, the “original organization of the forms of the ego” is precipitated in an infant’s self-recognition in a mirror image.’Footnote 29 At this point, the subject ‘anticipates’Footnote 30 or ‘imagines’Footnote 31 a coherence and unity of self. Lacan calls this the ‘imaginary’ or ‘ideal-I.’Footnote 32 But the mirror stage is also a moment of unsettling misrecognition because even the bodily image in the mirror can seem strange or inaccessible. That sense of alienation increases in social interaction as the ‘social-I’ ultimately fails to deliver the yearned-for sense of coherence. This ‘splitting’ of the subject results in what is variously referred to as ‘lack,’Footnote 33 ‘primordial loss,’Footnote 34 or ‘alienation.’Footnote 35 The ‘lack’ one experiences in society can, however, be positive. It creates desire, which works ‘as the motor of human agency.’Footnote 36 ‘Lack’ constitutes subjectivity, therefore. Alienation may be disaffecting, but the distance it creates can also be liberating. It enables a subject to recognise an individual self even if that self can never be fulfilled.

Lacan further argued that the lack of ‘lack’ – which occurs when the separation between self and society collapses – is another source of anxiety.Footnote 37 In response to this situation, the subject can recover its self through the ‘jouissance’ of transgression.Footnote 38 Jouissance gives expression to the subject’s desire, which is ‘aimed at recouping that which cannot be symbolised’ (i.e., the lack that constitutes subjectivity).Footnote 39 A ‘fantasy’ for social ‘objects’ promising fulfilment (e.g., consumer goods, sexual partners, or political goals)Footnote 40 also serves this purpose. By giving expression to desire, and thus subjectivity, a ‘fantasy’ recreates the imaginary space where the ideal-I ‘can take refuge.’Footnote 41 The concept of ‘fantasy,’ as a type of narrative, is thus important to Lacanians because it indicates how self-fulfilment, and a sense of ontological coherence, is always distant. This is because anxiety only increases when the subject ‘realises that the imagined wholeness does not live up to the promise of the fantasy.’Footnote 42 The focus on ‘fantasy’ is also important because it ‘renders visible’Footnote 43 the fact that all narratives perform the same function, which is to ‘impose closure on the ambiguities and complexities of the social world.’Footnote 44 Once this is accepted, we begin to see the ‘potential for the emergence of a radical, potentially emancipatory, politics driven by an active, wilful agency that embraces anxiety.’Footnote 45

This is an important contribution, but the emphasis in the call to ‘embrace anxiety’ is on ‘agency.’Footnote 46 This is understandable, given the Lacanian argument that the ‘symbolic’ order – the ‘universe of discourse’ or the ‘big Other’ – merely creates the illusion of security.Footnote 47 That does not help, however, when trying to answer my central question: How might the institutions of international society serve as an ontological security provider? This is why a question mark appears in Table 1. Indeed, we might conceptually locate this reading of Lacan on the lines that mark the process of transition between types of international society. A reflective process that questions old routines as part of a learning process inevitably creates anxiety. But then, if Lacanians do not substantively and normatively distinguish social institutions – because all of them ‘impose closure’ – they are limited to a position of constant negative critique.Footnote 48 That too can be valuable as a defence against complacency, but again, it does not answer my question of how international society can provide ontological security; and for some, the lack of a positive social vision often fails to mobilise the political support that is necessary to effect emancipatory change.Footnote 49

We might ask, therefore, if a positive vision of international society is possible from the Lacanian perspective; and, if it is, what kinds of institutions constitute that society. This (again) is a difficult question to answer, because the visions of a good society created by moral philosophy are problematic for Lacan. They attempt ‘to reinstate the big Other, the symbolic system … as a harmonious unified whole by referring it to a single positive principle’ and that creates anxiety for the subject.Footnote 50 Indeed, Lacan writes that the social and moral conscience attached to such visions can become ‘crueller and crueller’ as they ‘seek us out at the most intimate levels of our impulses or desires.’Footnote 51 From this perspective, moral philosophy represses desire, and therefore subjectivity, in the name of the public good. The threat that transgressive behaviour will be named and shamed to advance norm compliance – which is central to some versions of ES constructivism – is thus a source of ontological insecurity.

The pursuit of a moral or public good can, moreover, lead to tragic outcomes. Lacan tells us this in his discussion of the fifth-century BC Greek play Antigone, which appears in The Ethics of Psychoanalysis. Footnote 52 By defying King Creon’s order that her dead brother is not to be buried (because the public good demands he be shamed), Antigone acts on ‘pure’ desire. This is because she knows her transgression will lead to her death.Footnote 53 There is a clash of social norms here, but Antigone’s choice is read by Lacan as being based on desire, and the ontological need to separate herself from the symbolic order represented by Creon.Footnote 54 Once in the cave where she had been buried alive as punishment, Antigone commits suicide, only for the King to order her to be released after realising sufficient homage had been paid to the law. The King’s actions, however, lead to the loss of his own family when his son, who was engaged to Antigone, also takes his own life, an action that leads to the death of his mother. The implication is that such tragic consequences could have been avoided had the institution of law (Creon) paid more homage to human desire (Antigone). Creon’s error of judgment, Lacan writes, ‘is to want to promote the good of all … as the law without limits, the sovereign law, the law that goes beyond or crosses the limit.’Footnote 55

This might reinforce my point that the subject (Antigone) is moved to transgress the law (Creon) to secure subjectivity. But it can also be read as saying a legal order can be supported if it is limited in a way that respects what Lacan calls ‘the Real.’Footnote 56 One can ignore the reality of a subject’s anxiety (as Creon did) and continue to wonder why the subject does not comply with the public ‘ethics of harmony,’ or one can open up ‘our symbolic resources to uncertainty’Footnote 57 and adopt an ‘ethics of the Real.’Footnote 58 Contained in this latter position is, I suggest, a positive vision of an international society that goes beyond the focus on agency and negative critique. It is a pluralist vision committed to international norms and institutions because that shields multiple subjectivities against what are otherwise considered to be the overbearing demands of solidarists who are committed to an ethic of international harmony. It is, in short, committed to an international society that mitigates ontological insecurity by institutionalising the practices that allocate space for the subject to determine its self by itself.

It is important, for my subsequent analysis, to note the subtle shift of focus in this section. The issue is not simply how the subject recognises its self in society, it is how, and on what basis, the self recognises and associates with the Other. This shift to an other-regarding focus, and the practices that institutionalise it, will be a welcome shift to those who bemoan the ‘Self-regarding modalities of OS.’Footnote 59 Indeed, one might argue that it is a democratic ethos that emerges from a Lacanian respect for the dignity of the subject. Importantly, however, this democratic ethos ‘is not (or should not be) based on the vision of a utopian harmonious society. It is based on the recognition of the impossibility and the catastrophic consequences of such a dream.’Footnote 60 This again resonates with ES visions of international society. As noted, an international society that recognises differences and protects the principle of ‘national’ or collective self-determination through statehood is a check against the imperialist tendencies of philosophies that claim to identify an ethic of harmony across world society. At the same time, the ES vision of international society intervenes in the logics of anarchy to limit the antagonisms and misrecognitions that arise when states are insufficiently other-regarding.

The other-regarding ethos of the Lacanian-inspired pluralist international society (see Table 1) is limited for good reason, therefore. International recognition is extended to a collective subjectivity not because it complies with the moral standards and cosmopolitan identities that solidarists believe are universally applicable. International recognition is extended to subjectivities simply to mitigate their ontological insecurity and without pretension of interfering in the processes that define their collective identity.Footnote 61 International recognition in this sense constitutes something akin to a vase, which is a metaphor Lacan uses. It merely gives shape to an empty space that enables subjectivity to emerge. Put differently, international recognition ‘encircles’ the ‘lack’ that the subject feels in more solidaristic and more demanding societies. Pluralist society respects the reality of that feeling and gives space for the subject to realise and recognise its self.Footnote 62 Legal recognition of this kind ‘creates [an international] public space – a certain unifying field,’ but it does not aim to establish harmony and reconciliation.Footnote 63 The aim rather is the ‘partial emancipation’ of establishing ‘unity within an environment of conflict and diversity.’Footnote 64 Although those are the words of a Lacanian scholar, they could just as easily be the words of an ES pluralist.Footnote 65

One final point is necessary before moving the analysis along the spectrum illustrated in Table 1. The above reference to ‘conflict’ hints at the way pluralist international society helps diverse national or collective subjectivities realise their selves. The conflict envisaged in a pluralist international society is not the unlimited antagonism of the Hobbesian international system described by the ES, but the agonism of a pluralist international society based on a mutual recognition. This enables the subject to realise its self by defining the other as an adversary but not as an enemy to be destroyed.Footnote 66 Chantal Mouffe explains the distinction more fully. The adversary in a pluralistic (international) society is

somebody with whose ideas we are going to struggle, but whose right to defend those ideas we will not put into question. This category of the adversary does not eliminate, and it should be distinguished from the liberal competitor, with which it is sometimes identified. An adversary is a legitimate enemy, an enemy with whom we have in common a shared adhesion to the ethico-political principles of democracy [as mutual recognition]. But our disagreement concerning their meaning and implementation is not one that could be resolved through rational discussion, hence the antagonistic element in the relation … To be sure, compromises are possible; they are part of the process of politics. But they should be seen as temporary respites in an ongoing confrontation.Footnote 67

Mouffe is interesting to cite here because she argued in 2007 that agonism in international society translates into ‘the establishment of a multipolar world order’ to check the ‘unchallenged hegemony of the United States,’ a theme we find articulated in the more recent geopolitical narratives on the New Right.Footnote 68 This demonstrates the political character of such an approach, and a reason why the balance of power might be prioritised over international law as an institution of international society. Indeed, Bull articulated a similar thought when he discussed the relationship between the institutions of anarchical societies and how ‘the great powers’ may have to violate the legal principle of self-determination to politically check each other’s imperial ambitions.Footnote 69 This argument does not necessarily follow from either Lacanian OSS or pluralist ES, but it does raise a problem when considering what the balance of power as an institution of international society means for nations or peoples that are not ‘great powers.’ That problem was keenly experienced during the Cold War when superpower ‘spheres of influence’ subsumed many subjectivities in the name of the international public good. It is a problem I return to in the final section when I apply my framework to interpret Russia’s invasion of Ukraine.

A solidarist and rights-based international society as an ontological security provider

To recap, the previous section argued that a conception of international society that the ES call ‘pluralist’ could mitigate the anxieties collective subjects experience when confronted by the Other, which may be another self, or Lacan’s ‘big Other,’ that is, the rules, norms, expectations, and institutions of wider society. In this conception of international society, collective subjectivities are allowed to determine their self-identity and seek ontological security free from wider interference. The collective identity (e.g., nation or people) is recognised as sovereign, and international society is organised politically to provide ontological security on that basis. One way of politically organising international society along these lines is to codify the principle of national or collective self-determination in law, and that has been at the centre of the liberal order based on the UN Charter.Footnote 70 It is difficult to find a discussion of this document as an ontological security provider. For Nina Krickel-Choi, however, the practice of legally recognising a collective identity as a sovereign state is not merely a de jure codification of the de facto power to govern a particular territory; it is more emotionally charged than that.Footnote 71 Narratives of collective identity provide subjects with an ontologically secure sense of self, and because that is the case, international society’s relationship to that narrative is ontologically significant. An international symbolic order that legally recognises the collective identity as a self-determining sovereign state provides ontological security; conversely, an international society creates anxiety when it does not legally recognise a collective identity with a strong sense of self (e.g., the Palestinian people).

The possibility that an international society can mitigate ontological insecurity through the mutual recognition of the subject’s legal sovereign status thus exists in theory and – to a certain extent – in practice. International society can provide a degree of ontological security by recognising the collective self and its right to determine its identity free from the interference of an Other. There is a problem, however. The ontological security provided by an international society that recognises the collective identity as a sovereign state is likely to come with a correlative set of legal obligations and social responsibilities. These might be minimal, for instance, the self’s responsibility simply to respect another self’s sovereignty by not interfering in the routines it chooses to live by. Or they might be more demanding, for example, the self’s responsibility to come to the assistance of another self when its security (ontological and/or physical) is being threatened by a transgressor. The latter scenario is a problem for the Lacanian argument because the agonistic relationship (with the other as adversary) is tipping over into a cooperative relationship (with the other as friend). In this case, the pluralist order is tipping over into a solidarist order, with the latter making normative claims that may give rise to anxiety in the self.Footnote 72 As we know from the Lacanian perspective, the individual and/or collective subject becomes anxious and ontologically insecure when the distance between the self and the Other collapses.

This might be where the answer to my opening question concludes. Lacanian-inspired pluralism may insist that the way international society provides ontological security is to politically construct an order through a thin layer of law. This enables the national subject to determine its self by itself but places strict limits on solidaristic appeals to the international common good. That, however, is potentially unsatisfactory for reasons I alluded to above. It does not satisfactorily deal with the question of legal transgression. What happens to a collective subjectivity – such as the Palestinian and Ukrainian one – when they are denied full recognition (and therefore ontological security) because power is stacked against them? If international society is to provide ontological security, should it not act in solidarity with these collective subjectivities? That is an important question, but OSS also forces us to ask a prior question. Can international society demand this level of solidarity without itself causing anxiety in the subject? The Lacanian argument suggests it cannot, but from another perspective, it is possible that the collective subject can realise its self not by rejecting the demands of the big Other but by caring for another self in ways that are consistent with the expectations of a solidaristic international society. I argue in this section that this is possible for reasons the psychoanalytic theory of Melanie Klein alerts us to.Footnote 73

The aspect of Klein’s approach that is important here is what she referred to as ‘the depressive position.’Footnote 74 This is the moment in psychological development when ‘ego capacities enlarge’ and ‘anxiety is also felt on behalf of the object.’Footnote 75 This enables engagement of the other ‘as like the self.’ From there, a relationship can be based on ‘mutual recognition, even if as adversaries (but not as enemies).’Footnote 76 Gellwitzki and Houde apply this, and Klein’s related concepts of ‘introjection’ and ‘projection’ to IR, and specifically to the case of Germany’s identification with the European Union (EU) during the so-called refugee crisis of 2015. Where that crisis caused a rupture in the German sense of its wider European identity, a sense of solidarity was nevertheless maintained through introjection. In other words, German identity discourses were able to internalise the ‘good part’ of the European other (e.g., Brussels) and that part of a ‘contemporary German’ self. At the same time, those discourses were able to externalise the ‘bad part’ of a past German self by projecting it onto a “bad other”’ (e.g., Visegrád).Footnote 77 In this instance, ontological security was found not by retreating from the social expectations of – and solidarities toward – a wider society, ontological security was, in fact, found in a positive identification with that society. That positive vision then enabled the subject to consolidate the process of becoming a different self.

There is an overlap here with my first reading of Lacan and the emphasis on agency. It is important for my purpose, however, because it also suggests national or otherwise collective subjects can positively and securely identify with a solidarist form of international society that recognises them as sovereign states and requires them to protect others (and the legal institution of sovereign equality) when they are threatened by transgressive behaviours. It suggests, in other words, that self-determining states can securely identify as being part of a wider collective or international self. From a Kleinian perspective, it is possible for the subject to do this without causing the kind of anxiety that the Lacanian anticipates. This is because the otherwise threatening Other can be ‘split’ between the ‘good part-object’ – that is, an international society that protects sovereign equality based on national or collective self-determination – and ‘bad part-object’ – that is, a transgressor that violates these principles because it is acting out certain (e.g., imperial) fantasies. In this way, the principle of collective security, which we also find codified in the liberal order based on the UN Charter, can (in theory) act as an ontological security provider. The principle of sovereign equality enables the national or collective subject to recognise its self by existing without foreign interference, but the same subject is also able to see its self as part of a solidarist international society that protects that principle when it is threatened.

Indeed, this is how John Cash interprets Kleinian psychoanalysis and its implications for international society. He does not use ES language, but the inference is similar. He ‘re-conceptualises’ Wendt’s cultures of anarchy ‘and their different modes of relating,’ and argues subjects can draw on these as ‘cultural repertoires’ to mitigate anxiety.Footnote 78 These repertoires are ‘co-present’ and always available (thus the subject ‘dwells in ambivalence’),Footnote 79 which means ontological security can be restored after disruption by ‘rebalancing’ or ‘reweighting’ their ‘performative presence.’Footnote 80 The self’s ‘need to maintain a sense of a coherent identity that is centred, consistent, and continues through time and changing circumstances’ is thus regarded by Cash as a helpful self-misrecognition. It is helpful because it can ‘support the imaginary sense of self as continuous across any actual discontinuities of narratives, mentalities, and practices that follow from a reconfiguration of the cultural repertoire.’Footnote 81 This relates to my point because it suggests the ‘ambivalent’ self is capable of acting in support of Wendt’s ‘Lockean’ culture, or solidarist international society, which protects the sovereignty of an adversary, without that creating anxiety or ontological insecurity.

Cash demonstrates this with reference to his own work on Northern Ireland. That case is an example of

one society where a re-weighting of the cultural repertoire by Lockean forms – introduced and strengthened by decades of concerted and conflicted political action – has established the legitimacy and propriety of alternative cultural supports and routine practices that organize social relations differently. Friend–enemy (or Hobbesian) formations have been partially, but not thoroughly, displaced, by adversary-neighbor (or Lockean) formations that support ontological security in a qualitatively distinct way, although not without some haunting after-effects.Footnote 82

It is possible then to conceive of (international) society as an ontological security provider in these – solidarist – terms. What I have referred to so far, however, is best referred to as a ‘thin’ form of solidarism. It is thin because the only expectation it has of national or collective subjects is that they recognise the right of each other to pursue ontological security through a process of self-determination that is free from outside interference. In this respect, it overlaps with the Lacanian-inspired pluralism, which insists international societies should merely ‘encircle the lack’ to mitigate the subject’s anxiety. But Kleinian-inspired thin ‘solidarism’ is conceptually distinct from pluralism because this kind of society also provides ontological security through institutionalised collective action that protects the right to self-determination. This, of course, begs the question of what ‘thick’ solidarism entails, and why some argue it is needed to provide ontological security. To answer that question, I now turn to the work of Axel Honneth.

A solidarist and esteem-based international society as an ontological security provider

Axel Honneth’s work is rarely referenced by the ES and OSS.Footnote 83 This is probably because he is pigeon-holed by IR as a Critical theorist who rarely writes on international matters. Honneth’s work is relevant to my question, however, because it connects the psychoanalytic theory of Donald Winnicott to a theory of social institutions and the role they play in helping the subject secure its self.Footnote 84 OSS has drawn on what Winnicott said about the home as a protective space in which the subject develops that sense of self,Footnote 85 but Honneth draws on Winnicott to support his Hegelian-inspired claim that the self relies on the recognition of others. Drawing on Winnicott, for instance, Honneth notes how the mother’s care, and child’s ‘absolute dependence,’ cannot be regarded as secondary to the processes forming subjectivity, which is an implication of Lacanian thought. The relationship to the mother (an Other) is more fundamental than that.

This is important for my argument because, as Honneth explains, the ‘narcissism’ that Freudian theory sees as ‘primary,’ is, in fact, replaced by ‘primary intersubjectivity’: mother and child (self and other) cannot be separated. Of course, the mother and the child do learn to separate, but the nature of the relationship remains crucial to the formation of an intersubjectivity. Mutual recognition of different selves is possible after the initial use of transitional objects (e.g., the child’s silk blanket), which point to a separate domain of reality, and then personality struggles (e.g., tantrums). In this phase of ‘relative dependence,’ the child learns that the mother’s continuing care involves recognising her subjectivity, and the mother learns that her subjectivity involves recognising the child’s emerging independence. In this way, the two subjects see their selves in the Other, and they are each constituted by the Other’s love (solidarity).Footnote 86

From Honneth’s Winnicott-inspired perspective, the subject needs the Other’s recognition to become (and secure) its self. Or, as Honneth puts it, the subject needs the Other’s recognition ‘to be alone without anxiety.’Footnote 87 He goes on to argue that relationships built on friendship or love provide this kind of ‘confidence’ (which I take to mean ontological security). This is because relationships built on friendship or love strike an appropriate balance between ‘the subject-based pole of an intersubjective tension’ and ‘the capacity for boundary-dissolving merging with the other.’Footnote 88 In other words, those in loving relationships draw ontological security from an ‘us’ identity that recognises, respects, and cherishes the individuality of its constitutive selves. It is difficult to transpose this kind of thinking to IR and the ontological security of collective subjects. Some do, however, use the concept of friendship at this level.Footnote 89 Friendship is, for instance, the defining feature of Wendt’s ‘Kantian’ culture. Writing more specifically in the field of OSS, Browning and Joenniemi characterise friendship as a relationship that entails ‘equality, respect, and solidarity.’ It is ‘premised on far-reaching similitude but also entails an acceptance of difference.’Footnote 90

At this point, there is nothing to distinguish this approach from the ‘thin’ solidarism protecting the legally codified sovereign rights of subjects, as discussed in the previous section. The international society that bestows the legal rights of statehood on collective identities, such as nations or peoples, has the same effect as love or friendship. It provides the kind of ontological security associated with what Honneth calls ‘self-respect’ because it creates the ‘sense of possessing the universal dignity of persons.’Footnote 91 The legal recognition of a subject is not, however, a simple matter of recognising an empirical reality. It is, in practice, a political act that reflects the social values and culture of international society.Footnote 92 This is important because it demonstrates that the ontological security that comes from being legally recognised as a sovereign state is dependent on a prior (and thicker) level of social and political solidarity across international society. Honneth makes this point, which I have adapted with square brackets to make the link clearer:

Even before legal agreements aimed at promoting peace [or providing recognition] can do their work, and even before the cultivation of diplomatic relations and economic agreements can reduce international tensions [and provide ontological security], we need publicly visible signals that the history and culture of other nations are worth being heard among the cacophony of world’s peoples.Footnote 93

An example of a ‘publicly visible signal’ cited by Honneth is Willy Brandt’s 1970 Warschauer Kniefall, which socially recognised the victims of the Warsaw ghetto, as well as the need for atonement, before the treaties of the détente period could legally recognise the political borders of the post-war Europe.Footnote 94

The point being made is this: if international society is constituted only by international law, and if (thin) solidarism is limited to protecting the rights of states under that law, it may fail to provide ontological security because not all collective identities have been allocated these legal rights. Furthermore, not all subjectivities live vicariously through those states that have been legally recognised. Individual subjectivities might seek recognition from international society in ways that cannot be satisfied if international recognition is based only on national or collective self-determination. This calls for a thicker sense of social solidarity with those individual subjectivities, and that implies a more demanding conception of international society based on, for instance, human as well as state rights. It ultimately means working to change the power structures that deny (international) legal rights to those subjectivities struggling to find ontological security.

This form of social recognition is also important because it has implications for ontological security after legal recognition is granted. While legal recognition is necessary for self-realisation, it is also insufficient. This is because legal personality is a form of recognition that is shared with all other members of (international) society. It is important in creating – in Honneth’s terms – ‘self-respect,’ but it cannot create ‘self-esteem.’ This is because legal recognition as a universal principle does not recognise the self’s particular traits. Footnote 95 In order to fully realise and secure the self, therefore, subjects need to ‘assure themselves of the social significance of their individual capacities’ in the light of a community’s ‘value-conviction.’Footnote 96 In other words, there needs to be something akin to a division of social labour in the context of common values if universal rights-bearing subjects are to feel a deeper sense of self-esteem. That comes from the solidarity that first motivates the self to contribute to the realisation of common values, and then leads the Other to appropriately recognise that individual contribution.

This is so important to Honneth’s theory of recognition that it is worth expanding with the following quotation, which also links it back to the themes Honneth took from Winnicott. Honneth writes:

The esteem that the child directly experiences, to begin with, in the affectionate attention of concrete others must dissolve into a form of recognition that offers intersubjective confirmation of one’s individually chosen way of life. In order to arrive at a ‘me’ that can provide this sort of ethical support, every individual must learn to generalize the value-convictions of all of [their] interaction partners sufficiently to get an abstract idea of the collective goals of the community. For it is only within the horizon of these commonly shared values that one can conceive oneself as a person who is distinguished from all others in virtue of a contribution to society’s life-process that is recognized as unique.Footnote 97

If international society is to provide ontological security, therefore, it needs – from this perspective – to be based on a commonly shared value system and extend social (as well as legal) recognition to a collective subject by virtue of those ‘traits and abilities’ that make a specific contribution to the realisation of that value system.Footnote 98 Here, the sense of ‘we-ness’ in what we might call an ‘ontological security community’ enables the subject to fully realise its self by acting in solidarity with that community and contributing, in its own way, to its values.Footnote 99

Such a society is based on a thicker sense of shared values, as well as a solidarity with other nations or peoples that contribute to the realisation of those values. I illustrated this point with reference to human rights, but I make no judgement here on what those values are. Clearly, there has been a strong tendency within the ES to equate solidarism with a commitment to human rights norms,Footnote 100 but there is nothing here to say collective subjectivities cannot draw ontological security from an international society that esteems a different set of shared values. Indeed, nations and peoples do experience self-esteem when contributing to other socially valued aspects of international and world society, for instance, scientific advancement, health care, cultural development, environmental stewardship, and sporting achievement.

Operationalising the framework: the past and possible transatlantic security community

An implication of Honneth’s Winnicott-inspired argument is that international society can provide mutual ontological security if its legal and social institutions are based on an intersubjective ‘we-ness.’ This finds expression in the concept of an (ontological) security community. I understand the end of the Cold War, and the articulation of a common security agenda based on a trans-Atlantic community – ‘from Vancouver to Vladivostok’ – in these terms.Footnote 101 But that begs the question of how we got from that moment to the present situation, where Ukrainian sovereignty and identity have been so blatantly violated by Russia. In this final section, I use the framework illustrated in Table 1 to answer that question and to interpret what is, of course, a profound challenge to liberal international society. I then draw recommendations for policymakers as they seek to move beyond that challenge.

Perhaps the most prominent argument on why Russia othered, securitised, and ultimately invaded Ukraine is John Mearsheimer’s Realist-inspired claim that the NATO alliance provoked such actions by expanding up to Russia’s border.Footnote 102 Mearsheimer’s Realism is centred on materialist explanations and concerns about physical security, but other arguments, with similar implications, speak more directly to questions of Russia’s ontological insecurity and the institutions of international society. For instance, Richard Sakwa argues that the Russian self left behind by Gorbachev was not imperialist. It was, in fact, committed to what I have called a ‘thin solidarist’ version of the LIO, which was based on the UN Charter. This kind of international society enabled the national or collective self-determination of states (including those of the former Soviet Union) by codifying in law the principle of sovereign equality. Furthermore, Russia’s permanent position on the UN Security Council was sufficient recognition of its particular traits as ‘a great power.’

The problem started, according to Sakwa, when Western states in effect marginalised the United Nations as the preeminent institution of the post-Cold War order. Their use of NATO and other ad hoc (but Western-centred) coalitions to (recklessly) promote liberal democracy (in Iraq, Libya, Syria, and Eastern Europe) created a sense of misrecognition in Russia. It disrespected Russia’s self-image as a political equal.Footnote 103 That then created the political conditions for Putin’s form of national renewal, which involved the transgressions of liberal norms, including the principle of sovereign equality and national or collective self-determination (especially in the post-Soviet space).Footnote 104 The implication here is that if Western policies had paid greater homage to ‘the Real’ (to repeat a Lacanian formulation), they would have recognised Russia’s ontological security needs and avoided these perverse outcomes.

Looking forward, one might conclude that international society should now, belatedly, recognise ‘the Real’ of Russian subjectivity. That would mean accepting Russia’s desire to occupy Ukraine as an expression of Russian authenticity, and – if we recall Mouffe’s Reference Mouffe, Odysseos and Petito2007 point – because that checks the power of an overbearing Western-led liberal hegemony. As I noted, however, accepting that is difficult because ‘Russian authenticity’ and ‘the balance of power’ disrespect the national or collective subjectivities of others, particularly those living on Russia’s borders. The deeper implication, therefore, is that if international society is to provide ontological security, it must be based on legal norms that codify the principle of national or collective self-determination and that demands, at least, a condemnation of Russian action. It further demands international solidarity with the Ukrainian subject as it defends its self – and its internationally recognised status as a sovereign state – against Russian misrecognition. It does not necessarily follow that international solidarity requires a commitment to provide military support, and there are well-rehearsed arguments why that may be imprudent. But as a social symbol of the esteem in which the Ukrainian self is held, the international provision of material support is an important way of providing ontological security.

A final consideration stems from a point Honneth informed, which is that collective subjects only fully realise their self (and experience ontological security) if international society goes beyond legal recognition to socially recognise their specific contribution to the international or global common good. I made the additional point that international society can do this by esteeming nations or peoples that contribute to the international and global common good across a wide range of indicators, for instance, cultural, scientific, environmental, and sporting achievement. When this is read alongside Kleinian-inspired arguments, it opens up what I would call a ‘thick solidarist’ response to Russia’s sense of ontological insecurity. Cash noted, for instance, that subjects hold a ‘repertoire’ of identities at any one time, and that over time, the self can rebalance their significance.Footnote 105 Similarly, Gellwitzki and Houde argue that a subject can identify with (and express solidarity toward) the ‘good part’ of an object while rejecting the ‘bad part.’Footnote 106

A thick solidarist international society would build on this and provide ontological security not only by esteeming the Ukrainian self, but also by addressing Russia’s ontological insecurity – condemning the narratives and routines that threaten Ukraine while esteeming those specific Russian traits that contribute to the international and global common good in other ways.Footnote 107 The practical recommendation, therefore, would be for international society to provide ontological security by defending Ukrainian subjectivity but without essentialising the Russian one. That recognises and values those individual subjects who identify as Russian but feel the affective pull of a post-imperial identity.Footnote 108 It mitigates their sense of anxiety, which might otherwise push them to support Putin and the kinds of policies that make others ontologically and physically insecure.

Conclusion

My objective has been to answer the question: How might international society serve as an ontological security provider? This is a valid question for theoretical and practical reasons. OSS tends to see states and substate groups as the containers of anxiety or providers of ontological security. It is useful to extend that focus, however, because just as individuals live vicariously through collective identities, such as nations, those collective identities themselves live and evolve in their own social context, international society. It is theoretically significant, therefore, to consider how the institutions of international society may (or may not) provide ontological security. Furthermore, this theoretical research has practical significance in our current moment. This is because the institutions that have constituted the so-called ‘LIO’ are now in a state of flux and possibly transition. Theoretically understanding what is at stake for processes that constitute the self, and how new orders may or may not provide ontological security, has a very practical significance therefore.Footnote 109 As I noted, however, the answer to my question is far from straightforward. This is in part because the theoretical approach that is most strongly associated with the study of international society – the ES – has not fully engaged with research on ontological security. My aim then has been to follow the lead set by Brent Steele and build a bridge between OSS and the ES approach.Footnote 110

I have demonstrated that the conceptual multiplicity of the ES approach, in particular the way it identifies pluralist and solidarist international societies, makes the construction of this bridge possible. With these concepts, the ES can help us understand how international society may provide ontological security, despite the existence of various arguments within OSS on the way the subject relates to social institutions. It is useful to think of this bridge as having three lanes, therefore. In lane one, I identified a pluralist international society, which mitigates the anxieties Lacanians tell us are persistent by ‘encircling the lack,’ that is, respecting the space in which the subject can determine its self without the demands of an overbearing society. In lane two, I identified a ‘thin’ solidarist international society, which provides ontological security by acting collectively to protect the legal right to national or collective self-determination when that is transgressed. We know from Klein and Winnicott’s psychoanalytic work that the subject can do this without experiencing anxiety because it can identify with – even care for – the Other. That can create an intersubjectivity or shared identity in which both self and Other are secure. The ‘I’ is secure in, and secured by, the ‘we.’

In lane three, I identified a ‘thick’ solidarist international society, which I developed from Honneth’s theory of recognition. This provides ontological security by focusing on social recognition as something that both precedes and follows legal recognition. It is worth lingering on Honneth to make one final concluding point. I noted at the beginning that the ES focus on international society as the provider of ‘order’ had not engaged with the OSS focus on ‘self,’ but it had built a research agenda around the way institutions of international order interacted with conceptions of ‘justice.’ Honneth, in fact, argued that the self-respect and the self-esteem that subjects drew from legal and social institutions were forms of justice.Footnote 111 If we adopt the same language, then I think my framework can be used to bring a critical edge to the ES and OSS research agendas. If we walk with Honneth across my bridge in lane three and accept his view of the (collective) subject and (international) society, and if we accept that legal and social recognition is a matter of (international) justice, then it enables us to be critical of an (international) society that is not constituted by what I have called ‘thick’ solidarism. We might also experience ‘ethical anxiety’ amidst such injustice.Footnote 112 It follows that if we walk across my bridge in lanes one and two, we will come to a different conclusion.

Acknowledgements

This paper was first presented at the EISA European Workshop for International Studies, Kadir Has University, Istanbul, 2–5 July, 2024. Thanks to Thomas Diez and Bahar Rumelili for organising the section, and to the participants, especially my discussant, Alistair Markland. Thanks also to Ali Bilgic, Maysam Behravesh, Erman Ermihan, Nicolai Gellwitzki, Brent Steele, Matthew Weinert, three anonymous reviewers, and the International Theory editorial team.

Funding statement

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interests

The author declares none.

Footnotes

1 Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 11.

2 Ibid. See also Zarakol Reference Zarakol2017, 48. Gellwitzki and Houde (Reference Gellwitzki and Houde2023) do go beyond this level to ask how the European Union acts as an ontological security provider.

3 Steele (Reference Steele2025) has started to build the bridge between these approaches. See also Williams (Reference Williams2015, Reference Buzan17) on a link between psychoanalytical accounts of being human and ‘the kinds of patterns of behaviour that result in a pluralist international society.’

4 Bull Reference Bull1977, 4

10 Hurrell Reference Hurrell2007.

11 Falkner Reference Falkner2021.

12 Browning, Steele, and Joenniemi Reference Browning, Steele and Joenniemi2021.

13 Adler-Nissen and Zarakol Reference Adler-Nissen and Zarakol2021, 614.

14 I see the subject (and refer to ‘it’) as being separate from the ‘self,’ which can be multiple and changeable. Separating these words helps capture the way OSS has multiple views on the way the individual or collective subject (re)constitutes its ‘self.’

15 Buzan Reference Buzan2001; Reference Buzan2004. There are overlaps here with Wendt’s (Reference Wendt1999) Hobbesian, Lockean, and Kantian cultures.

16 The term ‘international society’ implies a focus on the ‘nation’ as the collective subject. In practice, international society is constituted by ‘states’ that may or may not be constituted by a specific nationality, ethnicity, or language group. To avoid confusion, I use the term ‘collective’ to refer to a subject, which could include, for example, a ‘people’ or ‘nation.’ I use ‘international society’ to refer to the object that may or may not provide that subject with ontological security by socially and legally recognising or misrecognising its self-conception.

17 There is a large literature on ES pluralism and solidarism (e.g., Buzan Reference Buzan2014; Linklater and Suganami Reference Linklater and Suganami2006; Weinert Reference Weinert2011; Wheeler Reference Wheeler2000; Williams Reference Williams2015).

18 Adler-Nissen and Zarakol Reference Adler-Nissen and Zarakol2021. On the rise of the ‘New’ or ‘populist’ Right, see Browning and Joenniemi Reference Browning and Joenniemi2017; Drolet and Williams Reference Drolet and Williams2018; Kinnvall Reference Kinnvall2018; Kinnvall and Svensson Reference Kinnvall and Svensson2022; Mandelbaum Reference Mandelbaum2020.

20 Dunne Reference Dunne1998, 136–60; Ralph Reference Ralph2007, 16.

21 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 88, 121, 126; Reference Honneth2007a, 224–7; Honneth Reference Honneth2007b, 129–33.

22 See Weinert Reference Weinert2011, 39 on how a ‘thin–thick’ typology helps ES better differentiate ‘the types and depths of normative commitments states are willing to make.’ See also Wheeler and Dunne Reference Wheeler and Dunne1996, 98, who equate ‘thin’ solidarism with ‘interstate law enforcement,’ and ‘thick’ solidarism with ‘a community of humankind.’

24 Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 240.

25 Giddens Reference Giddens1991.

26 Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 240.

27 Steele Reference Steele2008, 3.

29 Lynch Reference Lynch2008, 210, quoting Lacan Reference Lacan and Sheridan1948 [1977] and 1949 [1977].

30 Lynch Reference Lynch2008, 210.

31 Vieira Reference Vieira2018, 150–1.

33 Lacan Reference Lacan2016, 38–54; Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1999, 28–9; 52–3; 68–9.

34 Žižek Reference Žižek1997, 14.

35 Zevnik Reference Zevnik2021, 1052.

36 Epstein Reference Epstein2018, 824.

37 Lacan Reference Lacan2016, 42; Mandelbaum Reference Mandelbaum2020, 459.

38 Lacan Reference Lacan1992, 190–203. Mandelbaum Reference Mandelbaum2020, 454 translates ‘jouissance’ as the ‘powerful, bodily enjoyment that drives human desire’ (quoting Ruitenberg).

39 Mandelbaum Reference Mandelbaum2020, 469.

40 Eberle Reference Eberle2019, 247; Bilgic and Pilcher Reference Bilgic and Pilcher2023; Ermihan Reference Ermihan2024.

41 Lacan Reference Lacan1966/7, 275; Paipais Reference Paipais2016, 19.

42 Solomon Reference Solomon2015, 49.

43 Paipais Reference Paipais2016, 20.

44 Eberle Reference Eberle2019, 252. See also Epstein Reference Epstein2018, 824 on what is known as ‘traversing the fantasy’: the ‘necessarily lengthy, lifelong process that involves … deconstructing one’s foundational fantasy and revealing it for what it is, a phantasmatic construct that regulates one’s life.’

45 Rumelili Reference Rumelili2021, 1027; also Browning Reference Browning, Nyman and Burke2016, Browning and Joenniemi Reference Browning and Joenniemi2017, 44–5; Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 246; Kinnvall and Svensson Reference Kinnvall and Svensson2023, 4; Cash Reference Cash2022, 131; Zevnik Reference Zevnik2021; Zevnik and Mandelbaum Reference Zevnik and Mandelbaum2023, 2.

46 See also, Steele Reference Steele2025, 217–8 on the emphasis on agency in wider OSS research.

47 Lacan Reference Lacan1966/7, 14; Lacan Reference Lacan2016, 31.

48 Cash (Reference Cash2020, 312) makes a similar point when he stresses the importance of the ‘qualitative characteristics of the culturally organized role-identities, discourses, and practices’ that are available in ‘cultural repertoires.’ See also Steele Reference Steele2025, 214, when he encourages ‘scholars to think longer term about order as a principle that might be viewed as something other than just a value of exclusion, oppression, domination, and/or one reinforcing prejudiced power structures.’

50 Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1997, 85.

51 Lacan Reference Lacan1992, 89.

52 Ibid., 241–88.

53 Ibid., 282.

54 See Karp Reference Karp2025, who notes how Hegel read Antigone as ‘a tragic conflict between two sources of obligation that become irreconcilable in the world of action: the family and the polis.’

55 Lacan Reference Lacan1992, 259.

56 Lacan Reference Lacan1992, 17–34; Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1997, 86; Reference Stavrakakis1999, 68–74.

57 Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1999, 90.

58 Žižek Reference Žižek1991, quoted in Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1997, 87; Reference Lacan1992, 17–34, 96, 130–1.

59 Untalan Reference Untalan2020, 44, who adds: ‘[t]he consideration for the Other [in OS] is limited to how the Other threatens or satisfies the Self.’

60 Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1999, 111.

61 Steele Reference Steele2025, 220.

63 Stavrakakis Reference Stavrakakis1999, 131.

64 Ibid., 112; see also Mouffe Reference Mouffe1999, 752.

65The Anarchical Society can … be seen as an approach to understanding the contemporary international system – a system in which economic interdependence is compelling, where the network of common rules and institutions is dense … It is also a world in which the states remain the central actors, and where the diversity of cultures (even if it is not seen as leading to a ‘war of civilisations’) puts into question the solidity of international society and often challenges its rules.’ Hurrell Reference Hurrell2012, xxxii.

66 Note again the link to the IR constructivism of Wendt Reference Wendt1999.

67 Mouffe Reference Mouffe1999, 755.

69 Bull Reference Bull1977, 97–121.

70 Article 1 (2) states that a purpose of the United Nations is ‘to develop friendly relations among nations based on respect for the principle of equal rights and self-determination of peoples.’ Emphasis added.

71 ‘[T]o be a sovereign state is to provide citizens with a cognitive and emotional framework on the basis of which they can answer existential questions.’ Krickel-Choi Reference Krickel-Choi, Černy and Grzybowski2023, 72. On sovereignty as a fantasy that functions ‘as a compensatory structure by which international actors – states, but also “wannabe” states – chase after an imaginary “wholeness” projected onto an idealised past,’ see Epstein Reference Epstein2018, 825. See also Gallagher Reference Gallagher2018 in the same special issue.

72 I interpret the U.S. ‘sovereigntist’ opposition to the International Criminal Court in these terms, demonstrating how U.S. narratives appealed to pluralist conceptions of international society to protect self-understandings of American ‘exceptionalism’ and ‘exemptionalism’ (Ralph Reference Ralph2007).

73 The differences between Klein and Lacan and their implications for IR are now being articulated in OSS. See Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 10, who writes that ‘Kleinian and Lacanian theories are “mirror opposites in their premises about the nature of self.’” On Klein and OS, see also Cash Reference Cash2017, Reference Cash2020, Reference Cash2022; Gallagher Reference Gallagher2018; Gellwitzki and Houde Reference Gellwitzki and Houde2023; Houde Reference Houde2024.

74 Klein Reference Klein1950, 282–338.

76 Cash Reference Cash2020, 312. See also Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 5–6, 15–22.

77 Gellwitzki and Houde Reference Gellwitzki and Houde2023, 439. See also Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 15–22.

79 Cash Reference Cash2020, 312; see also Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 5.

80 Cash Reference Cash2020, 311.

81 Ibid., 317.

82 Cash Reference Cash2020, 309, emphasis added; see also Cash Reference Cash2017.

83 See, e.g., Greve Reference Greve2018.

84 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 97–105; Reference Honneth2014, 208–12.

86 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 97–105.

87 Ibid., 104.

88 Ibid., 105.

90 Browning and Joenniemi Reference Browning and Joenniemi2017, 43, drawing on the work of Berenskötter Reference Berenskötter, Koschut and Oelsner2014.

91 Anderson Reference Anderson and Honneth1995, xiv. This does not mean that those (national) subjects denied (international) recognition (e.g., Palestinians) can have no self-respect; indeed, they often find self-respect in the struggle for recognition. However, it does mean ‘that the fullest form of self-respecting autonomous agency’ can only ‘be realized when one is recognized as possessing the capacities of “legal persons,”’ i.e., sovereign statehood. Anderson Reference Anderson and Honneth1995, xv.

93 Honneth Reference Honneth2014, 149; Honneth Reference Honneth, Ringmar and Lindemann2016, 35. Zarakol makes a similar point. States ‘rely on recognition from other states for their sovereign existence, which implies that there is a shared understanding about what a modern “state” is. There are criteria for recognition as a state … [and] … the Standard of Civilization, the distinctions between modernity and barbarism, the obsession with development, etc., are all examples of shared normative ground between the established and the out siders of the international system.’ See Zarakol Reference Zarakol2010, 21; see also Zarakol Reference Zarakol2018. See also Heins Reference Heins2010, 166 and Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, 114–5, 122–4 on the distinction between legal recognition and the politics of underlying normative and classificatory schemes.

94 Honneth Reference Honneth2014, 149–50.

95 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 88, 121, 126; Reference Honneth2007a 224–7, Reference Honneth2007b, 129–33.

96 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 87, 111–3; Reference Honneth2014, 204–8.

97 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 87.

98 On this as a ‘thick’ form of recognition, see Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, 118; Gustafsson Reference Gustafsson2016a, 617, Reference Gustafsson2016b; Strömbom Reference Strömbom2014; Wendt Reference Wendt2003, 511–2. See also Zarakol Reference Zarakol2018, 850, who draws the distinction between a thin sense of ‘legal’ and a ‘thicker’ sense of ‘existential’ recognition.

99 As Greve Reference Greve2018, 858 puts it, ‘security communities need not only to reinforce a sense of ‘we-ness’ but also to recognise members’ distinctiveness. Denying this recognition threatens the self, undermining trust and eroding “we-ness”.’

100 Starting with Vincent Reference Vincent1986.

101 Kempster Reference Kempster1991.

102 Mearsheimer Reference Mearsheimer2022.

103 Honneth seemingly anticipated the difficulties of liberal solidarism when he referred to ‘Western nations’ delusions of omnipotence.’ Honneth Reference Honneth2007c, 212.

104 Sakwa Reference Sakwa2023. See also Akchurina and Della Sala Reference Akchurina, Della Sala, Akchurina and Sala2022; Hansen Reference Hansen and Götz2018; Kazharski Reference Kazharski2020, 25; Zarakol Reference Zarakol2010, 225–9; 236–7. Pouliot recalls how, during the period of NATO-Russia cooperation, Western practitioners saw themselves as the ‘teachers’ of Russian diplomats, who were represented as ‘irrational and emotional.’ Pouliot Reference Pouliot2010, 143. Predictably, Russian diplomats ‘despised’ NATO’s ‘self-attributed role as a teacher,’ and this experience contributed to a resurgence of the ‘great power’ habitus. Ibid., 144.

105 Cash Reference Cash2020.

106 Gellwitzki and Houde Reference Gellwitzki and Houde2023. See also Gellwitzki Reference Gellwitzki2025, 15–22.

107 Such an argument resonates with Gellwitzki’s (Reference Gellwitzki2025, 26) Kleinian-inspired analysis, which values the construction of states ‘in ambivalent terms rather than as enemies. In the case of Russia, we may want to focus on actors who articulate an ambivalent self, as well as guilt, possibly shame, and promote debates about reparations (real or mock) to compensate for (some of) the inflicted harm.’

108 On lack of reckoning with Russia’s imperial past and how that enabled the invasion of Ukraine, which may yet prove to be a decolonizing moment, see Mälksoo Reference Mälksoo2023. Of course, a full reckoning on one state’s imperial past is made more difficult if other states in international society are unwilling to recognise their own harms, or indeed celebrate the imperial great power identity.

109 Steele Reference Steele2025, 221, for an emphasis on the plurality of possible orders.

110 Steele Reference Steele2025.

111 Honneth Reference Honneth2004.

112 Subotic and Steele Reference Subotic and Steele2018.

References

Adler-Nissen, Rebecca, and Zarakol, Ayşe. 2021. “Struggles for Recognition: The Liberal International Order and the Merger of Its Discontents.” International Organization 75 (2): 611–34.10.1017/S0020818320000454CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akchurina, Viktoria, and Della Sala, Vincent. 2022. “Russia, Europe and the Ontological Security Dilemma: Narrating the Emerging Eurasian Space.” In The European Union, Russia and the Post-Soviet Space, edited by Akchurina, Viktoria and Sala, Vincent Della, 96113. Abingdon: Routledge.10.4324/9781003081722-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Joel. 1995. “Translator’s Introduction.” In The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, edited by Honneth, Axel, xxxi. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bartelson, Jens. 2013. “Three Concepts of Recognition.” International Theory 5 (1): 107–29.10.1017/S175297191300002XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berenskötter, Felix. 2014. “Friendship, Security, and Power.” In Friendship and International Relations, edited by Koschut, Simon and Oelsner, Andrea, 5171. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Berenskötter, Felix. 2020. “Anxiety, Time, and Agency.” International Theory 12 (2): 273–90.10.1017/S1752971920000111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bilgic, Ali, and Pilcher, Jordan. 2023. “Desires, Fantasies and Hierarchies: Postcolonial Status Anxiety Through Ontological Security.” Alternatives 48 (1): 319.10.1177/03043754221086170CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spillius, Bott, Elizabeth, Jane Milton, Garvey, Penelope, Couve, Cyril, and Steiner, Deborah. 2011. The New Dictionary of Kleinian Thought. Hove, East Sussex: Routledge.10.4324/9780203815762CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S. 2016. “Ethics and Ontological Security.” In Ethical Security Studies: A New Research Agenda, edited by Nyman, Jonna and Burke, Anthony, 160–73. Abingdon: Routledge.10.4324/9781315692005-12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S., and Joenniemi, Pertti. 2017. “Ontological Security, Self-Articulation and the Securitization of Identity.” Cooperation and Conflict 52 (1): 3147.10.1177/0010836716653161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Browning, Christopher S., Steele, Brent J., and Joenniemi, Pertti. 2021. Vicarious Identity in International Relations: Self, Security, and Status on the Global Stage. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oso/9780197526385.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, 2nd ed. Basingstoke: Macmillan.10.1007/978-1-349-24028-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. Peter. 2017. “The Real at the Origin of Sovereignty.” Political Psychology 38 (4): 653–68.10.1111/pops.12422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buzan, Barry. 2001. “The English School: An Underexploited Resource in IR.” Review of International Studies 27 (3): 471–52.10.1017/S0260210501004715CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buzan, Barry. 2004. From International to World Society? English School Theory and the Social Structures of Globalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buzan, Barry. 2014. An Introduction to the English School of International Relations: The Societal Approach. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Cash, John. 2017. “The Dilemmas of Ontological Insecurity in a Postcolonising Northern Ireland.” Postcolonial Studies 20 (3): 387410.10.1080/13688790.2017.1391671CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cash, John. 2020. “Psychoanalysis, Cultures of Anarchy, and Ontological Insecurity.” International Theory 12 (2): 306–21.10.1017/S1752971920000147CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cash, John. 2022. “Anxiety, Ambivalence and Sublimation: Ontological In/Security and the World Risk Society.” Uluslararasi Iliskiler/International Relations 19 (73): 129–45.Google Scholar
Drolet, Jean-François, and Williams, Michael C.. 2018. “Radical Conservatism and Global Order: International Theory and the New Right.” International Theory 10 (3): 285313.10.1017/S175297191800012XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunne, Tim. 1998. Inventing International Society: A History of the English School. Houndmills: Macmillan.10.1057/9780230376137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eberle, Jakub. 2019. “Narrative, Desire, Ontological Security, Transgression: Fantasy as a Factor in International Politics.” Journal of International Relations and Development 22: 243–68.10.1057/s41268-017-0104-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Charlotte. 2018. “The Productive Force of the Negative and the Desire for Recognition: Lessons From Hegel and Lacan.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 805–28.10.1017/S0260210518000347CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ermihan, Erman. 2024. “End of Jouissance, Start of Resentment: A Lacanian Critical Security Approach to Turkey’s Relations with the West.” Critical Studies on Security. Online First: 119. https://doi.org/10.1080/21624887.2024.2312317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkner, Robert. 2021. Environmentalism and Global International Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/9781108966696CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallagher, Adrian. 2013. Genocide and Its Threat to Contemporary International Order. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1057/9781137280268CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallagher, Julia. 2018. “Misrecognition in the Making of a State: Ghana’s International Relations Under Kwame Nkrumah.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 882901.10.1017/S0260210518000335CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gellwitzki, Nicolai C. 2025. “The Positions of Ontological (In)Security in International Relations: Object Relations, Unconscious Phantasies, and Anxiety Management.” International Theory 17 (1): 118–50.10.1017/S1752971924000125CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gellwitzki, Nicolai C., and Houde, Anne-Marie. 2023. “Narratives, Ontological Security, and Unconscious Phantasy: Germany and the European Myth During the So-Called Migration Crisis.” Political Psychology 44 (2): 435–51.10.1111/pops.12869CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 1991. Modernity and Self-Identity: Self and Society in the Late Modern Age. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
Greve, Patricia. 2018. “Ontological Security, the Struggle for Recognition, and the Maintenance of Security Communities.” Journal of International Relations and Development 21 (4): 858–82.10.1057/s41268-017-0108-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Karl. 2016a. “Routinised Recognition and Anxiety: Understanding the Deterioration in Sino–Japanese Relations.” Review of International Studies 42 (4) 613–33.10.1017/S0260210515000546CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Karl. 2016b. “Recognising Recognition Through Thick and Thin: Insights from Sino–Japanese Relations.” Cooperation and Conflict 51 (3): 255–71.10.1177/0010836715610594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, Karl, and Krickel-Choi, Nina C.. 2020. “Returning to the Roots of Ontological Security: Insights from the Existentalist Literature.” European Journal of International Relations 26 (3): 875–95.10.1177/1354066120927073CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, Flemming Splidsboel. 2018. “Russia’s Relations with the West: Ontological Security Through Conflict.” In Russia, the West, and the Ukraine Crisis, edited by Götz, Elias, 111–27. Abingdon: Routledge.10.4324/9781315175225-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heins, Volker. 2010. “Of Persons and Peoples: Internationalizing the Critical Theory of Recognition.” Contemporary Political Theory 9 (2): 149–70.10.1057/cpt.2008.48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition. The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2004. “Recognition and Justice: Outline of a Plural Theory of Justice.” Acta Sociologica 47 (4): 351–64.10.1177/0001699304048668CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2007a. Democracy as Reflexive Cooperation: John Dewey and the Theory of Democracy Today.” In Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory, 763–83. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2007b. Between Aristotle and Kant: Recognition and Moral Obligation.” In Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory, 129–43. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2007c. Is Universalism a Moral Trap? The Presuppositions and Limits of a Politics of Human Rights.” In Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory, 197217. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2014. The I in We: Studies in the Theory of Recognition. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2016. “Recognition Between States: On the Moral Substrate of International Relations.” In The International Politics of Recognition, edited by Ringmar, Erik and Lindemann, Thomas, 2538. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers.Google Scholar
Houde, Anne-Marie. 2024. “Navigating Anxiety: International Politics, Identity Narratives, and Everyday Defense Mechanisms.” International Political Sociology 18 (1): 119.10.1093/ips/olad028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurrell, Andrew. 2007. On Global Order: Power, Values, and the Constitution of International Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199233106.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurrell, Andrew. 2012. “Forward to the Fourth Edition of Hedley Bull.” In The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, viixxvii. London: Red Globe Press.Google Scholar
Karp, David Jason. 2025. “A Post-Hegelian Theory of Human Rights: Beyond Recognition and the State.” European Journal of International Relations 31 (1): 77100.10.1177/13540661241271029CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kazharski, Aliaksei. 2020. “Civilizations as Ontological Security? Stories of the Russian Trauma.” Problems of Post-Communism 67 (1): 2436.10.1080/10758216.2019.1591925CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kempster, Norman. 1991. “Secretary of State Baker Proposes New Partnership for East, West.” Los Angeles Times, 19 June. Available at https://www.latimes.com/archives/la-xpm-1991–06–19-mn-938-story.html. Accessed 18 August 2025.Google Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina. 2018. “Ontological Insecurities and Postcolonial Imaginaries: The Emotional Appeal of Populism.” Humanity & Society 42 (4): 523–43.10.1177/0160597618802646CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Mitzen, Jennifer. 2020. “Anxiety, Fear, and Ontological Security in World Politics: Thinking With and Beyond Giddens.” International Theory 12 (2): 240–56.10.1017/S175297192000010XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Svensson, Ted. 2022. “Exploring the Populist ‘Mind’: Anxiety, Fantasy, and Everyday Populism.” British Journal of Politics & International Relations 24 (3): 526–42.10.1177/13691481221075925CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Svensson, Ted. 2023. “Trauma, Home, and Geopolitical Bordering: A Lacanian Approach to the COVID-19 Crisis.” International Studies Quarterly 67 (3): 111.10.1093/isq/sqad053CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, Melanie. 1950. Contributions to Psycho-Analysis, 1921–45. London: Hogarth Press.Google Scholar
Krickel-Choi, Nina. 2023. “Ontological Security and the Emotional Significance of Sovereignty.” In Variations on Sovereignty: Contestations and Transformations from Around the World, edited by Černy, Hannes and Grzybowski, Janis, 6886. Abingdon: Routledge.10.4324/9781003287506-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacan, Jacques 1948 [1977]. “Aggressivity in Psychoanalysis.” In Écrits: A Selection. Translated by Sheridan, Alan, 932. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Lacan, Jacques. 1949 [1977]. “The Mirror Stage as Formative of the Function of the I as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience.” In Écrits: A Selection. Translated by Sheridan, Alan, 18. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Lacan, Jacques. 1966/7. The Logic of Phantasy. Available at http://www.lacaninireland.com/web/wp-content/uploads/2010/06/14-Logic-of-Phantasy-Complete.pdf. Accessed 18 August 2025.Google Scholar
Lacan, Jacques. 1992. The Ethics of Psychoanalysis, 1959–60. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Lacan, Jacques. 2016. Anxiety. London: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Laing, R. D. 1990. The Divided Self: An Existential Study in Sanity and Madness. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Linklater, Andrew, and Suganami, Hidemi. 2006. The English School of International Relations: A Contemporary Reassessment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511491528CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lynch, Richard A. 2008. “The Alienating Mirror: Toward a Hegelian Critique of Lacan on Ego-Formation.” Human Studies 31 (2): 209–21.10.1007/s10746-008-9083-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mälksoo, Maria. 2023. “The Postcolonial Moment in Russia’s War Against Ukraine.” Journal of Genocide Research 25 (3–4): 471–81.10.1080/14623528.2022.2074947CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, Moran. 2020. “‘Making Our Country Great Again’: The Politics of Subjectivity in an Age of National-Populism.” International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 33 (2): 451–76.10.1007/s11196-020-09717-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mearsheimer, John J. 2022. “The Causes and Consequences of the Ukraine War.” Horizons: Journal of International Relations and Sustainable Development 21: 1227.Google Scholar
Mitzen, Jennifer. 2006. “Ontological Security in World Politics: State Identity and the Security Dilemma.” European Journal of International Relations 12 (3): 341–70.10.1177/1354066106067346CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitzen, Jennifer. 2018. “Feeling at Home in Europe: Migration, Ontological Security, and the Political Psychology of EU Bordering.” Political Psychology 39 (6): 1373–87.10.1111/pops.12553CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mouffe, Chantal. 1999. “Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism?Social Research 66 (3): 745–58.Google Scholar
Mouffe, Chantal. 2007. “Carl Schmitt’s Warning on the Dangers of a Unipolar World.” In The International Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal War and the Crisis of Global Order, edited by Odysseos, Louiza and Petito, Fabio, 147–53. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Paipais, Vassilios. 2016. Political Ontology and International Political Thought: Voiding a Pluralist World. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Pouliot, Vincent. 2010. International Security in Practice: The Politics of NATO-Russia Diplomacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511676185CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ralph, Jason. 2007. Defending the Society of States: Why America Opposes the International Criminal Court and Its Vision of World Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199214310.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ralph, Jason. 2024. “Securing the Self, Embracing Anxiety, or Nurturing Growth? How the Pragmatism of Dewey, James, and Mead Speaks to Ontological Security Studies.” Global Studies Quarterly 4 (2): ksae032. https://doi.org/10.1093/isagsq/ksae032.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ralph, Jason. 2025. “American Pragmatism, the Frankfurt School and the future of Critical International Relations Theory.” Review of International Studies. Online First: 120. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210525101174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rumelili, Bahar. 2021. “[Our] Age of Anxiety: Existentialism and the Current State of International Relations.” Journal of International Relations and Development 24: 1020–36.10.1057/s41268-021-00226-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sakwa, Richard. 2023. The Lost Peace: How the West Failed to Prevent a Second Cold War. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, Ty. 2015. The Politics of Subjectivity in American Foreign Policy Discourses. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.10.3998/mpub.5031921CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stavrakakis, Yannis. 1997. “Ambiguous Democracy and the Ethics of Psychoanalysis.” Philosophy & Social Criticism 23 (2): 7996.10.1177/019145379702300204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stavrakakis, Yannis. 1999. Lacan and the Political. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Steele, Brent J. 2008. Ontological Security in International Relations: Self-Identity and the IR State. London: Routledge.10.4324/9780203018200CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent J. 2019. “Welcome Home! Routines, Ontological Insecurity and the Politics of US Military Reunion Videos.” Cambridge Review of International Affairs 32 (3): 322–43.10.1080/09557571.2018.1564899CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent J. 2025. “Order and Justice in Ontological Security Studies.” Cooperation and Conflict 60 (2): 213–36.10.1177/00108367241288080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strömbom, Lisa. 2014. “Thick Recognition: Advancing Theory on Identity Change in Intractable Conflicts.” European Journal of International Relations 20 (1): 168–91.10.1177/1354066112439217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Subotic, Jelena, and Steele, Brent J.. 2018. “Moral Injury in International Relations.” Journal of Global Security Studies 3 (4): 387401.10.1093/jogss/ogy021CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Untalan, Carmina Yu. 2020. “Decentering the Self, Seeing Like the Other: Toward a Postcolonial Approach to Ontological Security.” International Political Sociology 14 (1): 4056.Google Scholar
Vieira, Marco A. 2018. “(Re-)imagining the ‘Self’ of Ontological Security: The Case of Brazil’s Ambivalent Postcolonial Subjectivity.” Millennium 46 (2): 142–64.10.1177/0305829817741255CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vincent, John. 1986. Human Rights and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Weinert, Matthew. 2011. “Reframing the Pluralist–Solidarist Debate.” Millennium 40 (1): 2141.10.1177/0305829811406036CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511612183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2003. “Why a World State Is Inevitable.” European Journal of International Relations 9 (4): 491542.10.1177/135406610394001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheeler, Nicholas J. 2000. Saving Strangers : Humanitarian Intervention in International Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Nicholas J., and Dunne, Tim. 1996. “Hedley Bull’s Pluralism of the Intellect and Solidarism of the Will.” International Affairs 72 (1): 91107.10.2307/2624751CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, John. 2015. Ethics, Diversity and World Politics. Saving Pluralism from Itself. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198733621.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2010. After Defeat: How the East Learned to Live with the West. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511921421CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2017. “States and Ontological Security: A Historical Rethinking.” Cooperation and Conflict 52 (1): 4868.10.1177/0010836716653158CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2018. “Sovereign Equality as Misrecognition.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 848–62.10.1017/S0260210518000359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zevnik, Andreja. 2021. “Anxiety, Subjectivity and the Possibility of Emancipatory Politics.” Journal of International Relations and Development 24 (4): 1050–6.10.1057/s41268-021-00221-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zevnik, Andreja, and Mandelbaum, Moran M.. 2023. “Introduction to Special Issue: Interrogating the Void: Lacanian Psychoanalysis in International Relations.” International Studies Quarterly 67 (3): 13.10.1093/isq/sqad062CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Žižek, Slavoj. 1991. For They Know Not What They Do. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Žižek, Slavoj. 1997. The Plague of Fantasies. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. International society as an ontological security provider